Skip to main content

Full text of "The Social Teaching Of The Christian Churches Vol-ii"

See other formats




HALLEY STEWART PUBLICATIONS I 


THE SOCIAL TEACHING 
OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 




Halley Stewart Publications I 


THE SOCIAL TEACHING 

OF THE 

CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

by 

ERNST TROELTSGH 


TRANSLATED BY 

OLIVE WYON 


VOLUME TWO 


LONDON: GEORGE ALLEN & UNWIN LTD 
NEW YORK: THE MACMILLAN COMPANY 



FIRST PUBLISHED IN ENGLISH IN I931 


All rights reserved 

PRINTED IN GREAT BRITAIN BY 
UNWIN BROTHERS LTD., WOKJNG 



DEDICATED 

IN DEEPEST GRATITUDE AND RESPECT 
TO 

THE EMINENT PHILOSOPHICAL FACULTY 
AT GREIFSWALD 

AND 

TO THE EMINENT LAW FACULTY 
AT BRESLAU 




CONTENTS OF VOLUME TWO 


CHAPTER III 

PROTESTANTISM 

1. The Sociological Problem of Protestantism^- 

Protestantism as a new type of the sociological development of 
Christian thought 

Point of departure; originality of Luther; relation to class move- 
ments of the period 

Luther’s religious thought 
Sociological consequences of these ideas 

The new conception of the Church 477- 

Conclusions drawn from this Conception: 

(i) The absolute conception of Truth 

(ii) The ministry of the Word as the means of organization 

(iii) The Territorial Church system and the compulsory 

supremacy of the Church 

The Ethic of Compromise corresponding to the Church conception 

The peculiar character of the Protestant ecclesiastical ethic: the 
central position of the Decalogue; the dualism of a “personal” 
and “official” morality 

Retrospect and Forecast 

2. Lutheranism 

Church conception and the ecclesiastical organization of 
Lutheranism 

Unifying influence of the State Church conception upon Christian 
Society 

The Lutheran ethic 

The Lutheran conception of Natural Law 

The Sociological Fundamental Theory of Lutheranism 

The Family 

The State 

Economic theory 

The organization of Society and the “Callings” # \ 

Social Policy, Social Reform, and Philanthropy J 

Connection between Lutheranism and the general cultural situation 
in Germany and reflex action upon the latter 

Significance of Lutheranism for the political and social situation 
in Germany 


PAGE 


461 

4^5 

467 

477 

■494 


494 

501 

5H 


5i5 

52i 

523 

528 

540 

544 

547 

554 

561 

569 

575 



456 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

PAGE 

3. Calvinism 

Calvinism surpasses Lutheranism. Distinction between primitive 
Calvinism and Neo- Calvinism. Original development of Calvin- 
ism out of Lutheranism 576 

Special Religious and Ethical Characteristics of Primitive Calvinism: 579 

(i) Doctrine of Predestination 581 

(ii) Calvinistic Individualism 587 

(iii) The Holy Community and Resemblances to the Anabaptists 590 

(iv) The Calvinist Ethic. Asceticism. The idea of the “calling”. 

The Natural Law of morals 602 

(v) The Sociological Fundamental Theory. Equality and In- 

equality. Christian Socialism 617 

The Influence of the Cultural Situation in Geneva upon Primitive Calvinism 625 

(i) The democratic-constitutional characteristics of Calvinism. 

Conditions in Geneva. Beza’s doctrine of the State. The 
Huguenot anti-monarchist doctrine of the State. The Scot- 
tish doctrine of the State. Cromwell. Althusius. Grotius. 
Locke. Hobbes. Pufendorf 628 

(ii) The capitalistic element in the economic ethic of Calvinism. 

Calvinism and Capitalism. Capitalism restricted by Christian 
requirements. Calvinism reconciled to the modern economic- 
order 641 

(iii) Political Internationalism of Calvinism. The Problem of War. 

The Policy of Intervention 650 

Social Doctrines peculiar to Calvinism: 652 

Conception of the Church, of Society, and of the Family 

The Transition to Neo-Calvinism in the development of the Free 
Churches and of Pietism as the result of applying the standards 
of the Holy Community to great civilized nations 656 

The Free Churches 

(i) The Brownists and Barrowists 661 

(ii) Congregationalism 663 

(iii) Independency in England 666 

(iv) Penetration of the Free Church principle into genuine 

Calvinism 670 

(v) Religious Toleration 671 

(vi) Natural Law and Liberal character of Free Church Neo- 

Calvinism 673 



CONTENTS 


457 


PAGE 

Puritanism and Pietism 677 

(i) Puritanism in England 678 

(ii) “Precisianism” in the Netherlands 682 

(iii) Pietism on the Lower Rhine and in Switzerland 686 

The Ethic of Neo-Calvinism and its fusion with the ethic of the 
bourgeois sect-type. The rise of the collective group of Ascetic 
Protestantism as the result of this fusion 688 

The Sect-type and Mysticism within Protestantism 

The complementary movement of the sects and of mysticism 
alongside of the Protestant Territorial Church system, and the 
original inclusion of both these elements in the Reformation 
world of thought 691 

The Baptist Movement and the Protestant Sects 694 

(i) Connection between the Baptist movement and the Reformers 694 

(ii) Development of the sect-motive within the organized Baptist 

movement as an independent element. General charac- 
teristics of the Baptist movement 695 

(iii) Origin of the Baptist movement 696 

(iv) Difference in the position accorded to the sect-idea by 

Catholicism and by Protestantism 700 

(v) Baptists at Zurich and first extension of the movement 703 

(vi) Mennonites 705 

(vii) English Baptists and the rise of the General Baptists 706 

(viii) The radical Baptists and the English Revolution 710 

(ix) The Levellers 710 

(x) The Diggers 7 1 1 

(xi) The Millennarians 712 

(xii) Pietism 714 

(xiii) The Moravians 719 

(xiv) The Methodists 72 1 

(xv) The Labadists 724 

(xvi) Modern sects 725 

(xvii) Christian Socialism 726 

(xviii) Tolstoi 728 

Mysticism and Spiritual Idealism 729 

(i) The religious nature of Mysticism in general 730 

(ii) Mysticism in the New Testament 732 



458 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

PAGE 

(iii) Mysticism based on religious philosophy 734 

(iv) “Spiritual Religion” ( Spiritualismus ) 738 

(v) Protestant “Spiritual Religion” 740 

(vi) Difference between this “Spiritual Religion” and the Baptist 

movement 742 

(vii) Sociological character of “Spiritual Religion” 745 

(viii) Effects of Dogma 746 

(ix) The ethic of “Spiritual Religion” 752 

(x) Thomas Miinzer 754 

(xi) Karlstadt 755 

(xii) Schwenkfeld 756 

(xiii) Sebastian Franck 760 

(xiv) Castellio 762 

(xv) Coornheert 764 

(xvi) The Collegiants 766 

(xvii) “Spiritual” Theologians among the Baptists 767 

(xviii) Natural Philosophers 769 

(xix) David Joris 770 

(xx) Hendrik Niclaes 772 

(xxi) Labadie 773 

(xxii) Mysticism in the Netherlands in the seventeenth century 773 
(xxiii) Mysticism in England in the seventeenth century 776 

(xxiv) The Quakers 780 

(xxv) Methodism and Pietism 784 

(xxvi) The Moravian Church 788 

(xxvii) The modern religious philosophy of Idealism 791 

(xxviii) The Romantic Movement 793 

(xxix) Modern Theology 796 

(xxx) Sociological results of modern “Spiritual Religion” 797 

The social doctrines of Mysticism and of “Spiritual Religion” 800 

The social doctrines of the aggressive sect 802 

The non-aggressive sect and its fusion with Neo-Calvinism ; Ascetic 
Protestantism once more 805 

« 

The Sociological Fundamental Theory of Ascetic Protestantism 807 

(ii) The Sex Ethic 809 

(ii) The Political Ethic 810 

(iii) The Economic Ethic 812 



CONTENTS 


459 


PAGE 

The position of Ascetic Protestantism in the history of the Christian 
ethic 815 

Mutual influence of general civilization on the groups which have 
been described 8 1 6 

Significance of Ascetic Protestantism at the present day 818 

CONCLUSION 

Developments in Christian social doctrine since the eighteenth 
century 99 1 

Results: 

(i) The three chief types of the sociological development of the 

Christian idea 993 

(ii) Dogma and theology conditioned by sociological factors 994 

(iii) Conception of Truth and Religious Toleration 997 

(iv) History of the development of the Christian ethic 999 

(v) Significance of the Marxist method for Theology 1002 

(vi) The permanent ethical content of Christianity 1004 

(vii) The most suitable form of organization for Christian 

religious life at the present time 1006 

(viii) Christianity and the modern social problem 1010 




CHAPTER III 


PROTESTANTISM 

i. THE SOCIOLOGICAL PROBLEM OF PROTESTANTISM 

Protestantism: A New Sociological Type 

Mediaeval Christianity produced two great classic types of 
social doctrine: first, the relative type of the idea of Christian 
Society which is represented by Thomism; and, secondly, the 
radical idea of Christian Society which was evolved by the sects. 

The position of the first type may be stated thus : the Church, 
which is regarded as a universal institution, endowed with abso- 
lute authoritative truth and the sacramental miraculous power 
of grace and redemption, takes up into its own life the secular 
institutions, groups, and values which have arisen out of the 
relative Natural Law, and are adapted to the conditions of the 
fallen state ; the whole of the secular life, therefore, is summed up 
under the conception of a natural stage in human life, which 
prepares the way for the higher supernatural stage, for the ethic 
of grace and miracle, for the spiritual and hierarchical world- 
organization. 

The position of the second type may be thus summarized : the 
religious community has evolved its social ideal purely from the 
Gospel and from the Law of Christ; according to this type of 
thought the Christian character and holiness of this ideal should 
be proved by the unity reigning within the group and by the 
practical behaviour of the individual members, and not by 
objective institutional guarantees. Therefore, either it does not 
recognize the institutions, groups, and values which exist outside 
of Christianity at all, or in a quietly tolerant spirit of detach- 
ment from the world it avoids them, or under the influence of 
an “enthusiastic” eschatology it attacks these institutions and 
replaces them by a purely Christian order of society. 

In each instance the nature of the Christian fellowship itself is 
conceived from a different point of view ; in the first instance it is 
conceived as an institution, not dependent on individualism, 
possessing a depositum of absolute truths and wonderful,, civilizing 
sacramental powers; in the second instance it is conceived as 
a society whose life is constantly renewed by the deliberate 
allegiance and personal work of its individual members. This is 
the reason why the champions of the “Church” theory were able 
to discard the ideal of a strict Christian perfection, or at least to 



462 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Jijnit it to a particular group, that is, to monasticism; this also* 
explains why the supporters of the “sect” theory upheld the ideal 
of Christian perfection as binding on all Christians alike. 

Further, in both instances the Christian fundamental ideas of 
sin and grace are interpreted in a different sense. In the case of the 
Church-type, its doctrine of sin facilitated the acceptance of the 
existing secular social order, whose merely relative non-Christian 
character is regarded as the result of sin ; this social order, there- 
fore, must be frankly accepted and tolerated. At the same time 
“grace” is regarded as the miraculous power which purifies these 
institutions, uses them as the basis of a higher structure, and sub- 
ordinates them to a universal central authority. This authority is 
conceived in its essence as a wonderful supreme authority, 
transcending Nature, even pure and unfallen Nature; as super- 
nature it is superimposed upon Nature in the graded structure 
of the entelechies of the universe. 

In the case of the sect-type, the existing institutions, groups, and 
values of the secular life are equally explained by the fact of sin ; 
this, however, does not mean that they are inevitable, and must 
simply be accepted ; on the contrary, the supporters of this theory 
use this fact as an argument for the radical rejection by Christians 
of the secular life and all its works, and as a challenge to create 
a social order which is based purely upon the principles of the 
Gospel. According to this theory, grace means the “calling and 
election” which separates the Christian from the life of this present 
world, and inspires the pure gospel ethic with knowledge and 
power (an ethic which vindicates itself by its subjective influence 
and not by its institutional system) ; “grace” also means the hope 
that the Christian Church will be finally vindicated at the great 
reversal of all secular values in the Last Judgment. Grace is not a 
superstructure erected upon the basis of Nature — whether sinful 
or innocent — which has to be accepted, but it is identified with 
the complete, pure, ideal nature of the Primitive State. So far as 
fallen humanity is concerned, grace does not mean the purifica- 
tion of nature and the ascent to supernature, rather it means pure 
and radical hostility to the whole principle of sin, expressed in a 
genuine Christian spirit, and in the Christian moral law. 

This theory is connected with a whole series of further distinc- 
tions, which belong to the subtler realm of religious psychology 
and to theological thought. Christology, in particular, was 
obviously connected with the idea of the Church as a “fellowship” 
which prevailed at that time, in so far as the “Church” regarded 
Christ as the Founder of the Church and the Founder of the 



PROTESTANTISM 463 

objective treasury of grace and of salvation ; whereas the 
regarded Him as the Law-giver, the Divine example, the stimu- 
lating energy, the presence of the supra-historical Exalted Christ, 
the source of all immediate influence and activity. All this, 
however, really belongs to the history of doctrine. For our present 
subject it is vital to remember that the idea of the Church as an 
objective institution, and as a voluntary society, contains a funda- 
mental sociological distinction. This distinction leads to a corre- 
sponding distinction in the sphere of ethics : on the one hand, the 
Christian ethic is supplemented by the natural ethic, and is thus 
enabled to dominate the masses ; while on the other, this idea of 
nature as the “complement 9 5 of grace is rejected, and the influence 
of this group is therefore confined to small circles of passive 
resisters or revolutionaries. The Church-type accepted a natural 
ethic whose standards differ greatly from those of Christianity; 
the sect- type rejected this idea entirely. Those who regarded the 
Church as an objective institution looked upon “Nature” as 
something which, though different from grace, was yet capable of 
being moulded by it ; whereas those to whom the Church was a 
voluntary society regarded “genuine Nature” as something 
which was identical with grace, while they rejected “fallen 
Nature” altogether as something which could not possibly be 
harmonized with grace at all. 

This distinction can be traced right back to Primitive Christi- 
anity and the Early Church. We see it in embryo in the contrast 
between the love-communism of the local Church in Jerusalem 
and the conservative adjustment to the existing social order pro- 
claimed by Paul. The Church only reached her full development, 
however, when, in the days of Constantine, she became a State 
Church. Only then was it possible for her to realize her universal 
and absolute unity and supremacy, which, during the time of the 
Holy Roman Empire, then enabled her to subdue the State itself 
to the unity which had been gained with the help of the State; 
this meant that the Church was also able to assert her authority 
over the whole of the non-religious civilization as well. Since, 
however, it was only the Middle Ages which thus created a 
Christian unity of civilization, so also it was only the Middle 
Ages which produced definitely and clearly the complementary 
movement of the sect. At this point the social doctrines of Latin 
Christianity ceased to develop. Henceforth it became clear that 
Christian social doctrine could only produce further develop- 
ments if it were to receive a fresh infusion of new life. Only 
an inward change, and a further development within Christian 



464 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

thought itself, could pave the way for new ideals in the Christian 
doctrine of Society. 

It is well known that a new development of this kind did take 
place in the critical period of the later Middle Ages, and that 
with the rise of Protestantism it succeeded in coming out into the 
open at the Reformation. At the same time, in various directions, 
both positively and negatively, the Reformation was restricted by 
the forces which had already been developed during this crisis. 
More than two hundred years separated the Reformation from 
Thomism, which was the classic expression of the mediaeval spirit, 
meanwhile opposition of various kinds had developed, as well as 
development of the attempts at adaptation to its ideals. The spirit 
of opposition to Thomism was expressed, in the main, in three 
ways: (a) in the development of the sect-type, which had an 
increasing influence; ( b ) in mysticism, which fostered a radical 
religious individualism, preoccupied with the endeavour to free 
itself from the shackles of scholasticism and ecclesiasticism ; 
(c) in the critical self-destruction of the Thomist system in the late 
mediaeval theological school of thought, in Nominalism, or rather, 
to be more exact, in Occamism. Nominalism, in particular, had 
an important influence on the Reformation. This philosophy 
severed the connection between Reason and Revelation, destroyed 
the idea of an ascent from Nature to Supernature and the care- 
fully graded theory of the connatural and supernatural end for 
which humanity has been created. It intensified psychological 
self analysis by its appeal to experience and its emphasis on 
the doctrine that “the individual is the real” ; it also emphasized 
the positive nature of the Divine Will and altered the theory of the 
sacraments. According to Nominalism the sacraments do not 
convey a supernatural life, but they impart the righteousness which 
belongs to human nature by right, but which had been lost by sin. 
Otherwise, however, this school of thought still retained the funda- 
mental idea of the universal dominion of the Church — peculiar 
to Catholicism (in this particular it discarded the elements 
peculiar to Occam and the Conciliar theologians) — and the idea 
of the Christian unity of civilization ; the moral Law of Nature 
was still recognized, alongside of the positive Divine order, which 
was now c far more strongly emphasized. By means of treaties 
between the different States and the Church, the ancient 
ecclesiastical system was once more secured, both legally and 
doctrinally, but both in doctrine and in ethics much uncertainty 
remained, and under the surface a spirit of hostility towards the 
Church was widespread. The general effect of Nominalism was to 



PROTESTANTISM 


465 

dissolve the unity created by Thomism between dogma and philo- 
sophy, between a natural and a supernatural ethic, between Natural 
Law and the positive Divine decrees. This philosophy reflected the 
prevailing disharmony between the life of the Church and the life 
of the world; by laying increased emphasis upon the Divine 
authority, however, it maintained the old ecclesiastical idea of 
unity; in other directions it provided a safety-valve for reason 
and the natural powers in the dispositions for grace, in the co- 
operation of free-will. Luther himself was a product of this school 
of thought; Thomism was already a matter of ancient history. 
It was against it that Luther first directed his polemic; yet its 
way of formulating problems, its dualistic and authoritative habit 
of mind, its irrationalism towards philosophy, and its psychology 
of inner experience, also formed the primary positive assumptions 
of Luther’s most fundamental ideas. These ideas, however, are 
still going through a process of elucidation, and they do not 
belong to our subject. For us the main point of interest is the result 
of these ideas, and the new religious idea of the Reformation . 1973 
This, then, is our problem : in what did this change of Christian 
thought consist? What were the new religious ideas, and what 
were their sociological results? 

Although the forces which converged in the Reformation and 
in Protestantism were very varied, and although they gave rise 
to a rich development of movements and personalities, all this 
many-sided development was, in the last resort, based upon 
Luther’s fundamental principles. These principles were the 
absolute standard, doctrinally, for all these groups, even though 
later on many of them may have developed along very different 
lines. The Humanistic groups alone were independent of Luther, 
and for that reason also they speedily lost their significance, so 
far as he was concerned, at least for the next few centuries ; only on 
the scientific and scholastic side did they make a contribution to 
Protestantism, as well as to renewed Catholicism. 

Luther and the Protestant Ethic 

Thus our fundamental concern is with Luther’s religious ideas, 
and with the sociological results to which they gave rise. 

At this point, however, we must emphasize the fact th^t although 
Luther’s religious ideas were based upon an inward change in the 
whole situation which covered a century, they were still highly 
original and personal, and, above all, they arose simply out of 
the inner development of religious thought itself. Luther’s religious 

187a Seep. 821. 

B 


vol. n. 



466 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

ideas were not due to the reflex action of social, or even of eco- 
nomic, changes; they were based essentially and independently 
upon the religious idea, which alone gave rise to the social, eco- 
nomic, and political consequences. In order to carry out the 
religious idea in practice, and to make it victorious, in questions 
of practical organization, social, economic, and political causes 
did, it is true, play a very important part; but they had 
nothing whatever to do with the fundamental question of origin. 
So far as this was concerned the predominant and primary cause 
was the religious idea, pure and simple. At least, only very indirectly 
can we here discern certain traces of the influence of social, eco- 
nomic, and political causes. That is to say : the theories proclaimed 
by the Nominalism of later Scholasticism and the mysticism of 
the pre-Reformation opposition parties, were doubtless to some 
extent connected with the social changes which took place during 
the later Middle Ages. The whole tendency to emphasize the 
value of personal religious experience which this movement 
expressed, and the severance of the religious interest from the 
secular and political interest, was a result of the general situation, 
of the city-civilization, of the growing independence of national 
States, and of economic interests. Nevertheless, this influence was 
only indirect. It only cleared the ground for the new ideas which 
arose out of the intensely personal struggle and labours of the 
Monk of Erfurt and Wittenberg, and it penetrated them with the 
influence of an atmosphere in which a profound religious spiritu- 
ality was combined with an impulse towards activity and order. 
That, however, was the atmosphere of the German city-civiliza- 
tion of that period. This phenomenon, as is always the case at the 
great turning-points of history, was due to a combination of very 
different causes, originally entirely independent of each other ; only 
a doctrinaire fanaticism would try to reduce these causes to one. 
In this instance the religious idea was clearly the primary and the 
dominant impulse. For that very reason it is impossible to con- 
nect the Reformation world of thought with any particular social 
class. These ideas seized the imagination of peasants and demo- 
cratic artisans, of the lesser nobles who were fighting for their 
very existence, and of the greater nobles who belonged to the 
class of gr^at land-owners and princes, of city magistrates, guilds, 
and the proletariat of the towns. At the outset the Reformation 
was entirely free from social distinctions. If, however, it is claimed, 
and in a certain sense rightly, that upon the whole its tendency 
was bourgeois (especially as compared with the aristocratic 
Church of the early mediaeval period, and also with the sects, 



PROTESTANTISM 


467 

which were steeped in democratic and proletarian ideas), the 
reason for this can only lie in that indirect connection to which 
we have just alluded. This, again, was due to the fact (which it 
is not difficult to understand psychologically) that the growth of 
intellectual and spiritual individualism among large masses of 
people is invariably connected with the formation of cities ; within 
the city population, however, the Reformation — which from purely 
religious reasons was strongly conservative in temper — united 
with the bourgeois class, while, for the most part, the proletariat 
adhered to the more radical Protestant sect-type. It was only the 
later practical turn of events which constrained the Reformation 
to link its fortunes with those of the civil authorities, who could 
guarantee the preservation of order, that is, with the territorial 
princes ; but this did not alter its fundamentally bourgeois charac- 
ter. This whole development, however, was a very complicated 
affair, which cannot now be clearly and directly determined. The 
actual tendency, which was fostered by the religious emphasis upon 
the value of the individual, arose out of Luther’s own inner 
struggles . 198 What, then, was his religious position, which forms 
the basis of the sociological development of Protestantism? 

Theology of Luther 

It is customary to describe Protestantism as the revival of the 
Pauline and Augustinian religion of grace, in contrast to the 
Catholic religion of law. In the main this is true, but it needs a 
good deal of clear explanation and expansion. For in this renewed 
emphasis upon the Pauline and Augustinian doctrine of grace, 
the heart of the matter does not lie so much in the reassertion of 
‘‘Grace” against “Law”, as in the new conception of grace itself. 
The emphasis upon free grace and the exclusion of free-will was, 
however, directed immediately only against the dominant doc- 
trine of later scholasticism, which was prevalent in Luther’s day 
and which he outgrew. But this emphasis on “free grace” did not 
constitute an attack upon Catholicism in general . 199 To Catholi- 
cism as a whole Luther’s opposition was far more deep-seated. 
Catholicism, too, was a religion of grace, but its view of grace was 
that of sacramental grace, of supernature, of a higher, mystical, 

• 

1M See p. 821. 

199 This is strongly emphasized by Krogh-Tonningh: Der Letzte Scholastiker , 7904, 
by whom he means the Thomist and Dutch Carthusian Dionysius. The con- 
trast, however, does not lie in the polemic against Nominalist semi-Pelagianism, 
but in the idea of grace which is also opposed to St. Thomas and his ideas of 
predestination. % 



468 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

and miraculous power, imparted by the hierarchy, entrusted 
to the Church, which has a double effect : the forgiveness of sins 
and the mystical elevation of humanity. 

The idea of law was easily combined with this idea of grace. 
For, if the ethical character of grace were to be preserved, it had 
to be prepared for by ethical examination and earnest aspirations 
after holiness, both of which required a legal standard; for the 
same reason it had to be proved by good works, which again 
require a legal standard, and which without harm could be 
thought into the framework of the conception of Law, although it 
was still the power of imparted grace, which, at bottom, with the 
release of the natural energies of man, alone produced good works 
and merits. Luther’s new idea was therefore not merely the general 
re-emphasis upon grace, which makes a clean sweep of all com- 
promise with legalism, but beyond that, it gave a new meaning to 
the idea of grace itself. 

On the other hand, however, neither Luther nor Protestantism 
in general ever really removed the idea of Law from its central 
position. The Law remained as a stimulus to repentance, and as 
the pre-supposition of faith and the Gospel of grace. The Law 
remained as the most direct and primal expression of the Divine 
Will and Being, which only required a joyful and willing obedience 
in a spirit of love and confidence, but which precisely on that 
account required that the Law should be fulfilled in a complete 
and spiritual way. The Law remained as the pre-supposition for 
the Redemptive Work of Christ, who in His Death annihilated the 
Law, and only then made men free of the order of grace. Finally, 
the Law remained, although in a rather anomalous position, as 
the rule of life in the state of grace, only now severed from the 
idea of merit and of the achievement of salvation, because the 
grace on which salvation is founded does not consist in “merits” 
and “good works”, but in a transformed personality, in principle 
already wholly united with God. 

Thus, from this point of view also, it is clear that the new element 
in Protestant theology was not the overcoming of the conception 
of Law in itself, but the special content of the conception of grace, 
which gives to the Law a different meaning and position from 
that which it has in the Catholic idea of grace. Now the essential 
element in this new conception of grace is this : that grace is no 
longer a mystical miraculous substance, to be imparted through 
the sacraments, but a Divine temper of faith, conviction, spirit, 
knowledge, and trust which is to be appropriated ; in the Gospel 
and in the Love and Spirit of Christ towards mankind it can be 



PROTESTANTISM 


469 

discerned as the loving will of God which brings with it the forgive- 
ness of sins . 200 Religion thus steps out of the material substantial 
sphere, which was merely accompanied by thought and feeling, 
and enters into the intellectual, psychological, spiritual sphere. 
This does not mean that it ceases to be a miracle. But the miracle 
now consists in the fact that man in his weakness, rebellion, despair, 
and impurity can grasp such an idea from the Gospel; it is so 
entirely beyond the reach of his natural powers, and the religious 
idea of redemption is so far removed from the natural intellectual 
sphere, that only through the miracle of predestination can it come 
to pass. It is an inner miracle of faith in the Gospel and in Christ, 
not an interior-external miracle of the hierarchical-sacramental 
impartation of grace, which produces the power to do good works 
and to acquire merit. Moreover, it is not an idea that can be 
altered and changed at will, but a knowledge which is offered 
with the absolute certainty of revelation, which starts from the 
picture of the incarnate, suffering, and risen Son of God, and 
possesses in the Bible an absolute, wonderful, and authentic 
representation of this picture of Christ, even though, in detail, the 
Bible is not free from all kinds of human imperfections. In Protes- 
tantism, therefore, the heart of religion consists in the spirit of faith 
which is thus effected by the “Word 55 , just as for Catholicism it 
consists in priesthood and sacrament, in obedience and in mystic- 
ism. Religion is now a matter of faith and conviction, instead of 
one which is bound up with a hierarchical-sacramental system. 
The two Protestant sacraments which are retained are special 
methods of representing the Gospel ; their spiritual influence does 
not exceed that of the influence of the Word of God in the Scrip- 
tures; hence, in the Catholic sense, they are no longer sacra- 
ments . 201 

Now, however, this fundamental position contains, directly and 
indirectly, further implications. 

The first result is the reduction of the whole of religion to that 
which alone can be an object of faith and trust, that is, to that 
idea of God — evolved from the apostolic picture of Christ — which 
represents Him as a gracious Will, holy, forgiving sins, and thus 
leading men upwards into a higher life. All that needs to be 
added to this idea is that which will bring assurance to the sinner, 
namely, the knowledge of the Divine Revelation and condescen- 
sion in the Incarnate Son of God or the Logos. Further, the 
important element in this view of Christ is not the dim mysterious 
essence of His being, but the assurance of His Love which is 
200 See p. 823. 201 See p. # 824. 



470 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

conveyed by His self-abasement in the Incarnation, by His 
sufferings, and by His kindness — whereby sinful man can know 
for a fact that God forgives sins. 

This constitutes an immense simplification in doctrine, and a 
new method of basing doctrine upon its conscious power to 
awaken faith and trust. The unlimited authority of the apostolic 
picture of Christ, which guarantees all this, is taken for granted, 
as well as the miraculous nature of the Bible. The problem is not, 
how can this be proved? but, how can one gain this personal 
assurance? Surely this certainty is only possible through the 
predestinarian miraculous influence of the God who Himself 
creates faith. In every impulse towards trust the believer may 
feel something of the miraculous saving power of God. 

The second result of Luther’s teaching was that of religious 
individualism, that inwardness of communion with God which is 
independent of man or of a priesthood. Thus the whole idea of 
mediation through a hierarchy, and through sacramental grace, 
is swept away. This leads to the doctrine of the priesthood of all 
believers, and to lay religion, to the renewal of the primitive 
Christian independence and autonomy of the knowledge of God 
effected by “the Spirit”. At this point Luther came into touch 
with the corresponding tendencies in the sect-movement, which 
were also derived from the Bible. All that was actually discarded, 
however, was the idea of sacerdotal mediation ; mediation through 
the Word, that is, through the Bible (and, since this is essentially 
a witness to Christ, through the Scriptural picture of Christ) is 
emphasized all the more strongly. Only thus can God be known. 
Only thus does He reveal Himself as the God of Grace; every- 
where else, outside of Christ, He appears as the God of the awful 
metaphysical riddle and of the terror of the Law. Trust in Christ 
alone is genuine trust in God. Only through contact with Him 
does the soul enter into communion with God. Since, then, this 
picture of Christ is incarnated in the Bible, which is the work of 
God, the Bible or “the Word” is the only real means by which 
a personal relationship with God is mediated ; this idea totally 
excludes every kind of “direct” mysticism, which aims at union 
with God apart from Christ. This Bible, however, with its message 
of Christ, fprms the centre of the Church, which God has founded 
through Christ as the fellowship of believers which ought to result 
from the preaching of the Word. For this fellowship He has also 
established the ministry of the Word, or the preaching of the 
message of Christ, as the permanent objective foundation and 
mediation of salvation. All that is indifferent and left to human 



PROTESTANTISM 


47i 


choice is the method of calling to this ministry of the Word, and 
the technical-juridical details of organization. All that is needed 
is regular order and a proper training for one’s calling, in order 
to exclude self-will and mistakes due to lack of knowledge . 202 

The third conclusion to which this fundamental position leads 
is the principle of a pure spiritual ethic. If the whole value of 
man consists in a right attitude of faith and trust towards God in 
the Word, then this general spirit also forms the basis of the stan- 
dard for the ethical consequences to which it gives rise. Hence- 
forth there is no ecclesiastical, authoritative, moral law; the 
Church does not shoulder the responsibility of the individual ; the 
only rule for conduct is the impulse of the individual conscience. 
“Good works” exist no longer; all that matters is the general 
spirit and attitude of the individual. No longer can one reckon 
in terms of “merits” or “demerits” ; everything hinges on whether 
the new life is checked and hindered or allowed to develop freely. 
The system of future rewards and punishments has disappeared, 
and all that remains is the blessedness of the new creation, out of 
which all that is good will arise spontaneously. At the same time 
it was, of course, taken for granted that the standard of this 
spiritual ethic was still the law of the Decalogue and of the New 
Testament, since, as before, both agree with the natural moral 
law and therefore constitute the formula of the natural moral 
impulse — which merely became a “revealed” formula through 
those statements of Scripture. Those demands which were stabil- 
ized in the Decalogue, and which also formed part of the natural 
consciousness, only needed to be filled with the religious spirit 
which issues from faith in order to signify the good as presented 
by Christianity. It is therefore evident that this equation of the 
Decalogue and the Natural Law and the Christian Law, which 
is here taken for granted and continued, means the assimilation 
of the intra-mundane ethic into the Christian ethic, just as it had 
been assimilated previously in the whole of the patristic and 
mediaeval ethic . 203 

202 On this point cf. Herrmann: Der Verkehr des Christen mit Gott 5 , 1908. Here, 
however, the Lutheran Christology has been greatly modernized, and the 
significance of the sacraments, in particular that of the Real Presence in the 
Eucharist, has been very much modified. We only get a true picture when 
we add to this the Incarnational Christology and the objective sacramental 
doctrine. 

203 On this point cf. Gottschick: Ethik , 1906. Here the motives and the spirit of 

the Lutheran ethic are excellently explained; one misses here, however, as 
everywhere else, a detailed treatment of Luther’s conception of the content 
of the Christian moral law, of which more anon. t 



472 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

This spiritual ethic (or ethic of disposition) leads to the accep- 
tance of the world, to the disuse of monastic asceticism, to the new 
meaning given to the idea of vocation or “the calling”. The 
religious individualism of the religion of faith, which does not 
mean the acceptance of a certain number of authoritative ecclesi- 
astical dogmas, but simply a spirit of whole-hearted conviction, 
also affects the ethical temper. Everywhere this ethical temper is 
a whole, and therefore in principle it is everywhere the same, in 
spite of various ways of expression. This means that the ideal of 
perfection is the same for all alike ; hence it does away with the 
naive position of Catholicism which takes for granted the various 
degrees, grades, and ranks of perfection. It also discards all the 
works of supererogation and vicarious oblations which this idea 
involved. Above all, the Protestant ideal of perfection discards 
the whole idea of the monastic state as a false ideal of some 
special higher perfection. But this perfection, which is the same 
for all, is still not the rigorism of the Christian law, as in the 
sect; rather it means the spiritual equality, in principle created 
by the blessedness of forgiveness, from which the “doing” of the 
“new creature” issues freely. 

The religion of faith which denies the sacramental grace of 
Supernature also tends in the same direction. There is no longer 
any room for the conception of “Supernature” at all; the whole 
idea of a graduated system, leading from Nature up to Super- 
nature, from secular morality to that which is spiritual and 
supernatural, has faded away. Monasticism in any form only 
appears to be a special condition of moral behaviour, man-made, 
which flees from the natural conditions given by God; and by 
creating artificial conditions appears to set itself heavier tasks, 
although in reality it renders it easier for a Christian to overcome 
the world. The real problem, however, is to overcome the world 
wherever we find it, and in the midst of the life of the world to 
free our hearts from the world and to live in a spirit of detach- 
ment. There is no longer any room for self-chosen spheres of action, 
for forms of fellowship alongside of the life of the world, which 
claim to rise above it. It is precisely in the spirit of mutual service 
within the life of the world that Christian love is demonstrated. 
This also throws a fresh light on the system of vocational organ- 
izations, which, on the whole, Protestantism also regards as 
derived from the Natural Law. This system is no longer regarded 
as the organization of Natural Law in the lower sphere, above 
which rises the structure of the Church and of the mystical 
fellowship of love, but it is the sphere appointed by God for all, 



PROTESTANTISM 


473 


which includes the whole of Christian behaviour, in which each 
man must accept his own calling as the life-task assigned to him 
by God, and the contribution desired from him for the purpose 
of forming the Christian unity of love. 

The main types of “calling”, therefore — such as the calling of a 
house-father, or of marriage, the calling to be a paternal ruler, or 
to the exercise of authority in general — are held to have been 
specially instituted by God Himself. This idea does not contradict 
the other idea, that is, that these callings are equally derived from 
Natural Law; it is merely a special Divine confirmation of the most 
important “callings” appointed by Him . 204 Thus the previous 
conceptions of ministerium and officium are replaced by that of 
vocation this means that the whole system of callings is not a 
product of the lower sphere of Nature, a sphere which still has to 
be transcended, but that, like the natural sphere itself, it is a 
direct and immediate institution of God . 2043 It proceeds directly 
from Him, not indirectly from Nature, which is quite distinct 
from Him. This, however, is a new conception of Nature, as an 
inward and essential union between God and Nature, in which 
Nature is regarded as an immediate decree of His essential Will, 
and not as a lower degree of His self-emptying. To put it briefly : 
this system of vocational organization is a stable class-system of a 
patriarchal kind, fixed by Divine appointment in the Old Testa- 
ment and by the Law of Nature, to which each individual 
belongs, in permanent categories, usually receiving at birth his 
assigned calling. Further, we must not forget that this immediate 
Divine character of Nature is due to a simple, positive decree 
of the Will of God, which a Christian must accept in a spirit 
of humble obedience without any attempt at understanding it ; 
there is, however, no real inner essential connection between God 
and Nature; this is not asserted, nor is it felt to be so. Further, 
Nature has been so deeply corrupted by the Fall that not merely 
the present nature of man, but Nature in general, only reveals 
God in exceptional circumstances; on the whole it reveals far 
more the wickedness and cunning of the corruption of the Devil, 
and the misery which is the punishment of sin. Thus this ethic of 
vocation within the life of the world certainly means an accep- 
204 See p. 824. 

204a In order to understand the distinction between these two kindb of termin- 
ology we need to realize that the word officium was the official Latin term for 
“guild” (Z un ft)> von Oncken: Geschichte der Naturalokonomie , /, p. 112. Officium 
means the natural organization, vokatio means at the same time the Divine 
appointment which it contains; the latter, however, is much more strongly 
emphasized by S. 



474 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

tance of the world, but this acceptance is an act of obedience and 
surrender rather than one of joy in God’s world ; the idea of joy 
in the life of this present world because God made it, only appears 
now and again. At bottom, the acceptance of the world does not 
cease to be asceticism, that is, denial of the world, only it is a 
different kind of asceticism from the heroic asceticism of the 
Church, and it also differs from the legalistic detachment from 
the world practised by the sects. It is an asceticism which is in the 
world, yet not of it, which conquers the spirit of the world without 
fleeing from it; it means the practice of self-denial within one’s 
calling, which is regarded as a service to the whole community ; 
it means the obedience which remains where it is set, and there 
overcomes the “natural man” and the Devil . 205 As we proceed 
we shall often have to deal with the tension and difficulty which 
this acceptance of the world involves, an acceptance which far 
transcends the Catholic position and which is of great significance 
for the social philosophy of Protestantism. 

Ultimately, of course, more or less consciously, behind all this 
there are new conceptions of the fundamental ideas of religion: 
of God, the world, and man. We cannot here pursue this general 
question any farther 206 ; all we can do is to single out certain 
important points which are relevant to the subject of this 
book. 

In the doctrine of Man the influence of the new ideas appears 
most clearly in the doctrine of the Primitive State. Here the idea 
of an ascent from natural to supernatural perfection has disap- 
peared. In its stead we find the theory that the perfection of the 
Primitive State consisted in a spirit of complete and filial trust in 
God as an inherent element in the essential nature of man. Sin, 
therefore, is the destruction of human nature, and redemption 
is the restoration of human nature to full trust in God within the 
natural order of life. Here the new conception of the relation 
between God and man is perfectly clear. 

So far as the conception of the world is concerned, the natural 
consequence is the disappearance of the gradation idea. It dis- 
appears not only in ethics, and in the doctrine of redemption, but 
in the whole conception of the world itself. Matter and Nature do 

205 On this point cf. Karl Eger: Die Anschauungen Luthers vom Beruf> igoo, and 
Max Weber: Der Geist des Kapitalismus und die protestantische Ethik f Archiv. f. 
Sozialwiss.y XX and XXL 

106 On this point cf. the closing chapter in Harnack’s Dogmengeschichte and 
F. CL Baur: Der Gegensatz des Kath. u. Prot . nach den Prinzipien und Haupt- 
dogmen *, 1836. 



PROTESTANTISM 


475 


not constitute a stage in the Divine creation of the world which is 
more remote from the pure world of spirit; Nature is the sphere 
appointed by the Creator for the realization of ideal values. These 
values were completely realized in the Primitive State in the 
perfection of human nature, and they are restored by Redemption. 
They form an integral part of the life of the world as it now is, 
and do not transcend it by a higher degree of mystical-sacra- 
mental miraculous powers. The miraculous element is present, 
certainly, but its purpose is simply the healing of the misery of 
sin and the restoration of Nature, not the achievement of Super- 
nature. This is a different conception of miracle altogether. In 
the thought of Luther the miraculous element proceeds from the 
saving will of God which takes away sin, not from Supernature 
which constitutes the inmost heart of the Divine Being. This 
means, however, that the idea of evolution has disappeared in its 
Catholic form of an ascent from Nature to Grace, which Catholicism 
had combined with the Aristotelian doctrine of the steady process 
of the development of latent potentialities into actualities, or of 
the whole process of Nature as a struggle towards perfection. 
Man does not ascend from the Primitive State to a supernatural 
perfection which has already been prepared by Nature; the 
universe and the earth do not evolve from Nature into the realm 
of Grace ; Society is not linked with a natural basis in order that 
there may be a natural continuity between it and the super- 
natural fellowship of Grace. In the Protestant theory everything 
is complete in a moment, and the Aristotelian doctrine of evolu- 
tion disappears, as well as the Neo-platonic theory of emanations. 
The Fall does not mean a relapse into Nature, and Redemption 
is not the ascent from Nature to Grace ; rather the idea is that the 
Fall means the removal of Nature, and Redemption is its restora- 
tion. This theory leaves no room for compromise, adaptation, 
transitional processes, or evolution as in Catholic dogma ; all that 
matters is the Fall of Man and his restoration to God. That is 
why the Christian ethic is also not connected with and developed 
out of a natural basis, but is restored by the miracle of Grace, 
and then merely transferred, in a quite external manner, into the 
sphere of activity provided by natural conditions which have to 
be accepted in the spirit of obedience. This point of view shatters 
the whole fabric of Catholic reconciliation in the realm* of meta- 
physics and of ethics, as well as its doctrine of Society. Out of the 
ruins there arises a very hard and artificial conception of life — 
one in which there is no room for relative conceptions nor for any 
process of evolution. This comes out very clearly in the difficulties 



476 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

and inconsistencies of the Lutheran ethic , 207 which we shall be 
studying later on. 

Last of all, the whole change of view in Protestantism is summed 
up and expressed in its Idea of God. This is no longer a blend of 
the natural idea of the infinite absolute Substance which reveals 
itself in varying degrees, and the personalistic conception of the 
Divine Law which controls everything in Nature and in the 
spiritual world and which, by grace, makes it possible to fulfil 
the highest mystical law of revelation, with corresponding merit 
and celestial happiness as a result. In his Idea of God Luther 
discards scientific metaphysics and all attempts to reconcile the 
finite with the infinite; with resolute anthropomorphism this 
Idea of God is conceived as the Divine Will. No longer are the 
ideas of Nature and Supernature placed side by side, but their 
place is taken by the antitheses of the Law and the Gospel, the 
moral demand and the loving will which forgives sins, retribution, 
and grace. The method of harmonizing these elements is found 
in the Atoning Death of the God-Man. The Atonement, therefore, 
becomes the central doctrine of Protestantism, and the idea of 
vicarious achievement, discarded in every other connection, is 
here developed to its fullest extent. 

In such a conception of God the motives and aims of religious 
fellowship, and the justification of the natural social forms of life, 
are quite different from those inspired by the Catholic Idea of 
the Absolute Being, and of the development of the world from 
Nature up to the miracle of Supernature. As we pursue this inquiry 
further, it will become quite clear that this changed Idea of God 
is the final cause of all the other changes which we are now about 
to consider. 

The preceding analysis has noted the essential elements in the 
religious thought of the Reformation. It is manifest that these 
ideas are not a mere renewal of Scriptural Christian piety, 
whether of the Synoptic or of the Pauline and Johannine tradi- 
tion, but that they represent a transference of mediaeval dogma, 
the Mediaeval Church, and the mediaeval ethic, to a conception 
of religion (drawn from Paul) as a matter of inward faith and a 
new spirit ; in short, the Pauline religion of grace and of Christ. 
This coiRes out particularly plainly in the new value given to the 
natural life, which was only brought fully under Christian 
influence in the Middle Ages. This connection between the natural 
life and Christianity is retained ; it is only justified and made 
practical for different reasons. Beneath the thought of the Protes- 
, * 07 See p. 825. 



PROTESTANTISM 


477 


tant Reformation there lay the fact of the mediaeval expansion of 
Christianity. All that took place was that this mediaeval contribu- 
tion was based afresh on new religious ideas and was reshaped 
by them. 

Sociological Effect of Luther’s Thought: 
the New Conception of the Church 

We now come to our second main question: What were the 
sociological results of this religious transformation of Christianity? 
The preceding paragraphs have already suggested a simple reply 
to this question, at least so far as actual essentials are concerned. 
But as we proceed with the inquiry in detail we shall discover 
many difficulties which were caused by the complication of 
these ideas. 

In this connection the decisive element is not the peculiar 
juridical form of the Lutheran conception of the Church (with 
which the next section will deal), but, primarily, it is the funda- 
mental fact that, from the very outset, this whole intellectual 
outlook belongs, essentially, to the Church-type. This means that 
the new conception of the Church fundamentally determines 
the sociological outlook of all the Protestant groups and gives to 
them its peculiar difficulties. 

In spite of the fact that this school of thought has many affinities 
with the sect-type, in spite of its individualism, its lay religion, its 
appeal to the authority of the Bible, its emphasis upon the sub- 
jective realization of salvation in personal and inward Christian 
piety, and on the restriction of the true Church to real Christians, 
who have been truly “born again” — in spite of all this, in its in- 
most being it reveals no tendency whatever towards the sect-type ; 
indeed, it regards the Church-type, in the most natural way, as 
the only Christian type of ecclesiastical organization. 

From the very outset this is what Luther intended: (i) the 
reform of the ecclesiastical organ of grace and of redemption, so 
that its true basis of grace may be revealed in the Word, in the 
knowledge of Christ, and in the assurance of the forgiveness of 
sins which springs from Christ; (2) the reform of the priesthood, 
in order to restore it to its true office, instituted by Christ Himself, 
of the proclamation of the Word, or “preaching Christ” ; (3) the 
reform of the sacraments — that is, from rites which impart the 
“substance of grace”, they are to be transformed into rites 
appointed by Christ as “means of grace” which seal the assurance 
of the Gospel of the forgiveness of sins. 

Luther took for granted that, along with these demands for 



478 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

reform, all baptized Christians, however immature or nominal 
they might be, were included in the Church ; that Infant Baptism 
should be retained and universally practised, and that the 
efficacy of the means of grace is independent of the subjective 
state both of the celebrant and of the soul which receives these 
mysteries. Luther had no desire to found a new Church ; he simply 
wished to introduce an instauratio catholica , that is, to lead the One 
Catholic Apostolic Church, founded by Christ and endowed by 
Him with ministry, Word, and Sacrament, back to its purely 
spiritual activity of proclaiming the Word which creates faith. 

The Word itself, however, its foundation in the Bible, its 
manifestation in the Sacrament, and its proclamation in the 
sermon, is to him an objective and precious endowment, intended 
for the benefit of all the individuals in the world, which the 
Church (as an institution) appropriates, and which is to be 
administered in an orderly manner by officials appointed for that 
purpose. Where officials of this kind do not exist laymen may 
officiate in their stead. The layman who discharges this duty, 
however, is thereby entitled to that precise share in the objective 
treasury of grace. In this respect, in the significance of a Depositum 
which the organ of grace established by Christ appropriates, and 
in the complete independence of the organ of grace from any 
standard of subjective realization, Luther’s conception of grace is 
precisely the same as that of Catholicism. The differences lie only 
in the conception of the content of grace. From that point of view, 
however, both the nature and the method of influence of the 
ecclesiastical institution are considerably different. 

The hierarchical sacramental Church is replaced by the Church 
which lays the main emphasis upon the Word of Scripture and its 
proclamation by the preachers. This Church, however, is also an 
institution set over its members as their supernatural source, 
instituted and directed by God Himself. This Church is entirely 
unaffected by the occurrence or non-occurrence of the subjective 
effects of conversion in particular individuals : in itself it is holy 
and Divine, through the converting power inherent in the 
“Word” ; its position as a Divine institution is still supreme, even 
when very few are actually “converted” souls, while as a united 
body it extends its influence through all its special developments in 
the form of a national church, or in other ways. For, where there is 
the Word and the Sacrament, there is the Church, and the super- 
natural source of all experiences of salvation ; and faith is certain 
that “the Word of God never returns unto Him void”, that is, 
that finally its indwelling miraculous power will yet overcome all 



PROTESTANTISM 


479 

obstacles, and that in the end it must also inwardly convert 
humanity to Christ. This will certainly never be a comprehensive 
conversion including the whole of humanity. The Devil and 
sin are too strong for that, and the confusions of the present 
Church point to the End of the World, in which the great 
conflict between Christ and Antichrist will bring the struggle 
to a conclusion. 

This conception of the Church is extremely spiritual and 
idealistic, making the essence of the Church to consist in the 
Word, the Sacrament, and the office of the ministry, and restrict- 
ing it to a purely spiritual sphere of influence. It is, however, 
always and supremely a “Church” conception. It is the Catholic 
theory of the Church, only purified and renewed (in the New 
Testament there is very little support for these ideas at all) ; it is a 
transformation of the idea of a merely universal, all-inclusive 
Church, with an unbroken priesthood, and an absolute possession 
of truth, into the earlier and more primitive conception of a pure 
Christocentric religion which exalted the ideas of grace and 
faith, and whose only objective support is the word of Christ in the 
Scriptures. The whole of the supernatural element in this Church 
is focused in the “Word” — this idea gathers up all the objectivity 
and holiness, the sense that the Church as an institution is inde- 
pendent of the individual and personal point of view, and is, in 
fact, entirely objective — this idea of the “Word”, however, is of 
the very highest importance for the Protestant conception of the 
Church. It constitutes the sociological point of contact, freed from 
the subjective element, secured quite simply, and endowed with 
a supernatural power of influence, from which, it is held, the 
Church is to be reconstructed. This conception was the Protestant 
equivalent for the Catholic episcopate, with its final centralization 
in the Papacy. In addition, of course, stress is laid upon the fact 
that the Church does not consist merely in the “Word”, but in 
the interior personal influence of the Word, and thus in the 
“holy community”, the fellowship composed of those who have 
been truly born again. This reveals Luther’s principle of personal 
piety and of spirituality, and (as will appear later on) it was to this 
aspect of his teaching that the Anabaptists and the sectarians 
actually appealed. In Luther’s mind, however, this ^renewed 
inward fellowship was always only the correlate of the Word of 
Grace, and the ministry of the Word which has produced this 
fellowship ; this holds good whether the message was given by an 
ordained minister or by some lay Christian brother. Since, how- 
ever, in practice it was impossible to distinguish the converted from 



480 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

the unconverted by any external sign, this attempt to limit the 
meaning of the Church had no practical significance at all. In 
reality, wherever the Word is preached, there is the Church. Even 
if there were only one solitary believer in a certain place, there the 
Church would exist as an institution, for the Church is virtually 
contained in the Word, as the creator of the fellowship perpetually 
exercising its miraculous influence, and never in vain. The Church 
would still exist even if there were nothing left save the Word. 
From that source it would ever arise anew. It is the duty of all 
Christians, and especially of Christian rulers (in whom alone, 
indeed, at first Christendom is rightly represented), to render the 
Word accessible to every one, to arrange for its regular proclama- 
tion, and thus, at least in external matters, to do what is necessary 
to ensure the establishment of the supremacy of the Word, in order 
that everywhere the Church may arise out of the Word “in spirit 
and in truth”. The method by which this is to be effected — 
whether through some future General Council, or, if that is im- 
possible, through the nearest authorities who can be appointed in 
the district and in the whole country, together with their natural 
counsellors, the professional theologians — is simply a matter of 
convenience, a question of linking on to the positive law which is 
already in existence. In all this, however, as far as possible all 
violent excitement is to be avoided, and until order has been 
evolved out of confusion the matter may be handled in very 
different ways — Luther, indeed, expresses very varying and in- 
consistent opinions on this point. When he is confronted with the 
question of a non-Protestant Government he feels it needful to 
organize a body which shall be entirely independent of the 
State; when this happens he emphasizes the fact that the secular 
power must not interfere in spiritual matters. 

The result of these ideas is obvious : if universal order is not 
affected by the Empire or by a Council, and if the expectation of 
the approaching End of the World which is rife amid all this 
confusion is also not fulfilled, it then becomes the duty of the 
laity, and especially of the rulers, to help the Word of God to 
have free course, as Occam and the Conciliar theologians had 
already demanded — a demand which was entirely in accord with 
the whok previous outlook of Christian Society. This does not do 
away with the idea of the “holy Church throughout the world” 
which Catholicism preserves; for wherever the Word is present 
in any Church at all, there is the universal Church, and the par- 
ticular Church in question is only a section or a corruption of 
the one universal Church. The “Invisible Church” is not the right 



PROTESTANTISM 


481 

term for Luther’s conception of the Church, although he himself 
sometimes uses this confusing expression; what he really meant 
was that the Church is visible in the Word and the Sacrament, 
but invisible and incalculable in her purely spiritual influence. 
His idea might be expressed rather differently, somewhat in this 
way: the Church of the Word is purely spiritual, effecting the 
New Birth by means which cannot be defined outwardly, while 
at the same time she is present in the Word and the Sacrament 
and endued with the possibility of exercising a universal influence 
upon the State and upon Society, (which for that very reason 
means that she requires an external Christian organization 
of the State) which will make it possible for the Church to 
reach everyone, while otherwise her own organization is left 
very free. 

Luther and the Reformers, like the Catholic theologians, focus 
Christian thought in the theory of the conception of the Church. 
This, however, is no mere relic of mediaeval thought, a barrier 
which can easily be swept away, but it is part of the very essence 
of its religious thought, which, in this respect, is entirely in agree- 
ment with the mediaeval and primitive conception of the Church, 
traced back to its very beginnings in St. Paul. Stated quite simply, 
the one thing we need to realize is this : Luther conceived and 
understood Christianity essentially as grace, as the basis of the 
assurance of salvation. A soul with this point of view is pre- 
destined to belong to the Church-type. To this type of mind 
salvation is something finished, certain and sure, a pure gift of 
God, independent of the ego, of all one’s own struggles and 
subjective efforts, and only has to be appropriated by faith ; the 
soul then absorbs the great principle of an objective Divine 
creative energy, which effects everything in and through the 
individual, while it is itself quite independent of the individual. 

It is the profound conception of an historical life-substance 
which first produces all individuals, combined with the religious 
idea of grace, in accordance with which the possession of faith is 
a gift, not an achievement. This means, further, that it is only 
through this most precious gift that the powers of the individual 
are set free to develop their highest and richest possibilities. Both 
these phenomena, however — the historic substance* and the 
element of grace which it contains — are conceived as a super- 
natural institution, strictly distinguished from all that is secular, 
whose fundamental supernatural elements, the Word and the 
Sacrament, produce faith, freely and inwardly, without com- 
pulsion and apart from external law, through the Divine energy 
vol. n. c 



482 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

which they contain. 208 In Luther’s view a Divine operation of 
this kind could not be based upon the subjective foundation of 
individual illumination and mystical knowledge — experiences 
which often cannot be disentangled from the phantasy of the 
individual. He felt that the Divine operation must be manifested 
in something objective, “given”, the same for all, something 
entirely authoritative, miraculous, and definite, standing out in 
clear relief against all that is merely human. To him this objective 
element was summed up only in the Divine institution of the 
Church, and in the Divine Word, through which the Church 
becomes outwardly visible, and is, indeed, its creative centre. 
This is the reason why Luther opposed the sectarians with such 
heat, because they regarded the basis of salvation and the bond 
of fellowship as consisting in obedience to the Law of God and 
therefore in subjective attainment. All forms of sociological 
development which were made concrete in the idea of law were 
suspect to Luther. In spite of the fact that the Law was part of 
the Divine revelation, he still insisted that it could not serve as a 
basis for salvation or for fellowship because law cannot exist 
without subjective achievement, and therefore it would again 
lead to placing the main stress upon the subjective achievement 
of man rather than on the “givenness” of the Grace of God. Like- 
wise he would have nothing to do with mystics, enthusiasts, or 
fanatics. He held that in their “illuminations” there was nothing 
objective, no creative element of unmistakably Divine origin, 
upon which their fellowship was based. Rather, he believed that 
these “lights” were the creation of their own minds — auto-sugges- 
tion, in fact — which they tried to prove, later on, to be of Divine 
origin, by practical achievements or by the subjective fulfilment 
of the Law. This is why, in his study of the Bible, Luther discerned 
solely the Pauline and Johannine type of doctrine; that is, the 
type in which grace, and its objective assurance in the Body of 
Christ and in the Person of Christ, is everything. The Christ of 
the Synoptic Gospels, however, the Christ proclaimed by the 
Franciscans and the Waldensians, made no appeal to him whatso- 
ever. Neither had Luther any interest in the Law of Christ, so 
far as this could be regarded as a general rule of life and a basis 
of Christian fellowship. It never seems to have occurred to him 
that there might possibly be some other interpretation of Christ 
and His Law than that proclaimed by legalistic orthodox sect- 
arians. Luther makes Paul his doctrinal standard in everything, 
and even in Paul he ignores all the “enthusiastic” and mystical 

808 See p. 825. 



PROTESTANTISM 


483 

features, and concentrates on his idea of the Church. To Luther, 
therefore, Infant Baptism was absolutely essential, as it is to all 
men of the Church-type. He held that this Sacrament is the 
outward sign and seal of the objective, universal, world- wide 
claim of the Church, asserting her will over every individual ; it 
also represents the pure “givenness” of grace, the independence 
of the Church of all individualistic subjective effort and achieve- 
ment, and, finally, it stands for the utmost comprehensiveness, 
implying that the Church is composed of Christians at all stages 
of experience, from the simplest believer to the greatest saint. 
Luther regarded Adult Baptism and rebaptism, on the contrary, 
as a symbol of legalism and of the sectarian spirit, which bases 
fellowship and salvation upon personal subjective achievement. 
The doctrinal expression of the idea of Baptism itself was still 
regarded as a matter of no particular importance, but logically it 
approximated more and more to the idea of an actual miracle of 
regeneration, which gives to all who have been baptized — in the 
possibility of appealing to the fact of their baptism — a character 
indelebilis. Every experience of repentance and conversion, and 
the entire work of the religious and moral life, means a renewal of 
baptismal grace, in which grace is fundamentally assured to every 
member of the Church, just as an entail belongs to all those who 
have been born into it. As time went on, in the interest of this 
objective institutional character of the Church, Luther laid more 
and more emphasis upon the sacraments, in which the Word 
which creates salvation reveals its objective aspect, and in which 
the Sacrament of Holy Communion in particular, in the Real 
Presence of Christ in His Flesh and Blood, reaches the highest 
point of objectivity. In this emphasis Luther established the 
distinctive character of Lutheran theology, whereas the Calvinists 
were content to regard the sacraments simply as tokens which 
conveyed the certainty of grace and the spiritual character of the 
Word. Thus Luther restored the practice of confession as a means 
of conveying the objective assurance of absolution through the 
ministry of the Word, and also in order to ensure a thorough 
preparation, through self-examination, for the reception of the 
Word of God which was contained in the Word of absolution . 209 
This whole tendency arose quite logically out of Luther’s own 
personal position, which was determined by his training in 
scholastic theology, as well as by his original interpretation of the 
Bible. For lack of more exact knowledge it is impossible to decide, 
at this distance of time, to what extent his views may also have 
109 Cf. E. Fischer: Z ur Gesch. der evangelischen Beichte , 1903. 



484 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

been affected by his personal temperament, as well as by the 
atmosphere in which he lived, which was steeped in the idea of 
authority. It is manifest that Luther was strongly inclined towards 
the side of authority, in spite of all his sense of the need for inner 
freedom, and it is Ice wise evident that he was essentially con- 
servatively inclined, in of all his fearlessness and recklessness 
in instances when he was urged forward by his conscience. It 
seems, however, almost certain, that while these ideas affected the 
special form in which, later on, he formulated his conception of 
the Church (and above all, as we shall see, his conception of 
Natural Law), yet they did not affect the central idea, the con- 
ception of the Church itself. This central conception was essen- 
tially bound up with his idea of grace and the Word, with his 
conservative attitude in questions of revelation, especially in cases 
of supposed “illumination” and “new revelation”, and with his 
aversion to every other rule of life save that of the revelation 
through grace, which possessed its objective standard in the Word 
and the Church, upon the basis of which it was then possible to 
adapt oneself to the life of the world. To erect any other standard 
seemed to Luther to savour of subjectivism and fanaticism, or of 
dependence upon “good works”, and therefore to betray a 
legalistic spirit . 210 

Thus we see that the whole of the thought of the Reformation 
was dominated by the Church-type, which was due in the last 
resort to the religious originality of the Reformation itself. Luther 
was only able to exert his enormous influence on world-history as 
a Reformer of the Church. It was only because he held so firmly 
to the idea of the supernatural universal character of the Church 
that he was able to have an influence on institutions of a universal 
character. Without this conception Luther would have been 
merely the founder of a new sect, or of a new Religious Order, or 
even a solitary individual like Sebastian Franck. 

Sociological Effects of 

this Conception of the Church 

This predominance of the Church-type, however, meant that 
all the essential sociological effects also appeared. It led first of 
all to the Remand for the uniformity, unity, and universal dominion 
of the Church, which, in the impossibility of carrying throjgh a 
thorough Reformation, either European or German, finally led 
to the establishment of united Territorial Churches. Secondly, 
this emphasis on universality led to the extension of the ecclesi- 

210 See p. 827. 



PROTESTANTISM 


485 

astical ethic into the sphere of secular civilization and of the social 
order, to the acceptance of the general order of life which did not 
harmonize directly with the Christian moral ideal, but which 
was inevitable; and, finally, to the perpetuation of the funda- 
mental conception of the Lex Naturae , which was the complement 
of the purely Christian ethic . 211 

That these effects were the natural product of the Church-type 
is apparent from the fact that Luther himself did not accept these 
conclusions at all easily ; only gradually did they force themselves 
upon his mind with increasing insistence as inevitable and logical 
deductions from the idea of the Church. He only developed the 
idea of universality with difficulty, and almost in spite of himself. 
This was due to the fact that the idea of the compulsory dominion 
of a Universal Church was opposed to his spiritual and inward 
conception of the nature of the Church, and also because his pre- 
occupation with the idea of the priesthood of all believers inciden- 
tally brought him very close to the sect-type, with its method of 
building up a Church fellowship on the basis of voluntary in- 
dividual membership. Nor did the extension of the ethic of the 
Church into the social sphere take place without hesitation and 
misgiving ; this was due to the fact that Luther’s emphasis upon 
the Bible led him into deep sympathy with the Gospel ethic of 
love, which was utterly opposed to the ordinary life of the world, 
to the secular nature of the struggle for existence, to the lust of 
power, to law, and to the desire to amass possessions; thus in this 
direction also he came into touch with the sectarian ethic. 

Let us now turn to the first result of Luther’s conception of the 
Church. 

(I) Absolute Conception of Truth 

With the supernatural idea of the Church — which regards the 
Church as a Divine foundation, endowed with a truth absolutely 
authoritative, and secure against all merely human opinion — there 
was constituted the absolute conception of Truth, which implied 
unity, unchangeable character, universality, and infallibility of 
the Church in the heart of the organization upon which it was 
based. 

In Catholicism this idea was achieved through degma and 
tradition, through the hierarchy and the sacraments, and from 
this fundamental impulse it developed into the world-dominating 
system which was finally forced to inscribe upon its banner its prin- 
ciple of compulsion, in direct opposition to its original principles. 

211 See p. 829. 



486 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

In Protestantism this central fact was the Word of the Scriptures, 
and the Sacrament which was the sign and seal of the Gospel, 
with the natural result of an ordered ministry of the Word, which 
was, however, dependent upon circumstances for the way in 
which it was to be exercised. Protestantism, therefore, was faced 
with a twofold problem : (a) to stabilize the definition of the “pure 
Word”, and ( b ) to organize a ministry of the Word, which would 
proclaim the Faith in its purity. In both directions, however, the 
new conception of the Church experienced considerable difficulty. 
The Word which lay at the root of this conception should be, in 
Luther’s great and free way of thinking, the activity of Christ — 
the Pauline and Johannine conception of Christ contained in the 
Bible, interpreted in the sense of the Nicene Creed and the Creed 
of Chalcedon, through the doctrine of the Trinity. But how was 
this Word to be defined within the Bible? Its free development 
beyond the Bible, and its basis upon personal experience, opened 
the door to the most varied interpretations, and to new mystical 
interpretations which went far beyond the standpoint of the 
Bible. The only course to pursue was to close the door, to make a 
very clear distinction between the free proclamation of the Word 
and its written foundation in the Bible. Then the proclamation 
of the message was closely connected with its written basis, the 
Bible as a whole was canonized, in harmony with the dogma of 
the early Conciliar legislation, while its exposition was regulated 
by fixed standards, drawn from the Scriptures themselves, that is, 
from Paulinism. Thus the Protestant dogma of the Bible was 
created, according to which the Bible is the centre of the Church, 
the absolutely inspired authority, and the operative power of 
salvation through the converting power which dwells within 
it. The Bible proves and manifests its own infallibility by the Holy 
Spirit who dwells within it; its meaning is sufficiently clear to 
enable it to overcome all difficulties arising out of varieties of 
interpretation. This result was inevitable, if the conception of the 
Church were really to be based upon the Bible, and thus to attain 
genuine stability. Thus with Luther himself the rudimentary 
beginnings of a free historical human interpretation of the Bible 
disappeared, and the process was completed in the subsequent 
period of ^orthodoxy. The conception of the Church as the organ 
of salvation, Divinely instituted, required once for all a truth 
which should be firmly established, clearly defined, equally 
binding upon all, and this conception of truth required the abso- 
lute authority of the Bible, which would be impossible apart from 
a kind of literary Incarnation of the Divine. The Protestant 



PROTESTANTISM 


487 

extension of the Incarnation in the Bible corresponds to the 
Catholic extension of the Incarnation in the priesthood. The 
historic-human Bible criticism, and the establishment of the 
validity of the Bible upon the personal experience of salvation, 
was the weak point in the whole idea of the Church . 212 

(II) The Ministry of the Word 
The other question, namely, the problem of the organization 
of a ministry for the proclamation of the Word, was no less 
difficult. The Word is the support of the Church, and not a 
hierarchy based on apostolic succession. The essence of the Word, 
however, consists in its power of forming personal conviction and 
of producing the New Birth. Thus the real supporters of the 
Church are Christians who have been born again through 
the Word, genuinely converted and live Christian people, and the 
direction of the organization of the Church is in their hands. Thus 
the Church seems to be constituted by the co-operation and strict 
Christian piety of its members. This, however, only seemed to be 
the case. In reality, the situation was quite different. In the 
confusion of the period of transition, when the adherents of the 
old religion and the associates of the Augsburg Confession still 
worshipped together, when the order of the Roman Church had 
not yet been discarded, and the new order had not yet been 
established, when men still hoped that a Council or an order on 
the part of the Empire might find a way out of the impasse, and 
when these hopes had been shattered, Luther began to believe 
the End of the World was imminent, and that the only Church 
organization which mattered was the gathering of the faithful 
into groups to prepare for the Second Advent. It was then that 
Luther gave several instructions about the formation of smaller 
groups of genuine believers, with their own Christian order of life, 
and a distinct practice of confession and communion, based on 
the principle of financial self-support and the right to call their 
own pastors. This happened during the period of ferment, when 
the attempts at reform were purely local, the time when Luther 
allowed the congregations to make experiments based on the 
principle of the priesthood of all believers. By some this period }ias 
been described as a complete break with the Catholic idea of the 
Church; by others, on the contrary, it has often been Excused as 
a temporary deviation towards the sect-type. In reality, both these 
interpretations are incorrect. This “congregational ideal” does 
not in any way mean that the idea of the Church as an institution 

212 See p. 830. 



488 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

has been renounced. For these smaller and purer Christian groups 
have also been created by the Word, and their view of doctrine 
is always exercised by means of a wonderful agreement produced 
by the Word and its miraculous power; the congregation is only 
the product of the heart of the institution, of the Word, and never 
the factor which produces the Christian fellowship itself. More- 
over, these groups are only regarded as the kernel of Christendom, 
as a temporary means of education, which by their example and 
influence are to educate men from whom the Word shall again go 
forth to mankind in general. Not only, however, is the institutional 
conception of the Church preserved, but the tendency towards 
universality, and towards a state of affairs in which, ultimately, a 
given territory and the religion of that territory would coincide, 
with some unimportant fluctuations, is also retained. In all this, 
however, it is assumed that, sooner or later, matters will come 
to a head, and that the final issue of all these events will be either 
the End of the World, or, if the world is to continue in existence, 
a universal reform of the Church. Luther, indeed, only turned to 
the idea of this group organization after the appeal to the nobility 
(that is, to the ruling princes) had failed, and the hope of a General 
Council had been indefinitely postponed. In his mind these groups 
were to be meetings of the faithful during the dissolution of the 
Church before the coming of Antichrist; he regards the vital 
unity of the Church as so essential and natural that he can only 
account for its breakdown by regarding it as a sign of the begin- 
ning of the final throes of a dying era. These groups were to be 
merely temporary forms of organization ; there was to be nothing 
final about them. It is also obvious that in addition to these 
groups he was counting on the power of a Christian Government 
to maintain the Christian order of life, and to defend it against 
“tumult” and open blasphemy. Indeed, he only recommends this 
new form of congregational organization in cases where the 
existing Church-order and the rights of patronage exclude the 
reform of the whole parish in the Protestant sense. In such a case 
the Christians who have become genuinely “evangelical” ought 
to form a group, and if they appoint one of their members as a 
preacher it should be a priest who has adopted the new views ; 
in this way the continuity of Church-order will be secured. Further, 
these groups ought to act as far as possible through their natural 
representatives, the local authorities, in order that all should be 
done in harmony with the existing order, and in the interests of 
the ChurclTand not at the caprice of individuals. Public worship 
should be open to all ; it is only the more select body of communi- 



PROTESTANTISM 


489 

cants which is to have a closer form of special organization ; 
Infant Baptism, of course, is to be administered as before, and 
the children and young people must receive religious instruction. 
All these experiments, however, are to cease from the moment 
that it has been decided that a Reformation of the Church at 
large is out of the question ; that is, when action no longer has to 
be regulated by the points of view prevailing in the various 
parishes which often were entirely opposed to each other, but 
when the countries which have accepted the principles of the 
Reformation proceed to undertake an independent united organ- 
ization of their ecclesiastical affairs. When that took place it was 
quite natural that the ruling princes and the civil authorities, as 
parishioners who are bound to obey the Word of God, and as the 
appointed representatives of the parishes, should undertake to set 
the Church in order by means of special “Visitations”, and to 
establish the dominion of the “pure Word”, which, at least in its 
purity, must be set everywhere upon the lampstand, that all may 
rejoice in its light. This “group ideal”, which had only been 
understood in a very relative sense, disappeared entirely, and the 
idea of a universal world-wide Church was replaced by the 
Territorial Church system, without, however, doing away with the 
idea of the universal Catholic Church, since wherever the ministry 
of the Word and the administration of the sacraments are practised, 
even under very different forms, there is the Catholic Church. 
With his conception of the universal united Church, Luther can 
only explain the apostasy of the Roman Church by declaring that 
the Pope is the Antichrist who was prophesied in the Apocalypse ; 
in this way he removes the stumbling-block created by the falling 
away of so large and permanent a section from the original 
pure Church of the Word, so long as the ideal is retained of a 
universal Church, ruled by God Himself, outside which there can 
be no salvation. That which has already been Divinely foretold 
can be no argument against the institution of the “pure Church” 
set up by God Himself. 

(Ill) The Territorial Church System 
The Territorial Church system, therefore, finally secures the 
following elements: the universal character of the Church, its 
claim to dominate the life of the world, the maintenance of “pure 
doctrine”, and an ordered ministry on orthodox lines. Naturally 
Luther did not want the ruling princes to control the Church; 
this development was due rather to a logical development from 
the situation in the later Middle Ages, and, in any case, it was 



490 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

inevitable once the whole organization had been entrusted to the 
rulers of the different States. All that Luther desired was to 
secure the kind offices of the various Governments for the Church, 
but he also expected that the Word of God within these churches 
would be left entirely free. This ideal of Luther implied a division 
of authority within the social order which involved many diffi- 
culties from the very outset. In its purely Lutheran sense it was 
only possible to maintain this ideal in the over-idealistic belief 
that the Word would spontaneously produce within the Church 
a harmonious understanding of the truths of Scripture and a clear 
message; further, so far as events outside the Church were con- 
cerned, Luther held that the Word would teach the Government 
what to do, and that the laity would accept its ruling in free and 
willing obedience, so far, that is, as the right way had not already 
been made plain by the Law of Nature. Since church-order is no 
longer regulated by the legal supremacy of the hierarchy, the 
whole question is now entrusted to the influence of the Word 
itself, an influence which can never fail to produce an effect, an 
influence which is both united and uniting, an influence, which, 
apart from violent human efforts, will create the unity of the 
Corpus Christianum . When the Word fails to do this the only 
conclusion that can be drawn is that this failure is due to the 
power of sin and of the Devil, as so often happens in this wicked 
world. At this point Luther came very near to the eschatological 
apocalyptic point of view, in which the one thing that matters is 
that in the evil of these latter days individuals shall save their 
souls through faith and patience. This close connection between 
the renunciation of the uniform Christian order and the eschato- 
logical temper, as well as the close connection between plans 
made with permanent conditions in view and the reform of the 
whole life of Christendom, reveal more clearly than anything else 
that in his conception of the Church Luther had not given up 
the idea of universality, nor the ideal of a spiritual dominion over 
the whole of life ; it would, indeed, have been impossible for him 
to give up this hope, since it was based upon the assumption that 
the purified Church also possesses the absolute Truth which alone 
can bring salvation to mankind. These fluctuations and these 
early expressions of a “group ideal” do certainly show very 
plainly tHfe peculiar nature of the Lutheran church conception. 
Luther evidently believed that it was possible to base the uniform 
and all-embracing dominion of the Word purely upon inward 
personal conviction and fellowship, purely upon faith in this 
Word working through love, while the question of external 



PROTESTANTISM 


491 


organization was ignored. In his conception of the “Word” and 
of “Faith” Luther wished to combine the objective character of 
an institution with the subjectivism of personal Christian piety, 
as the fundamental creative forces within the Church. He found 
it very difficult, however, to combine these two opposite idea s, 
and it is therefore not surprising that this conception of the 
Church went far beyond Luther’s own ideal, first in one direction 
and then in another . 213 

Since, however, the universal character of the Church was thus 
restored, not merely through the power of the Word, but by the 
maintenance of an external Christendom on political lines, and 
by the creation of a Territorial Church organization, Luther’s 
conception of the Church was obliged to adopt a further element, 
which was quite alien to his own thought, but which became 
logically necessary if the unity and universality of the Church 
were to be retained, that is, the compulsory supremacy of this 
uniform ecclesiastical system. 

The principle of a pure religion based on faith and personal 
conviction alone logically implied the voluntary principle of 
Church membership. And in fact, in his early days as a Reformer, 
Luther spoke out very strongly in favour of liberty of conscience 
and freedom to proclaim the Word by purely spiritual means. He 
had no desire to see the adherents of the “old religion” compelled 
into any kind of conversion by force from outside ; much less did 
he desire to see this policy applied to those who lived under the 
new conditions. The Word was to be left free and untrammelled, 
and to overcome everything by its own spiritual influence. The 
emphasis, however, was laid upon faith in the miraculous power 
of the “pure Word”, which alone contains converting power. “Set 
the Word free”, he seemed to say, “and the human and priestly 
illusion will fade away and disappear.” Thus Luther was not a 
champion of religious toleration ; the cause for which he fought 
was the freedom of the Word to exercise its purely spiritual 
influence without the aid of external compulsion. The religious 
toleration which was possible from the standpoint of the Lutheran 
conception of the Church may be thus expressed: it did not 
consist in a toleration based upon the right of individuals to hold 
varying convictions, because in religious matters it is impossible 
to judge objectively, and compulsion in such matters is futile; it 
was rather the absolute certainty of the sole truth of the Lutheran 
position, or, rather, of the Divine nature of the Word, and of its 
capacity to propagate itself on purely spiritual lines. Here also, 

213 See p. 831. 



492 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

however, the cessation of conflict was only to be a provisional 
arrangement during the^time of ferment and transition ; Luther 
never doubted that the Word would finally triumph, that is, as 
soon as he realized that these conflicts were not the sign of the 
approaching End of the World, but the birth-pangs of a new and 
more settled era. He was, however, obliged to go through the 
experience, common to every faith of this kind, and one which 
the Primitive Church had already undergone — namely, that 
thought and faith alone can never attain an unlimited universal 
dominion by purely spiritual methods, and that restriction to 
these methods indeed endangers the stability both of the univers- 
ality and of the unity of the Church. Thus Luther also was 
obhged to resort to compulsory methods, which, just as in the 
case of the Catholic Church, were not exercised by the Church 
but by the State. The Church was to exercise her functions in 
freedom and in love, and in the face of opposition she was merely 
to warn and exhort. But in order to ensure that all citizens 
should be baptized and come under the control of the Church, 
the custom was introduced of uniting all civil rights with the 
exercise of the Christian religion, and in cases of permanent 
heresy the State intervened with its penalties, since heresy also is 
a breach in the social order. Both institutions, the unity of the 
social and civil order and of the ecclesiastical and spiritual order, 
are, quite naturally, co-terminous, just as they were in the Middle 
Ages. If, however, this agreement does not evolve quite automati- 
cally, it then becomes the duty of the State, at least outwardly, to 
make any sign of permanent opposition impossible . 214 Further, in 
view of the illiteracy and immaturity of the masses, it might seem 
as though it were quite justifiable to compel them to accept truth 
and salvation; even at the present day the State is still in the 
compulsory stage, and in countless ways, by the compulsory 
creation of a certain atmosphere, it forces men for their own good, 
just as every party, every group, and indeed even artistic and 
scientific movements only maintain their spiritual unity by 
compulsory methods of a coarser or more refined kind, whether 
direct or indirect. In the last resort no sociological cohesion can 
possibly exist permanently without some method of compulsion 
This is a feet of life, and all faith in the exclusive power of pure 
thought is an idealistic illusion; it does not belong to the sphere 
of reality. Above all, however, an association which is based upon 
that absolute Truth which alone can “make men wise unto 
salvation ’ 5 (which requires, at the very least, that this truth 

214 See p. 833. 



PROTESTANTISM 


493 


should be made accessible to all, and also needs protection against 
the obstinate undermining of its influence) cannot do without 
such methods of compulsion. On this question Luther completely 
revised his earlier idealism, since, in addition to the claim that 
this truth should be made accessible to all, he also demanded that 
all heresies which disturbed the order of the Christian common- 
weal in general should be removed forcibly by the authorities. 
This demand was aimed primarily at the Anabaptists, with their 
different ideal of Church and State. Finally, however, and quite 
logically, purely doctrinal heresies came under the heading of a 
“disturbance of Christian society”, which, in the interest of the 
Corpus Christianum , it was the duty of the State to suppress. In the 
kind of penalties inflicted, too, the Wittenberger authorities 
became increasingly severe. Exile was followed by imprisonment 
for life, and then even by capital punishment — all these penalties 
were inflicted in the name of the State, after the offenders had 
been duly warned by Christian exhortation. But even the Catholic 
Church did not thirst for blood in this harsh manner ; it allowed 
heretics to be punished by the State as obstinate disturbers of 
the peace and harmony of the Christian Society. Melancthon’s 
attempt to justify these methods shows how much the Reformers 
felt this was a question of the preservation of Christian social 
unity ; he argued that the punishment of heretics is required by 
the Natural Law, the fundamental law of a united society, to 
which the Christian Law is its complement, since the Natural 
Law itself desires the protection of religion. It is obvious that this 
position was entirely opposed to Luther’s earlier point of view ; 
yet it was not an entire denial of his earlier ideals. It was, indeed, 
a logical development from the ideal of a united Church, as soon 
as he realized that the Word could not be established upon 
a purely spiritual propaganda, and a permanent church-order 
became desirable. Luther was not driven to adopt this position 
by the law of the Empire, or by the political situation of the day. 
This point of view developed spontaneously out of the idea of the 
Church as the only organ of salvation which is obliged to protect 
sinners, great and small, from the forces of temptation. It is un- 
deniable that Luther and the jurists of Wittenberg did set up a 
terribly cruel system of compulsion against “Zwinglians^ despisers 
of the sacraments, fanatics and Anabaptists”. They did this not 
simply under the pressure of the ruling princes, whose own interests 
were involved in the unity of the Church, and who were also very 
nervous about the influence of the Anabaptists. No, they adopted 
this policy deliberately, of their own free will, without, however, 



494 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

giving up the theory that the Church ought to exercise her 
influence solely on spiritual lines. It was a form of self-deception 
which is possible to men who believe that they are in possession 
of absolute Truth, and who are therefore honestly convinced that 
it is right to claim from the political authorities toleration for the 
Truth, but no toleration for falsehood. It is not the Church, as 
such, which punishes the rebels, and gets rid of them by violent 
methods, but the ideal created by the Church of the universal 
dominion of the only saving Truth over Society, the absolutist 
objective conception of truth, and the universal idea of Christian 
society supported by it . 215 

The Protestant Ethic and Compromise 

Parallel with the development of this first logical outcome of 
the Church-type is the second result, namely, the steady develop- 
ment of an ethic which accepts the life of the world. 

At first Luther’s ethic had a tendency towards a radical Christ- 
ianity, which was only concerned with “spiritual” matters and 
was aloof from and indifferent to the world. It was only gradually 
that Luther learnt to balance this tendency with the idea of the 
Christian nature of society required by the ecclesiastical concep- 
tion, which always seemed very natural to him, and with the 
natural institutions of the State. Here, too, this development did 
not take place without many violent contradictions, and, just as 
the contradictions in the idea of the Church caused the compli- 
cated character of the Protestant relation between Church and 
State, so the contradictions and tensions contained in the Lutheran 
ethic caused the difficulties in the Protestant social philosophy . 216 

In itself Luther’s Christian piety was a return to the purely 
religious character of the Christian ethic, to which he was led in 
like manner, even though with varieties of emphasis, by the 
mystical doctrine of the supreme and unique value of the love of 
God, by the main Augustinian formula of the Christian ethic of 
the love of all things in God alone and for the sake of God, and 
the Gospel message of Jesus of sanctification of the self for the 
love of God, and of love of the brethren for His sake. As law, the 
moral law disappears entirely, and he again exalts the free pur- 
posive character of ethics, which knows only one absolute aim, 
that of self-surrender to God in faith. Luther then claims that 
out of this supreme end (which alone is valid) the whole Christian 
Ethos with a great variety of motive will evolve quite naturally. 
The fluctuations in these various motives only show that in 
N 6 See p, 833. 8ie See p. 836. 



PROTESTANTISM 


495 


Luther’s mind the attainment of a fundamental religious position 
was the one genuine moral imperative, and that, as soon as the 
central question had been settled, everything else seemed com- 
paratively indifferent and obvious. It is the return to the ethic of 
the Gospel ; the only difference is that its imperative character has 
been transformed by the apostolic doctrine of grace, which means 
that the element of demand is only interpreted as a result and a 
gift of faith, through surrender to the grace which is revealed in 
and guaranteed by Christ. Faith is the highest and the most real 
moral demand, and at the same time it is a gift of grace : this is 
the high paradox and the leading idea of the ethic of Luther. 
Conduct, however, flows from this naturally. From this point of 
view Luther rejects all legal moralism to the point of the danger 
of antinomian consequences. Above all, Luther discards all the 
reconciliations and transitions of the Catholic ethic, which, by 
means of its casuistry, had always managed to connect the natural 
stage of life with the higher stage of asceticism, mysticism, and 
supernature. Luther defines as the heart and centre of Christian 
morality solely that pure inwardness of spirit, of trust in God in 
pain and trial, and that brotherly love which is completely self- 
sacrificing, which renounces all secular rights, the use of power 
and of force, and, indeed, of all right over one’s own property. 
From the very beginning this genuinely Christian ethic had been 
strongly tinged with a kind of mystical spirituality, and to a large 
extent it remained so, in contrast with the purely practical ethic 
of the Gospel, which treats moral behaviour as a means of entering 
into union with God, and estimates it according to its power to 
effect this union . 217 

Over and over again, in countless passages, Luther has ex- 
pressed the characteristic principles of this ethic, which consists 
in aloofness from the world, and in the concentration of 
attention upon the question of personal salvation and of the 
unity of the brethren in the love of God. He also makes it quite 
plain that this ethic of love and salvation is opposed to the ethic 
which is produced by the struggle for existence, with its concern 
with questions relating to law, honour, war, the State, and retribu- 
tion. The Christian is actually only concerned with the life of the 
world on the side of his physical existence, because fois life is 
temporarily involved in the conditions of earthly existence. To 
him the real laws of Christian behaviour are those laid down in 
the Sermon on the Mount: “Resist not evil”. . . . “Love your 
enemies”. . . and all that suggests that evil can be overcome by 

817 See p. 836. 



496 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

love. True Christians have no need of the State, nor do they need 
the protection of the law for their private property. Natural 
opportunities for exercising this faith — which for the sake of 
happiness in God renounces all else and puts itself out freely in 
love — are to be used when they occur, just as the Gospel suggests ; 
there is no need to create special conditions or to induce an 
artificial state for extraordinary sacrifices, as in monasticism. 
But this radical religious ethic, especially in the earlier statements 
of Luther, is entirely remote from the whole sphere of reason, 
might, law, force, to which the Christian only submits because it 
all forms part of this sinful world, and because, as things are in 
this world, it is impossible to render loving service to one’s neigh- 
bour without using these secular institutions . 218 

The deduction of ethical behaviour from the religious element 
is still not very certain ; it was, however, evidently intended, for 
Luther’s faith is a “living, busy, and active thing”. It is more 
difficult to determine in what way from the standpoint of this 
definitely religious general ethic of sentiment the real standard 
of the content of the Christian life was formed, and especially to 
estimate its attitude towards the “this-world” (intramundane) 
values and institutions which are so difficult to adjust to the 
demands of the radical ethic of love. Theologians usually deal 
exhaustively with that first general question of the basis of the 
ethical element in the religious sphere, but they neglect this 
second problem, because even in the Gospel itself they usually 
do not feel that there is any difficulty at all in discovering how it is 
possible to develop a “this-world” morality out of an ethic based 
on the absolute religious values of love to God and love of the 
brethren. In reality, however, it is this fundamental problem of 
Christian ethics which reappears in Luther’s teaching. The 
Catholic compromise of a natural and a supernatural ethic has 
been destroyed, since to Luther a natural ethic, produced by 
human strength alone, would have seemed a complete denial of 
grace, and the limitation of the ethic of grace to the mystical 
higher life which exists alongside of the natural life would have 
seemed a misinterpretation and a narrowing of the Christian 
ethic which ought to influence the whole man. Luther’s ideal 
was the ^restoration of the purely religious ethic, which, at the 
same time, should be applied unceasingly to the whole man. 
Since — whether in the mystical and spiritual sense, or in the spirit 
of the Sermon on the Mount — Luther emphasizes the real Christian 
ethic of the love of God and man in its completely radical sense, 

218 See p. 837. 



PROTESTANTISM 


497 

while at the same time he alters the whole idea of Christian piety 
by transforming the idea of piety as mere membership in a sacra- 
mental institution into one of real complete inwardness of spirit ; 
from this point of view also he seems to come very near to the 
sect-type, and to its radical Christianity of detachment from the 
world ; just as he also emphasizes repeatedly the rarity of true 
Christians and the smallness of the true Church, which he explains 
by saying that the last Judgment and the great apostasy are near 
at hand. In reality, those elements in Luther, which, in the tradi- 
tional view, are often held to be relics of monasticism, are in the 
main, though not entirely, due to evangelical radicalism, for the 
understanding of which it is true that monasticism in certain 
respects is certainly a help. It is also, for the very same reason, 
an approximation to the sect-type . 219 

There is here, however, no real fusion whatever with the sect- 
type. Luther always rejected such ideas very clearly and even 
passionately. But he never systematically and theoretically 
formulated the reasons for this refusal. One of the great funda- 
mental self-evident elements of Luther’s thought, however, lies 
behind this refusal, and in order to discover this our first endeavour 
must be to try to discover the ultimate reason for the form in 
which he shaped his positive ethic. 

The reason which Luther gives most frequently is the definite 
rejection of legalism. In his mind insistence on the necessity for a 
radical Christianity expressing itself in life and behaviour meant 
an emphasis on “works” instead of upon “grace”. He held that 
although the inner spirit of these “works” might be strongly 
emphasized, the real criterion of the state of the Christian would 
still be human achievement. Such an idea, however, is opposed 
to theTundamental idea of grace, which*can only be appropriated 
through faith and trust, by which alone its presence can be recog- 
nized, and not by practical results and practical achievements. 
Although this insistence on freedom and this hostility to all rules 
and regulations, to all levelling tendencies, and to all compulsion 
forms part of Luther’s character and temperament, it does not 
become really intelligible until we see that his basic idea is that of 
grace as the gift of God, which objectively precedes and implies 
everything else, and that this Divine grace is only ohgcured by 
human effort. Thus this stress upon free grace and human 
impotence leads Luther into an emphasis upon spiritual freedom 
and abandonment, which merges almost imperceptibly into a kind 
of Quietism. The active and legal spirit of Calvinism is based 

219 See p. 838. 

D 


VOL. u. 



498 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

upon a different idea of grace and of the Church ; this helps us to 
discern the peculiar nature of Lutheran freedom. Essentially it is 
based upon the fact that the Church possesses the grace of God, 
whicff makes everything else superfluous. It is, of course, true 
that Luther believed that grace ought to bear fruit in a genuine 
Christian piety expressed in daily life, but he taught that Divine 
grace is in no way dependent upon this result, and that in general, 
owing to the sinfulness of mankind, it is only very imperfectly 
realized . 220 

This now brings us to his second main reason. Original sin is 
only overcome by faith in the grace of God and in the forgiveness 
of sins ; again and again, however, it attacks the soul which is in 
a state of grace, but, in spite of this, sin cannot destroy the state of 
grace if the soul abides steadfast in faith. In Luther’s opinion, to 
make radical Christianity the standard of the Christian state of 
grace and of the Christian fellowship would be to dream of a 
perfection which is seldom or never found, even among the finest 
Christians, and which the majority do not even imagine. If we 
must talk of Christian perfection at all, it consists in faith and 
trust, in the acceptance of an individual by God, not in an active 
fulfilment of the Christian ideal. Upon earth this is impossible, 
and it will only be realized in the future life. Thus the Lutheran 
conception of grace and the impossibility of overcoming sin 
render it impossible to draw any external line of demarcation 
between perfect and imperfect Christians; and the bond of 
Christian union does not lie in the realm of practical achievement 
at all, but in the objective possession of grace guaranteed and 
preached by the Church. This ideal persists, even when in actual 
life the Church contains Christians at very different stages of 
experience, as well as souls which fall grievously into sin. Luther 
insists that Christianity consists in this objective possession of 
grace alone, and not in any kind of subjective achievement, 
although to some extent faith should always issue in works. The 
extent to which this takes place, however, affects neither the 
quality of Christian piety nor the fact of personal salvation . 221 

This brings us directly to the third reason. Luther believed that 
any attempt to estimate the “state of grace” in individuals by the 
standard ^of radical Christianity would lead to the making of 
distinctions and divisions among Christians, to self-made agita- 
tions and sects. The result of this would be to break the unity of 
the Body of Christ, which would result in the pride of the 
sectarians and the lovelessness of separation. Imperfection and sin 
880 See p. 839. 881 See p. 840. 



PROTESTANTISM 


499 


within the Church should be overcome rather by mutual instruc- 
tion and love and wise admonitions. This point of view implies 
the unity of the Corpus Christianum — a unity which ought never to 
be deliberately broken, but which should be maintained rather 
by the spirit of love and service. Within this unity of the Body of 
Christ even coarse and open sinners and non-Christians ought to 
be tolerated, at least outwardly (for it is never possible to decide 
quite positively about the real Christianity of any individual), 
and, further, the primitive masses of the people ought to be kept, 
at least outwardly, under the control of the Christian way of life, 
partly as a means of preparatory discipline and education, and 
partly with the aim of repressing — at least outwardly — external 
evil behaviour. Grace must not renounce faith in mankind too 
quickly, but it must gradually permeate a whole people, and 
for the sake of the religious element in the nation, society must 
restrain the activities of open sinners . 222 

At this point, however, a whole host of other reasons appear 
which explain why Luther rejected “sectarian” views. These 
reasons are not directly connected with the idea of grace. As a 
matter of course Luther regarded secular institutions and natural 
possessions as appointed and ordained by God. Nature and the 
life of the senses, a humanity almost entirely dependent upon 
mutual help and organization, government and property, law 
and oath, war and violence — all is willed by God ; therefore this 
social order has its good side ; so far as the rest is concerned it is 
an inevitable state of affairs, and is necessary, owing to the 
presence of sin, as the arena in which the conflict with evil must 
be fought. The Christian, therefore, is not set in the midst of a 
social order controlled solely by the radical Christian ethic of the 
Sermon on the Mount, nor by the mysticism which preaches self- 
denial and detachment from the world. As an individual, of 
course, in questions of personal piety and in the sphere of purely 
personal relationships, the Christian is bound to try to obey this 
higher law. But the Christian also belongs to the secular order of 
Nature and of reason. This natural order has been, in part, 
directly instituted by God, and in part it is indirectly permitted 
to exist by Him. It serves the end of material well-being as well 
as that of repression of evil; the Christian, therefore^ ought to 
submit to it in so far as this does not require him to deny the 
pure doctrine. This means, however, that for fallen humanity the 
Christian ethic is a dualism : on the one hand, it isja pure and 
radical Christian ethic, a personal ethic which is mainly con- 

* aa See p. 840. 



500 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

cerned with the preservation of the Christian spirit and temper ; on 
the other hand, it is “natural 55 — governed by reason — and there- 
fore only relatively Christian, that is, it is an official morality 
appointed and permitted by God. This view of the natural order 
means that the Christian may and should use law and compulsion, 
swear in courts of law, take part in divorce proceedings, strive to 
acquire wealth, property, whenever such action is required by 
his official or social position, or by the demands of the State or of 
the civil order — in fact, whenever it is necessary for any cause 
whatsoever; the individual, however, the “spiritual 55 Christian, 
on the other hand, must ignore everything of that kind ; in utter 
love he must be the servant of all, to the entire exclusion of all 
personal interests. 

In his Sermon on Good Works , and also in the treatise addressed 
To the Christian Nobility of the German Nation , in spite of all his 
mystical spirituality and the radical emphasis upon love in his 
ethic, Luther had no difficulty in immediately outlining a pro- 
gramme of Christian social reform and of a Christian world order, 
in a spirit which accepts the life of the world from a very broad 
point of view. In this programme Luther was thinking mainly of 
external Christendom, of the Christian as a citizen and a member 
of the State, of the Corpus Christianum or the Christian Society, 
within which, however, the only real and spiritual Christianity is 
the Christianity of the individual and of the spirit. To what a 
limited extent, however, these two aspects coincided is revealed 
by the fact that during the early years of experiment and re- 
organization Luther would have liked to see some outward 
institution representing the true Christians who formed the 
smaller groups within the Church . 223 

To some extent there is a familiar ring about these ideas of 
Luther. This is due to their presence in the earlier Christian ethic, 
and the fact that they are here gathered up into one central 
thought, which is regarded as self-evident, is not difficult to under- 
stand when we remember the analogous patristic and mediaeval 
developments. This self-evident idea which is here predominant 
is precisely that conception of the Church which implies that 
Christian piety and holiness do not consist in the subjective 
achievement and activity of individuals, but in the objective 
Divine nature of the wealth of grace which belongs to the institu- 
tion as such. This idea of the Church also contains these further 
elements : the universality of the Church, which includes the most 
varied degrees of the practical realization of the ideal ; its system 

828 See p. 840. 



PROTESTANTISM 


501 

of religious instruction which aims at educating all who have been 
baptized with the aim of full Christian maturity ; its acceptance 
as a logical result of this universality, of secular, political, and social 
institutions, as institutions which have been founded by natural 
Divine Reason as they had to be developed within fallen human- 
ity; this is why these institutions should and must represent a 
relative contrast to the radical ethic of the Sermon on the Mount, 
with which, however, by means of the Decalogue, a final unity is 
attained. 

Since, however, Luther’s arguments are based on fresh assump- 
tions, they naturally carry a different meaning from that of 
analogous statements by Catholic theologians. The objective 
holiness which constitutes the status of the Christian, which 
relieves the individual of the impossible obligation of even 
attempting the full realization of the Christian ideal, is not the 
concrete holiness of the institution, of the priesthood, of the 
sacraments, in which it is possible to participate by entering into 
the ritual of public worship. In the Lutheran view this objective 
holiness consists simply in the Word of the forgiveness of sins, 
which broods above all sin and imperfection as a consoling and 
joy-bringing energy ; the soul can only enter into this state through 
a full personal faith, born of repentance, which alone makes the 
Christian community holy and well-pleasing to God, in spite of 
their sins and their permanent imperfections; it is a purely 
objective treasure, and as such it is absolute, even though it can 
only be appropriated in the spirit of entire surrender. 

The Word of the forgiveness of sins, however, is the super- 
natural agent which creates the Church ; it is the treasure which 
has been established by God ; it constitutes both her essence and 
the treasure which she has to administer; it forms the heart of 
the institution, from which to all who surrender themselves to it 
in faith, in spite of all unequal achievement, there radiates the 
glory of an entirely equal reconciling light which makes everyone 
well-pleasing in the sight of God. 

Characteristics peculiar to 
the Protestant Ethic 

In accordance with this point of view, therefore* Luther’s 
conception of the universality of this ecclesiastical ethic is also 
different. It does not mean an ordered “scale of perfection” with 
its various degrees of holiness, combined with the permission of a 
dualistic morality to various groups within the Church. It implies 
rather that the same ethical claim is made on all the members 



502 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

of the Church, combined with the belief that no one can attain 
an active perfection. It requires “faith” from everyone, and this 
ought to be made possible, or at least accessible, to everyone, 
through baptism and the proclamation of the Gospel in the 
ministry of the Word. But this demand is combined with a tolerant 
recognition of the varied effects of faith, due to the feeling that 
since it is impossible to overcome sin, and since the only thing 
that really matters is faith in the forgiveness of sins, the various 
differences in the exercise of faith really do not matter at all in 
essentials. The Lutheran ecclesiastical ethic does not imply a 
lowering of the Christian ideal; its real significance consists in 
this: that the central importance of practical achievement in 
general is replaced by the supreme decisive power of a personal 
“heart-faith” in the forgiveness of sins. It is no longer a service 
based on “good works”, rendered in an anxious or scrupulous 
spirit, nor a sharing out of “merits” among different classes of 
people; it is not the compensation for the concrete institutional 
holiness by the strenuous endeavour to produce “good works”, 
nor, on the other hand, is it the quantitative grading of the idea 
of perfection, nor does it mean that the ideal is maintained in 
theory while the attempt to realize it in practice is renounced. 
The meaning of this Lutheran ethic is rather that all kinds of 
degrees and stages of Christian development are tolerated for 
their own sake, because ultimately they do not really matter at 
all, since everything that does matter is focused in the grace of 
the forgiveness of sins, and in the blessedness of those who have 
been justified by faith. The universalism of the Church now 
means a system of religious education, which includes everyone 
through the preaching of the Word, and a passive quietistic 
attitude towards the relics of sin, combined with the hope that 
the power which proceeds from grace will of itself ever afresh in 
some measure overcome these sinful tendencies, and that the 
earthly conflict will be followed by a heavenly victory. 

The third characteristic of the Lutheran ethic, therefore — the 
acceptance of the secular institutions of reason — of law, might, 
compulsion, and property — which is connected with that univers- 
ality which tolerates the non-realization of the Christian ideal, 
is also interpreted in a fresh way. It must be admitted, however, 
that in the main Luther here carries forward the Catholic ecclesi- 
astical idea of a Christian unity of civilization as something which 
is absolutely natural and obvious. 

But this acceptance of the natural order is now no longer inter- 
preted in the mediaeval sense, in which the natural order and all 



PROTESTANTISM 


503 


its institutions are placed under the control of the Church, in 
order to serve the purpose of life in the supernatural order. In the 
Lutheran ethic these secular institutions become pure forms and 
presuppositions; in themselves they have no meaning. Luther’s 
view is that these institutions have either been appointed by God 
directly, or by reason, indirectly — that therefore they are implied 
in the creative order of reason and the Divine Law ; it is, therefore, 
the duty of a Christian to accept them just as he accepts sun and 
rain, storm and wind. This situation happens to be that which 
has been definitely appointed as the one within which Christian 
love ought to be exercised, and Christians have no right to leave 
this sphere for self-chosen conditions of life. The right attitude 
towards them, therefore, is not the acceptance of the natural 
order as of a lower stage of development, regulated by the higher 
standpoint of the purpose of the Church and the community, but 
it is that of obedience to conditions of life willed by God, which 
provide natural opportunities for exercising the Christian spirit 
of love. The intramundane political and social ethic has thus been 
changed from a doctrine of relative ethical values which have 
to be subordinated to the supreme aim of Supernature, into a 
doctrine of forms and presuppositions of the Christian way of 
love appointed by God, which lie ready to hand in the ordered 
and law-abiding life of the State, with its guild and class organ- 
izations. These forms can be understood from the natural law of 
morals, and their apparent inconsistency with the Christian ideal 
can be explained by their adaptation to the conditions of fallen 
humanity; the right attitude towards them, however, is not one 
of explanation and ethical acceptance, but of religious obedience 
and humble submission . 224 

(I) Central Position of the Decalogue 
This radical Christian ethic of the love of God, and of that 
love of the brethren which flows from the love of God, was now 
to constitute the ethic both of a national Church and of an 
exclusively Christian Society. If this were to be realized, however, 
the idea that a living faith would spontaneously generate a 
spiritual and moral order was felt to be inadequate. Luther saw 
that a definite moral rule of life must be established, a Christian 
law of ethics, which could be held up to the masses as* an ideal, 
which would also secure the very important factor of the incor- 
poration of secular morality into the whole Christian order. In 
order to do this Luther naturally turned to the Bible, in which it 

224 See p. 843. 



504 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

was quite evident that an expression of that fundamental Christian 
impulse might be found. It is characteristic of Luther that he 
found the objective revelation of the moral law which manifested 
this inward impulse not in the Sermon on the Mount, but in the 
Decalogue, which, again, in his mind, was identified with the 
natural moral consciousness or the Natural Law, which has been 
simply confirmed and interpreted by Jesus and the Apostles. It 
was thus that the Decalogue developed its characteristic abso- 
lute meaning within Protestantism, as the complete expression of 
the Lex Naturae , and of the Protestant ethic with which it was 
identified . 225 

The Decalogue seemed suitable for this purpose, in part 
because its significance within the whole of the previous tradition 
had already developed along those lines ; in part, too, because it 
was most useful in the instruction of catechumens, and also 
because it formed part of revealed religion, and occupied a central 
position in the Old and in the New Testament; above all, how- 
ever, probably Luther seized on it instinctively because it pro- 
vided the opportunity he sought for incorporating “this-world” 
morality and “this- world” institutions into his whole ethical 
scheme. The ethic of a universal Church, and the belief that sin 
could never be overcome, which arose out of the Lutheran 
emphasis upon the forgiveness of sins, could certainly not find its 
watchword in the Sermon on the Mount; the Decalogue alone 
could provide it. The national religious ethic of ancient Israel was 
better suited to this purpose than the radicalism of the message 
of Jesus, which was concerned solely with personal religion, and 
in his later development of ethical theory Luther drew more and 
more widely upon the moral teaching of the Old Testament 
and the moral wisdom of the Jews . 226 

The Decalogue thus became the substance of the Christian 
moral law, and in so doing it also gained a new theological 
meaning. The mediaeval ideal, which contained, on the one hand, 
the Lex Naturae and its Christian expression in the Decalogue, and, 
on the other, the higher theological virtues and the Evangelical 
Counsels, has been abandoned. The Decalogue, combined with 
the Lex Naturae , in its full original sense, is now steeped entirely 
in Christian thought, and is proclaimed as wholly identical with 
the fundamental Gospel law of love to God and man. Luther 
claims that the Decalogue, rightly understood, is the complete 
Christian ethical ideal. This is why he lays so much emphasis 
upon the difference between the First and Second Tables of the 
225 See p. 844. 226 See p. 847. 



PROTESTANTISM 


505 


Law. The First Table, with its commandments which concern 
man’s relationship to God, contains the fundamental demand for 
reverence, love, and trust, which can only be fulfilled on the basis 
of a believing assurance. It requires the right religious attitude, 
the motus spirituales , and it constitutes the purely religious demand. 
This claim, however, leads to the Second Table, with its demand 
that our attitude towards our neighbour should be one which 
expresses love, in a state of life which accepts the natural order as 
something which God has ordained in order to provide a sphere 
in which love can be exercised. This Second Table includes the 
doctrine of the “Calling”, and of the teaching on adjustment to 
existing conditions in the State and in Society, and the idea that 
love is to be exercised not beyond but within the natural order of 
human life. Obedience to the Second Table of the Decalogue, 
however, only has a true ethical value when it issues from the 
spiritual temper of faith, and when it aims at the exercise of a 
living faith towards one’s neighbour, a gathering up of everything 
in this one real supreme value of life. Hence the Decalogue and 
the Natural Law, when they are fully understood, constitute the 
pure Christian and spiritual ideal. Wherever the Decalogue and 
the Natural Law are interpreted apart from these motives and 
aims — as, indeed, pagans have done, and as unregenerate reason 
still does to-day — neither of them has been fully understood. Thus 
pagans, and those who have taught a remnant of the Lex Naturae , 
were really only acquainted with the Second Table of the Law; 
they had forgotten the First Table. Their interpretation of the 
Second Table was well expressed in positive law, especially in 
Roman Law and in philosophical morality. 1 But, in spite of that, 
Luther felt that such an interpretation only became useful when 
it was inspired and vitalized by the right Christian and spiritual 
temper — that is, with the spirit of the First Table, which in the 
Primitive State was also the spirit of the Lex Naturae in its full 
sense. Unless this is borne in mind this ethic is simply cold self- 
righteousness and pagan self-love. Thus the scientific ethic of 
Protestantism may expound the Lex Naturae according to the 
Decalogue and according to Cicero and Aristotle, but it is only 
a vital Christian piety which breathes into these forms that 
inspiring and radiant spirit — maintained in the midst of trial and 
sorrow and temptation — of gratitude and surrender to God which 
is based upon the consolations of grace. 

Thus, within the Protestant confessions, the development of a 
right conception of the Decalogue became*a task of primary and 
fundamental importance. The problem was to formulate a theory 



506 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

in which the inner impulse of faith and the positive revelation of 
the ideal should unite. Theologically, therefore, the chief problem 
was to make a clear distinction between the First and Second 
Tables of the Law, and yet to relate them to each other. This 
involved the necessity for making a clear distinction between the 
absolute Decalogue and the Law of Nature, (as it was in the 
Primitive State and has been renewed by Christ) and the relative 
interpretation of the Decalogue and of the Law of Nature (as it is 
when the First Table is misinterpreted by the pagan philosophical 
ethic, by jurisprudence and the natural conscience). In its absolute 
form in the Primitive State, however, the essence of this moral 
law simply meant the religious consecration of natural conditions 
and natural duties, the permeation of nature with a spiritual 
atmosphere ; indeed, the essence of the doctrine of the Primitive 
State does not consist in the ascent from Nature to Supernature, 
but in the perfection of man as a human being. Thus, in spite of 
the fact that many earlier formulas and theories have been 
retained, the Protestant ethic still forms a new interpretation of 
the patristic and mediaeval equation of the Decalogue and the 
Law of Nature — that is, it is a new conception of the Law of 
Nature itself. This means that the Law of Nature is no longer 
regarded as the radical expression of the idea of personality, 
of equality, of community of property, of a life without compulsion 
or law, but the inspiration of all natural and necessary activity 
with the spirit of faith, since everything which is required by 
Nature (which is itself of Divine appointment) can be combined 
with the spirit of faith, with love to God and man. 

Moreover, from a Natural Law of this kind it is manifestly 
impossible to draw conclusions in favour of equality and com- 
munism, not merely because in its present relative form it is 
modified by the conditions of fallen humanity, but because, in its 
very essence, it cannot produce such results. The observance of 
this Natural Law simply means that the activity required by 
natural circumstances and by Divine appointment is to be 
impregnated with the religious spirit of trust in God and of 
surrender to Him, and also that social behaviour is to be the 
outcome of love, since social usefulness is emphasized for love’s 
sake, and not simply for its utilitarian character. 

(II) Dualism of this Ethic 

At this point, however, the question arises : which conditions 
are the product of Nature? So far as the undefined but painless 
•and harmonious conditions in Paradise were concerned, there is 



PROTESTANTISM 


507 

very little to say in answer to this question. It is obvious that at 
that period both elements agreed with each other, and we do 
not need to pursue this subject any farther. In any case, un- 
bounded love and freedom from compulsion and pain prevailed. 
But that which it was possible to unite under such circumstances 
became, in the course of world-history, separated: the relative 
Natural Law of the state of sin, which expresses itself in the 
State, law, and dominion, was at variance with the religious ethic 
of love, which renounces law, self-assertion, and the effort to 
achieve its own ends. When, however, the Decalogue and the 
Natural Law had been renewed and interpreted by Christ, the 
purely religious aim of life and the purely religious fellowship of 
love emerges as the real Christian ideal, an ideal which concerns 
the inner life of the individual, along with the secular ethic of 
professional life, the State, and Society, to which man belongs 
either officially, or through being incorporated into the order of 
Society and the State, with its marks of law and compulsion. 

This is the difficult aspect of the Lutheran ethic. The patristic 
and Thomist doctrine had been able to explain its dualistic 
morality by interpreting the Law of Nature as an institution 
which served both as the penalty and the remedy for sin ; upon 
this basis of fallen humanity it then constructed the peculiarly 
Christian order as a higher form of fellowship. When, however, 
Luther took over this Catholic theory, he felt that it did not really 
harmonize with his fundamental point of view ; for, although he 
was prepared to admit that the natural order may have lost its 
spiritual content through the Fall, he felt that actual opposition 
between the two was impossible. Either there is no room for the 
transformation of the Natural Law of Paradise into a largely 
contradictory Natural Law of fallen humanity (and therefore for 
the essential contrast between the Natural Law of Paradise and 
the Natural Law of the present day) ; if so, then the present 
Natural Law, and the political and social order which corresponds 
to it, must be present in it or be transferred to it in a form which 
is really in conformity with Christian thought. Or, the Natural 
Law of Paradise has actually been transformed into an empirical 
Natural Law which is strongly opposed to it ; if this is so, then its 
institutions are not simply forms and presuppositions which can 
be expanded by the Christian spirit and the spiritual love of God. 
If the latter is the case, this gives rise to a very definite and clear 
contradiction in thought. Since, then, Luther adopts this latter 
point of view between his ideal of Natural Law and the Deca- 
logue, or between his fundamental conception of the Christian 



508 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

moral law and his really dualistic instructions to Christians 
which decree an inward morality for the individual and an 
external “official 55 morality, there exists an extremely painful 
inconsistency. At this point in Luther’s doctrine there breaks out 
once again the tension which is essential in every Christian 
ethic — the tension between the Christian ethic and the world 
and Nature which he had removed in his ideal of the Law. 

This contradiction which Catholicism had turned into a 
contrast between two stages — between the lower stage of develop- 
ment of relative Natural Law and the genuinely Christian higher 
stage of development — has here been transferred to the individual 
as the contrast between “person 55 and “office 55 . Since, like the 
Catholic theologians, Luther maintained the idea of grace and 
of universality, and could not possibly have adopted the sectarian 
attitude of world-denial, his ethic was also obliged to incorporate 
into its theory the contrast between secular morality and the 
morality of grace. The solution was provided, not as in the 
mediaeval Church by apportioning responsibility among various 
classes and groups, for mutual supplementation and vicarious 
service, but by placing each individual in the midst of a dualistic 
ethic ; this dualism is then explained as due in part to the ordering 
and arrangement of God, in part to sin, and in part to the actual 
conditions of physical existence. 

As time went on, however, Luther modified this dualism a good 
deal. Just as in his conception of the Church the earlier subjec- 
tivity of his view gave place to the idea of the objectivity of the 
institution, so also, and in close connection with this change of 
view, in the sphere of ethics the opposition between a personal 
and an official ethic, between the Sermon on the Mount and 
Natural Law, was increasingly modified. More and more he came 
to regard secular institutions as mere forms of life, which are due 
less to the relative tendency of sin than to the positive institution 
and appointment of God, and the general assumptions arising 
out of Natural Law . 227 Finally, the Protestant ethic finds it once 
more possible to use the ethics of Aristotle, Cicero, and the Stoics, 
and the ancient Humanistic ideas of politics, economics, and 
social doctrine. These ideas provide material which, lacking the 
religious motive, in themselves do not yet constitute an ethic at 
all ; as the results of Natural Law, however, they only need to 
be penetrated by the religious principle which was originally 
contained in the Natural Law, in order to become a Christian 
ethic. More and more the contrast between a Christianity of 

227 See p. 847. 



PROTESTANTISM 


509 

disposition and the secular official morality disappears; and the 
sense of tension and contrast gives place to an attempt to construct 
a synthesis. Existing conditions, which are permanent either 
because they are founded on reason or appointed by God, become 
more and more the normal condition, and the Christian ethic 
becomes, as modern Lutherans say increasingly, “the truth of 
the natural order”, the work of Redemption consists more and 
more in the “glorification of the natural order created by God, 
and not in a species of destruction of that which God has 
created” ; 228 also, one might add, not merely in a patient endurance 
of the natural order, but in a humble and obedient acceptance of 
it. “Nature”, that is, the political and social order which has been 
evolved by the Law of Nature, is conceived as a stable order of 
Society, existing for one purpose, which is required by reason in the 
sense of the territorial state ; and the religious sentiment regards 
it less and less as an opposition to the radical ethic of love, but 
rather as an institution which has been founded and decreed by 
God, and which therefore has to be obeyed. In place of the earlier 
and more spiritual point of view, in which Luther formulated the 
purpose of life from the point of view of the absolute religious end, 
and of the opposition to the world to which that gave rise, Luther 
insisted more and more upon the necessity for obedience to 
positive authority. As faith was replaced by dogma, so, instead of 
the justitia spirituals of the individual which was opposed to the 
relative Natural Law of the “official” ethic, he emphasized 
obedience to the ordinances of God and to the world conditions 
which He has appointed. The relative order of reason, tainted 
by sin, becomes the authoritative, entirely positive order of 
reality, to which, without thinking very much about it, the 
Christian has to adapt himself. This is how the problem of the 
inconsistency of the Lutheran ethic has been overcome . 229 The 
radical ethic of love disappears, and the ethic of obedience 
towards authority comes into prominence. Increasingly the 
Lutheran ethic is summed up in the following characteristic 
features: confidence in God founded on His grace, and love of 
one’s neighbour which is exercised in the social duties of one’s 

228 Cf. Luthardt: Kompendium 10, Thieme IV; most decisively in Uhlhorn: Kath. 
u. Prot.,p. 2Q: “With that the dualism of the present and the future life, of the 
natural and the supernatural, of Christian and worldly, of the perfect Christian 
and the average Christian, has been overcome. Science, trade, and commerce 
gain once more their free movement. Therefore Uhlhorn thinks that Protestantism 
will be able to solve the social question” for which Catholicism is inwardly 
incapable and only externally concerned. 

229 See p. 848. 



5 io THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

calling, combined with an obedient surrender to the order of 
Society created by the Law of Nature. 

Thus the deep inner tensions of the Christian ethic, which had 
always appeared whenever a fresh attempt was made to shape 
the life of the world according to the Christian standard, were 
also retained in the ethical theory of the Reformation. This 
ethic also is a compromise, a dualistic morality, above all 
in the fundamental conception of Luther. Only the incon- 
sistencies are not distributed among various grades, but are 
interwoven in such a way that they form a dualistic attitude 
towards life in each individual. The compromise has become a 
more interior thing, and in the process it has become increasingly 
modified, since the world is accepted not so much as a sinful 
institution or as an order which, through sin, has obscured the 
light of reason, but as a direct and positive appointment by God. 
The happy and docile humility which accepts the grace of the 
forgiveness of sins increasingly resembles the humility which 
accepts the conditions appointed by God; the converse is also 
true ; therefore on both sides the religious attitude becomes similar. 
The thread of pure idealism, however, constantly reappears. For 
as soon as the ideal of the Sermon on the Mount reveals the deep 
cleavage between existing conditions and the genuine Christian 
ideal, and as soon as the existing social and political order fails 
to harmonize with the Church and the Word of God, a spirit of 
violent anger breaks out against the world of sin and of the Devil — 
the Last Judgment becomes a desirable end of all things, and the 
! Christian life seems essentially to be a life “under the Cross” and 
; the hope of a blessed life beyond death. Joyful acceptance of the 
1 world then becomes patient endurance of the world, and Luther- 
j anism, in particular, oscillates between these two extremes. 

( From another point of view, however, the same problem 
4 reappears. If the spiritualizing of the Decalogue is taken seriously, 
if all that is done in the earthly secular sphere is really regarded 
purely from the standpoint of the love of God and as an obvious 
duty, and if it is precisely in the presence of this motive that the 
Christian nature of morality is seen, then secular institutions sink 
to the level of merely concrete conditions; they become forms 
which are in themselves valueless, within which it is the Christian’s 
duty to live as though the world did not exist at all. The reduction 
of the world to mere form and presupposition is just as' much an 
acceptance of the world on the one hand as it is a depreciation of 
it on the other. The outlook on the world, however, then becomes 

880 See p. 849, 



PROTESTANTISM 


5*1 

ascetic, in the sense that men believe that secular institutions and 
values possess no independent purpose of their own, nor an inner 
Divine element. They become purely positive institutions and 
facts, which only proceed from the Will of God, not from inner 
necessity. They become entirely formal and hollow, and the 
endurance of them becomes an act of p ure obedience and patience. 
Within this sphere, however, the world is not accepted, but it is 
regarded as a matter of indifference and overcome. Here, there- 
fore, asceticism, as depreciation of the world, is no longer (as in 
Catholicism) merely connected with individual achievements, 
but it permeates the whole fabric of life and its activity, leaving 
behind nothing save the expectation of the much desired Last 
Day, which will set the soul free from those conditions of life 
which have never quite squared with the Christian ideal, most of 
which are still wholly perverted by sin. The one thing that is 
forbidden, however, is the effort to free oneself from these condi- 
tions, as is done in monasticism. Instead, the spirit of world- 
renunciation is to be carried into the natural course of daily life 
within the world itself. This view also contains some expressions 
of a real love to the world and to Nature (which, indeed, in them- 
selves are good and have only been spoilt by sin), and now and 
again the whole ethic can even appear as a religious glorification 
and penetration of Nature. This only means, however, that the 
deep inner inconsistency, the deep inner tension, which lies in 
the whole problem, still remains ; it shows that the compromise 
undertaken by Catholicism has only been removed to a different 
plane ; it has sunk deeper into the inward depths of life, but it is 
still a compromise. It is the compromise (required by practical 
life, inevitable in the universality of Christian fellowship, made 
possible by the transferring of holiness from the activity of the 
individual into the objective ecclesiastical possession of grace) be- 
tween a purely religious ethic and the claims of the life of the world. 

INTROSPECT AND "FORECAST 

If we summarize all these considerations, and look back at the 
presentation of our subject in the Middle Ages and in the Early 
Church, we can then say: Protestantism carries forward the 
acceptance of the life of the world into the ethic of a universal 
Christian Society, which had been dimly foreshadowed in late 
antiquity, but which was only really attained in the Middle 
Ages, and it intensifies this principle to the highest possible 
degree. Since Protestantism is a renewal of the primitive Christian 
religious spirit, its greatest difficulty arose, primarily, at this 



512 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

point. In the endeavour to deal with this problem through the 
formation of small communities within external Christendom, 
and in the distinction it draws between the personal spiritual 
ethic and secular official morality, it approaches the sect-type, 
which also in reality springs out of Protestantism at this point. 

Since, however, on the other hand, Protestantism maintains the 
ideal of a pure institution of grace which comprehends the whole 
of Society, and the unity of the Christian Society, it rejects the 
sect-type as the tendency towards legalism and loveless division. 
This rejection of the sect-type led Protestantism to an ever- 
increasing recognition of the life of the world and of the morality 
of the world. Just as in Thomism the contrast between the relative 
Lex Naturae and the ethic of grace gradually disappeared, till it 
became a lower stage in the ethic of grace, so here the Lex Naturae 
becomes increasingly a mere form, which the Christian spirit 
inspires with the glow of religious love and energy, making it the 
presupposition of its activity. In close connection with the develop- 
ment of the Church as the organ of grace into a unity of life 
dominating the State and Society as a whole, ethics also are 
developed into a Christian inspiration of life, into the “classes 
and callings” ordained by God, and therefore holy, which, 
further, are given with the Natural Law, and to a great extent, in 
the Old Testament, have been directly appointed or confirmed 
by God, and have not been rescinded by the New Testament. 
The idea of Grace as the perfection and superstructure of Nature 
may be due to Catholic influence, but the permeation of the 
existing forms of life with the spirit of faith and love is a Protestant 
conception. While Catholicism distributes the ethical claim among 
various classes of people, Protestantism demands the same moral 
standard from all alike. While Catholicism asserts the possibility 
of attaining absolute holiness, and therefore maintains special 
groups for the cultivation of the higher Christian piety, Protestant- 
ism proclaims the impossibility of overcoming sin for all alike, 
and gives to all as a common spring of morals the believing 
disposition, which can be preserved, even despite the outward 
conditions of life, granted that complete holiness is impossible to 
attain. Protestantism usually claims that in relation to the problem 
of “Christianity and Civilization”, which Catholicism and thesects 
in their own way have both solved along the lines of asceticism 
and legalism (in Catholicism by reorganizing" and secularizing the 
life of the world, in the sects by the rejection of the world and 
therefore as a definite rigid asceticism, and in both instances as 
law), it has maintained the inwardness of Christianity freed from 



PROTESTANTISM 


5i3 


all legalism, and that it has thus made it possible for the life of 
the world to be freely penetrated with the Christian spirit. 
Compared with the solution provided by Catholicism and the 
sects this is only, to a very limited extent, a new solution of the 
problem. The principle of pure spiritual freedom, which Protes- 
tantism certainly did restore, is still in its content a principle which 
is closely connected with the Bible, and in this respect it comes 
very near to the ethic of the sect-type, with its general rejection 
of law, might, the State, force, and self-interest ; while the extension 
of this spirit by means of a Church, as the organ of redemption, 
controlling a united Christian Society, approximates very closely 
to the ethic of the Catholic Church-type. The Protestant solution 
of the difficulty in the dualistic ethic of a “personal” and an 
“official” kind is no solution; it is simply a new formulation of 
the problem, and even in Protestantism the problem has some- 
times been made superficial by reducing it to the legalism of a 
secular and Christian ethic deduced simply from the authority of 
the Bible. This development has sometimes taken place not only 
in Calvinism, but also in Lutheranism ; it has only been empha- 
sized more strongly in Calvinism because that denomination 
generally lays greater stress on the ethical organization of the 
Church . 2303 

These similarities and differences between Protestantism and 
mediaeval Catholicism produced, therefore, on both sides similari- 
ties and differences in their social philosophy. 

Protestant social philosophy carried forward the patristic and 
Catholic intellectual point of view based on Natural Law with 
its close relation to the Christian ideal, but it gave to the relation- 
ship and the constitution of both a new meaning. Since, however, 
the tension between both these elements had only changed its 
position, it also reappears, in an altered form, in the social 
philosophy of Protestantism. From this point of view also the 
same process is repeated with reference to the sect-type. The 
similarity between Protestantism and the sect-type lies in the 
emphasis upon the Christian demand as a strict and equal demand 
upon all men, and thus on Christian individualism. Protestantism, 
however, always deduces this individualism solely from the 
influence of the Church as the organ of redeeming grace, and in 
this way it places the individual in connection with the general 
cultural life by which it is surrounded. Hence, in spite of its indi- 
vidualism, the social teaching of Protestantism is much nearer to 
Catholic social doctrine than to that of the sect-type. 

* 30a See p. 849. 

£ 


VOL. II. 



514 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

At this point at last we have before us the presuppositions which 
are necessary for the understanding of Protestant social philosophy. 
From this point of view we can clearly distinguish the essential 
difference between it and Catholic social philosophy, as well as 
its attitude towards Christian radicalism, which, as a complemen- 
tary movement, was produced just as much by Protestantism as 
it was by Catholicism. 

In the following sections, therefore, I shall present the social 
philosophy of Lutheranism which has developed, fairly logically, 
out of these basic ideas. I shall then present a study of the social 
philosophy of Calvinism, which introduced considerable modifi- 
cations into the common stock of the intellectual heritage. The 
first point to be considered in connection with both confessions 
will be the conception of the Church, and the way in which it 
secured the universality and dominion of the Church. The next 
point will be the ecclesiastical ethic, and the way in which secular 
culture and secular-social values were incorporated into this 
ecclesiastical ethic. Since in thus gathering the whole of life under 
the dominion of the idea of the Church there is implied, con- 
sciously or unconsciously, the ideal of a sociological fundamental 
theory which embraces all these formations, we shall deal further 
with the sociological fundamental theory which was dominant at 
that time. Only upon this basis will it then be possible to answer 
the last question about the particular forms adopted by the main 
social phenomena in the Family, the State, and Society. 

Confessional Lutheranism and Calvinism, however, were not 
the only products of the Lutheran movement. Alongside of these 
movements which belonged to the Church-type there arose out 
of them other movements which burst through the Church-type 
and, more or less logically, developed the sect-type. From this 
type there extends a whole unbroken chain of complementary 
movements, extending from the Anabaptists and all “spiritual 
reformers” to the Independents, Pietists, and the modern sects. 
These complementary movements, as has been shown several 
times already, were a logical development of Luther’s world of 
thought, as soon as its presupposition — the idea of the Church — 
was broken through; Luther himself, in his “group” ideal and in 
the radical mysticism of his ethical ideas, in spite of the fact that 
inwardly he was far from the sect-type, came very near to the 
ideals of these movements; indeed, he only missed them by a 
hair’s breadth. Only in the light of the contrast which these move- 
ments present can we fully understand ecclesiastical Protestantism. 

Further, since these movements broke away from the main body 



PROTESTANTISM 


5i5 


which supported the Reformation, they have had an amazingly 
strong reflex action upon orthodox Protestantism. The effect on 
Lutheranism was manifest: as it watched the development of 
these sect-movements it realized the danger of subjectivism, and 
it reacted violently in the direction of objectivity. Calvinism was 
influenced by these movements in the sense that it accepted to a 
great extent their ideal of holiness, and in so doing ultimately 
made a breach in its national and State Church system. Apart 
from their influence upon the two leading Protestant confessions, 
these movements are of universal significance in world-history, 
since in their various ramifications they produced results which 
led to and fostered religious subjectivism in general, separation 
between Church and State, the independence of local congrega- 
tions, and finally of the individual, thus bringing a whole host of 
religious motives into the subjectivism of the Enlightenment. 
Thus in the last section we shall still have to deal with the sect- 
type within the sphere of Protestantism. 


2. LUTHERANISM 

The Ecclesiastical Organization of Lutheranism 

The whole social fabric of Lutheranism — that is, of those 
ecclesiastical and cultural organizations which were the direct 
logical result of Lutheran ideas — was erected upon the basis of 
the thought of Luther’s later period, the period, that is, when he 
had deliberately decided in favour of the Territorial Church 
system. This Lutheran system, however, did not spread very far 
beyond its original home; its chief expansion took place in the 
German territorial States, in Scandinavia, and in the Baltic 
States. On the Western frontier of Germany it lost large sections 
to Calvinism. In France, England, Holland, and Scotland it 
succumbed before more active and progressive ecclesiastical 
movements of a very different kind. In the South and East its 
progress was checked by the Counter-Reformation within the 
Roman Church, which fused Thomism and the Renaissance in 
a new combination ; the result was, that for some time to come, 
in many respects the Roman Church once more became superior 
to Lutheranism in the social and cultural sphere. 

Lutheranism was based entirely upon the idea of an ecclesias- 
tical civilization, forcibly dominated by religious ideas. This was 
actually the case, in spite of the fact that in theory the Lutheran 
system regarded the civil and the spiritual authority as entirely 



516 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

independent of each other, and in spite of the fact that the 
Catholic supremacy of an international, hierarchical Church, 
enforced by directly ecclesiastical methods, had been discarded. 
Thus the conception of a State Church still remains the centre 
of the social doctrines of Lutheranism, and all social developments 
which take place outside the religious sphere are estimated from 
the point of view of the result of their incorporation into the ideal 
of a social order composed of a unified State penetrated by the 
Church with the ultimate aims of religion. In Lutheranism this 
idea was not simply part of its religious and ethical ideal ; it was 
essential to its very existence. Lutheranism realized that it could 
not stand alone; it was like some frail sapling which needed the 
robust support of a Christian State or a Christian Society if its 
pure spirituality were ever to bear good fruit. 

The centre of the whole system, therefore, was the specifically 
Lutheran conception of the Church, and in this matter the 
theoretical religious and dogmatic view of the Church, from its 
own standpoint, was of fundamental importance . 231 

This conception contains two main elements which control the 
Lutheran view as a whole : ( i ) The idea of the Church has been 
greatly spiritualized ; this was Luther’s intention, and in the main 
the Lutheran theologians maintained this point of view during 
the classic period of orthodox Lutheranism. (2) This entirely 
spiritualized Church, which does not desire any human organ of 
compulsion for the enforcement of the pure doctrine, and which 
neither is able nor desires to carry out its work of Church discipline 
by any external method of compulsion which can be legally 
formulated, is, in spite of that, based entirely and wholly upon 
the idea of a fixed and rigid system of doctrine to which all 
consent, which alone has the power, in its purity and exclusive- 
ness, to secure redemption from sin and from hell. This means 
that, in spite of her spiritual character, and in spite of her renuncia- 
tion of the methods of law and compulsion as natural rights, the 
Church is still obliged to submit unconditionally to the external 
life of the political sphere which she dominates. Inconsistencies of 
this kind had existed within every previous theory of the Christian 
Church, but the tension which they caused never became so 
acute as in Lutheranism, and their mutual hostility has had a 
paralysing effect upon the whole course of Lutheran development. 

The idealistic aspect of this conception of the Church, which 
introduces an entirely new element into the history of the Christian 
idea of the Church, thus becomes manifest. The Word of God as 

* S1 Sec p. 850. 



PROTESTANTISM 


5i7 


the herald of the pure doctrine of that grace which forgives sins 
and renews men’s souls brings everything to pass purely in its 
own strength, by virtue of its inward miraculous power in assur- 
ance of faith. The inward witness of experience proves its unique 
Divine inspiration, which to an increasing extent is expanded 
until it covers the whole content of Scripture, even including the 
literal translation of the text and questions of punctuation. The 
Scriptures, therefore, are the sole absolute authority, the standard 
by which the Church is guided, in which Christ Himself is at 
work, and alongside of which there is no need for any human 
tradition, infallible ministry, priesthood, or hierarchy. The Bible 
is its own interpreter, since it illuminates obscure passages by the 
standard of those which are clear, and through the power of 
the indwelling Holy Spirit it effects an entirely uniform objective 
creed ; these norms, which the Bible itself has created by its own 
method of interpretation, are fixed in the Creeds. 

The Word, or the Christ who is active in and through the Word, 
completes the work of the sermon and the sacraments; the 
ordained minister is only the channel of the Word, and through 
the pure doctrine it is Christ Himself who speaks, preaches, and 
judges in him. The Word, or Christ in the Word, imparts faith, 
love, and obedience, by means of which all submit to the truth of 
the Scriptures, listen willingly to the preachers, who by spiritual 
gifts and training for their calling have been fitted to proclaim 
the Word; the faithful also willingly endure the chastisement of 
the Church. Thus through the Scriptures Christ rules the Church ; 
in Him resides the supreme redeeming power; it is He who 
operates in the sacraments, who controls the exercise of ecclesias- 
tical jurisdiction, who is the formative, controlling decisive 
authority in the Church ; He achieves purely by His own spiritual 
influence all that the Papacy, the priesthood, and the hierarchy, 
Roman law and Roman compulsion, had achieved by external 
human methods. The government, the supreme court of appeal, 
and the executive power do not lie within the hands of the faithful 
as a community of believers, since this community is indeed only 
a product of the Scriptures and of the “pure doctrine” ; neither 
does this power reside in the clergy, who are only the appointed 
channels through which the Scriptures operate along their own 
lines ; nor does it reside in the Prince, who is only a servant of 
the sanctuary, and who only places his services at the disposal 
of the self-propagation of the Word. No ; this authority is centred 
solely in the Church of the Word itself, built up upon the miracle 
of Scripture, whose miraculous powers only need to be given 



518 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

a free course in order to allow this Church of the Word and 
Christ Himself finally to produce all the results required. If 
from the Catholic point of view the Papacy is the extension of 
the Incarnation of Christ, the living authority in doctrine and 
in jurisdiction, in Lutheranism the same thought is represented 
by the Word, through which, as in a living being capable of 
action, Christ Himself is directly operative . 232 

In practice, of course, it was impossible to carry out this 
extremely “spiritual” conception of the Church, with its miracu- 
lous faith which staked everything on the power of the Word. 
In reality, this idea of the uniform influence of the Word, over- 
coming all difficulties and bringing order out of chaos, stood in 
dire need of human support. The uniform interpretation of Scrip- 
ture did not come about naturally; it had to be enforced from 
above. The institution of ministers in an orderly way did not 
come about spontaneously, neither through an outpouring of 
charismatic gifts nor through the voluntary exercise of love and 
willing submission to a charismatic ministry; a definite church- 
order had to be created in order to call ministers and to give them 
official recognition. Excommunication could not be carried out 
by expecting defaulters to submit to the jurisdiction of the Church 
of their own free will, but it needed the help of the State and the 
imposition of civil penalties for spiritual transgressions. 

In addition, the whole ecclesiastical organization needed to 
be regulated on the financial, administrative, and mechanical 
side, and the purely spiritual form of Church government through 
the Word made no provision for this side of the life of the Church 
at all, nor for the fact that the Church was involved in questions 
of civil rights and the marriage law. Not only did the purely 
“spiritual” Church of the Word possess no organ by which this 
business could be transacted; more important still was the fact 
that it possessed no inward, inevitable Divinely authorized system 
of regulation. Thus the Church was obliged to hand these matters 
over to other courts, since it regarded them as purely external 
and mechanical, of purely human interest, trusting that these 
courts, led by the Divine Spirit, would settle these questions as 
wisely as they could from a purely human point of view. Thus it 
came about that it was only the ruling Prince — the political 
authority — who, in any case, was occupied with matters of 
organization and administration through his official position, 
and who, as the most important member of the Church, as the 
membrum praecipuum , had the duty of rendering this service to the 

131 See p. 851. 



PROTESTANTISM 519 

Church. To that, of course, there were added arguments based 
on Natural Law. The Government protects the Natural Law 
(which is regarded as identical with the Decalogue), and as a 
Christian Government it has to maintain this Natural Law in 
its full sense, since it also includes the First Table, which requires 
the true worship and the pure fear of God. Thus as custos utriusque 
tabulae it is also bound by Natural Law to support public worship, 
the pure doctrine, and the ecclesiastical jurisdiction . 233 

Thus it came to pass — at first as far as possible in the spirit 
which Luther intended — that the purely spiritual church-order 
was supplemented by a purely secular order of law and 
authority, which, by means of the compulsory secular methods 
of the brachium saeculare is able to exercise that authority which 
the Church, as a purely spiritual institution of love and freedom, 
neither can nor desires to procure by coercion. A legal compulsory 
church-system has been established. But the element of compul- 
sion is not exercised by the Church, but — in accordance with its 
inferior status — by the State. The fact that all this takes place in 
the civil sphere, and under the aegis of the secular authority, saves 
appearances for the Church as a spiritual body which is con- 
trolled by love; actually, however, the effect is the same, for in 
the majority of cases the secular power only acts upon information 
and suggestions given by the spiritual authority through the 
pastors . 234 In practice the whole procedure was very cumbrous. 
Thus, although it meant a departure from the pure Lutheran 
theory, in order to simplify matters it was ultimately found 
necessary to create the consistories, which were ecclesiastical 
organs of government, ordered by the ruling Prince, which, with 
the co-operation of ministers and lawyers, governed the Church 
directly and forcibly, and which could directly decree and 
impose fines, imprisonment, and corporal punishment, who thus 
in the Church and for the Church introduced a system of govern- 
ment based on penalties and compulsion in order to uphold 
purity of doctrine and Christian behaviour . 236 

Thus that very element which from the theoretical and religious 
point of view was regarded merely as a human insignificant 
side-issue within the fabric of a Church, which was essentially 
based upon supernatural powers, became in practice, as we can 
well understand, the main issue. 

The ruling Princes created doctrinal uniformity, and imposed 

*** For the theory of the membrum praecipuum ( Sohm , pp. 553-573) is excellent 
and clear; for the custodia utriusque tabulae , Sohm , pp. 549-553 
m Sec p.851. ' See p.851. 



520 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

the Symbolical books upon the Protestant (Lutheran) Church 
by force. 

They created State Church councils which undertook the work 
of administration and of Church courts with the aid of the pastors. 
They placed questions of Christian faith and morals under 
secular control, and spiritual procedure and penalties were 
followed by civil legal consequences. In theory, the Church was 
ruled by Christ and by the Word ; in practice it was governed 
by the ruling Princes and the pastors. At the outset, however, 
this whole system of church-order was something quite human, 
fluctuating and casual. But when its importance for the whole 
development of the Church became apparent, to some extent at 
least, even if only indirectly, the system itself came to be regarded 
as of Divine appointment. It even came to be linked up with the 
system of doctrine, for as the proclamation of the Word required 
an organized ministry, and this ministry was appointed by God 
Himself in Christ, an organized official ministry became necessary 
from the doctrinal standpoint. For even when a man who has the 
requisite spiritual gifts makes the decision to enter the ministry 
on the strength of an inward Divine “call”, he cannot obey this 
call outwardly unless an official ministry instituted by God does 
exist, a ministry which is carried on in an ordered succession. 
Thus even in Protestantism there remains a jus divinum , even 
though it be only a poor apology for the real thing : that is, the 
necessity for an official ministry is recognized, together with the 
further implication that a man who is called to the ministry 
should receive his official appointment in an ordered way. This 
inevitably involves a church-order jure divino , so far as the exist- 
ence of the ministry in general and a regular procedure for 
induction to office is concerned. The way in which this is to be 
carried out is merely a matter of convenience. It is de jure divino 
that at least there should be a church law regulating this point 
at all. The secular law itself, which arises out of the church law, 
is a purely human institution. The fact is Divine, the method 
human. Further, the sanctity of the church-order only extends 
to the appointment to the ministry of the Word, but it does not 
affect the other technical duties which form part of the system 
of church administration. Indirectly, however, this element of 
consecration of the fundamental element in church-order — the 
office of the ministry — was sufficient to impart the sense of a 
Divine mission and a Divine authority to those who exercised 
the right of appointment to the ministry, that is, to the civil 
authority ; inevitably this meant that the rest of the church-order 



PROTESTANTISM 


521 

which was administered by the State shone in the reflected glory 
of this Divine authority, which gave the whole system the stability 
which it urgently required. 

Thus after the tree of the supernatural church-order had been 
cut down, the stump which was left put forth branches in the 
shape of a system of church-order which was, at least indirectly, 
of Divine appointment, and which entrusted the government of 
the Church, or rather the official representation of the pure truth 
of Scripture, to the clergy and the ruling Prince. 

Thus the aim which was realized in Catholicism through a 
directly Divine church-order, Lutheranism, in its purely spiritual- 
ized form, stripped of every kind of hierarchical or sacerdotal 
organ, realized through the government and the civil administra- 
tion, to which, however, precisely for that reason, there accrues 
a certain semi-divinity. 

The distinction between the temporal and the spiritual elements 
in this system is not a separation, but only a fresh aspect of their 
relationship ; the State now serves the purely spiritual Church in 
a spirit of love and freedom, and by this service it dominates the 
Church which has no independent legal organ of its own. Rivalry 
between Church and State is excluded, theoretically, by the 
assumption that in both there is at work the truth of Scripture 
which unites both in the Faith; and practically by the weakness 
of the Church, which depends entirely upon the State, and also 
by the fact that the State incorporates religious motives and 
tasks into the purpose of its own life . 236 I can only mention in 
passing that it is a well-known fact that this fresh orientation of 
the relation between Church and State, in its secondary aspect, 
had already been foreshadowed in the Territorial Church system 
of the later Middle Ages. We need, therefore, to realize that the 
Lutheran ecclesiastical system was not simply the acceptance of 
a tradition which was essentially foreign to its own nature, but 
that from its own point of view — with its spiritual conception of 
the Church, and its decided rejection of a church-order based on 
the Divine right of the congregation to settle its own affairs (like 
that which Calvinism evolved later on)— it was simply impossible 
to pursue any other course. 

Unifying Influence of 

the State Church Conception 

This complicated State Church social order was, however, in 
spite of its artificial construction, a social whole. In this connec- 
286 See p, 852. 



522 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

tion the important point is that this system included the whole 
sphere of Church and State, that the interests of Church and 
State had become interwoven with each other, and that both the 
ecclesiastical and the political authorities had combined to form 
a harmonious conception of a Christian society. 

It is, of course, clear that within this society the true Church 
— that is, the fellowship of those who have been truly “born 
again” through the Word — includes only the vitally religious 
section of the population. This is the Ecclesia stride dicta , to use 
the term of the theologians. But between it and the Ecclesia late 
dicta , that is, the total number of those in any given region who 
belong to the Church, upon whom, through the compulsory 
religion of a State Church, the Church has set her seal in baptism, 
and who, at least outwardly, must be constrained to listen to the 
pure Word, to maintain the Christian way of life, and to respect 
Christian doctrine , 237 there only exists a difference, but no 
division. This agreement between the Church and the Christian 
Society is expressed still more clearly in the Lutheran doctrine 
of classes, which continues the mediaeval organization of the 
population into sacerdotes , domini saeculares , and vulgares , as the 
division into a Status ecclesiasticus politicus and oeconomicus , and defines 
these three classes explicitly as ranks of the Church, or as hier- 
archies . 238 

This classification, which was far too rough and ready, even 
for the simple conditions in Germany at that time, was, however, 
very important from the practical point of view. For, as in the 
mediaeval civilization, it means the distinction between a Church 
in the real sense of the word and one which is not a real 
Church : 2384 by the real Church is meant only the institution of 
the proclamation of the “pure Word”, visibly expressed in the 
clergy and the authorities in Church and State; by the Church 
in the second aspect is meant the Christian Society — in the whole 
range of the sphere of Church and State, in the totality of their 
activity and social groups. 

This is simply the mediaeval idea of the Corpus Christianum , 
within which, in the modern sense of the word, there is, as yet, 
no separation between Church and State, between sacred and 
secular. The civil authority and the ecclesiastical authority are 
two different aspects of the one undivided Christian Society, 
for which reason the Government and the State have directly 
Christian aims, and the Church includes the whole of Society. 

All that has been discarded is the Roman system of social 
1,7 See p. 852. 181 See p. 853. tWa See above, p. 283. 



PROTESTANTISM 


5«3 


grades within the range of a small independent State, and the 
idea of a Universal Church which has the right to intervene 
forcibly in all matters of human concern. This order of things has 
been replaced by one in which, within any particular State, 
there is a voluntary agreement between the Christian government 
and the Church which consecrates all the work of the world, in 
which the civil authority serves the Church through its adminis- 
tration, while the Church hallows all “labour in a calling”, in 
the State, in the administration of justice, in Society, and in 
domestic life, as the service of God and one’s neighbour. In 
theory the purpose of the whole remains religious, only the 
relationship between the two authorities, whose business it is 
particularly to realize this purpose, has become a different one, 
through their mutual co-operation . 239 

Now, however, this conception of the Church and the harmony 
between the Church, the State, and the social order, which is 
expressed in the Corpus Christianum, combine to form the final 
assumption upon which the social philosophy of Lutheranism 
is based: the whole social fabric is enclosed within the frame- 
work of the Church, and is related to the religious purpose of 
Society. The only question is: how and in what sense is this 
relationship effected? The answer to this question will become 
plain as we try to realize clearly the leading characteristics of 
the Lutheran ethic. 239a 

The Lutheran Ethic 

The Lutheran ethic is of dual origin. Just as Church and State 
exist side by side within Society, so here also we have the ethic 
of love and grace on the one hand and the ethic of law and reason 
on the other. The fundamental idea of this dualism is due to 
Luther, and it here only modifies the mediaeval dualism in ethics. 
Melancthon carried this dualistic tendency a step farther in the 
dualism of a philosophical and theological morality, and ortho- 
doxy has only broadened both these currents of thought, which 
have branched off still farther in various directions. In so doing, 
however, it was only the philosophical side which was scientifically 
developed ; the theological side of the question remained bound 
up with dogma. It is only in practical life that we see both ten- 
dencies combined and mutually influencing one another. This 
combination is regarded as something quite natural and obvious, 
which is carried out in practice without further reflection. 
Ultimately, indeed, this is true of all the previous Christian ethic. 
1,1 Sec p, 854. am See p. 854. 



524 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Even the first scientific ethical development on a larger scale 
which was embodied in Thomism was in reality only systematic 
in so far as it followed in the steps of Aristotle and made the 
Christian virtues square with those laid down by Aristotle. Even 
Thomism did not dream of presenting ethical problems in their 
widest range and in their ultimate conceptual origins. Thus, 
since the Christian ethic in general is rather a practically useful 
Ethos with individual points which have been developed into 
theories, so also the ethic of Protestantism, and, above all, the 
ethic of Luther, is not a theory which is in any way comparable 
with its dogmatic system. Ethical theory only comes into being 
when — as at one period in late antiquity, and also at the time 
of the Enlightenment — the natural ethical foundations of life 
have been destroyed . 2395 

The Christianity of the Middle Ages and of the confessional 
period had a scientific theory of its own doctrines, and from the 
estimate of life based upon this metaphysic it drew the main 
impulse of its ethic. So long as that was dominant, the ethical 
results followed as a matter of course. All that needed to be 
worked out in further detail were points like the following: the 
relation between the moral element or “good works”, and grace 
in general, the relation between Christian morality and secular 
institutions and the morality which is not based upon the ethical 
results of grace, or with the traditions of the ancient “philo- 
sophical” morality, which regulated the relations between law 
and freedom, between the Christian morality of life and the 
impossibility of overcoming sin. Everything else was settled, 
naturally, by life itself. 

Thus the real Lutheran ethic of the sixteenth and seventeenth 
centuries has to be sought out and reconstructed by the modern 
scholar, sought, that is, in the sphere of ordinary human life and 
in fragmentary theoretical statements, and this ethic will be 
discovered not merely in theological dogmatic statements, but in 
the theories of jurists and political economists as well . 240 

So far as Lutheranism is concerned this is a comparatively 
easy matter. The Lutheran ethic consists primarily in the estab- 
lishment of a religious relation with God, in that love to God 
which humbly, joyfully, and thankfully surrenders the self to Him 

S 3 »b This is why it is so mistaken to try to save the honour of early Protestantism 
by attempting to discover in it “theological moral philosophers’*. The people 
of that day neither desired nor needed any ethic alongside of dogma ; this only 
became necessary after the upheaval of the Enlightenment. 

840 See p. 855. 



PROTESTANTISM 


525 


in prayer and self-discipline, and the outpouring of this love of 
God, which cannot give anything to God, upon one’s neighbour. 
It is an inward impulse which uses to its fullest extent the over- 
flowing happiness produced by justification, making it a means 
of leading one’s neighbour to God and of uniting him with 
oneself in God. 

Since however, as a rule, the Lutheran considered that fulfilling 
your “duty to your neighbour” meant the wise use of all the 
obvious opportunities, stimuli, and forms of the natural life, with 
the avoidance of all unbalanced mysticism and all special cliques, 
this means, then, in the second place, that “loving one’s neighbour 
as oneself” implies that all the duties and tasks which life brings 
naturally in its train, especially those connected with the family, 
the State, the labour and vocational organization, are to be filled 
with this spirit of love, which makes these forms into methods 
and means of expression of the Christian love of mankind. The 
mysticism which centres in love to God and man pours itself into 
the existing forms of human life : into the life of class and guild, 
into family and domestic life, into the life of the State and the 
administration of justice. Sublime religious feeling is clothed in 
the garb of the most ordinary and everyday forms of service 
within the home and the ordinary duties of citizenship. Down to 
the present day the ethical teachers of Lutheranism only differ 
from each other in this — that some would give more scope for the 
independent development of the specifically religious and mystical 
ethic, while others would exhaust its significance entirely in 
loving service to the brethren in an ordered society as “the great 
workshop of the love of one’s neighbour”. In the former there 
is still a trace of the original tension which Luther set between 
the sacred and the secular, between love and law, while with 
thinkers of the latter kind there predominates Luther’s demand 
for obedience towards all natural ordinances which the God who 
is concealed in history had Himself created, and in which there- 
fore He desires to see the believing soul exercising love and 
happiness in simple obedience. 

The ideal of such a way of life is reflected in the conception of 
the Christian Moral Law, which here appears not so much as the 
law which effects conversion, but as the interpretation and the 
description of the impulse towards activity which is set alongside 
of the bliss of justification by faith, for which therefore the legal 
form has only an unreal significance. The Lutheran theory of 
Christian freedom from the Law is still maintained, but in 
practice this theory changes into a purely Protestant legalism based 



526 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

on the Catechism. This Law is contained in the Decalogue, which 
in the usual way is regarded as exactly the same as the Natural 
Moral Law. The Decalogue is thus held to include all the stimuli, 
opportunities, assumptions, and social forms of Natural Law 
under the Second Table, and at the same time, in its First Table, 
it includes the inspiration of the whole with the Christian spirit 
of faith and love. This distinction between the two Tables of the 
Law means that the dualistic ethic was still maintained. But since 
believers are urged constantly not to allow brotherly love to 
peter out in vague and indefinite sentiment, or in special cliques 
and sentimental emotionalism, the purely interior, spiritual 
ethic which utterly renounces all use of law and force, finds, in 
actual practice, very little scope ; as swiftly as possible it is trans- 
ferred into the ordered sphere where love is expressed in dis- 
charging the duties of one’s vocation, in civil life, in a healthy 
division of labour, and in loyal obedience. This is the channel into 
which, so far as possible, the currents of purely personal and 
human relations are guided, in the interests of law and order. 
Further, domestic and civil authority is to some extent hallowed 
by the fact that it has been appointed by God, and this sense of 
consecration almost effaces the stain which clings to it as part of 
the sphere of law and conflict. Thus, alongside of the ethical 
labour involved in the effort to attain interior union with God, 
which culminates in communion with Christ in the Sacrament, 
for which the soul has been prepared by repentance and self- 
examination, there is only the ethic of the service of the State 
and of the “calling” which is consecrated by Divine appointment. 
The fact that this ethic lays a great deal of emphasis upon order, 
stability, and peace entirely obliterates in theory, and also modi- 
fies in practice, the fact of its connection with the severity of the 
law and the unrest caused by the struggle for existence . 241 

We do not need to deal any farther with the question of this 
“morality of the disposition” (Gesinnungsmoral ) , which was to 
breathe its spirit into the secular forms of life. This has been done 
by the early theologians in their treatises on dogmatics or on 
practical asceticism. They do not call this Christian ethic an 
“ethic” at all but Pietas y and treat it in this sense in Scholae 
pietatis, or similar practically edifying treatises, which indeed also 
include the whole thorny apparatus of the dogmatic doctrine of 
justification by faith. It is only the modem Lutherans who have 

141 Cf. the tractate De lege in Gerhards Loci comunes (ed. Cotta ) , V and VI. Here 
also there is a detailed explanation of the Decalogue which contains a great 
deal of ethical material. 



PROTESTANTISM 


527 

transformed this subject into an independent “theological” ethic, 
into which they have also incorporated the absolutely necessary 
component parts of the “natural” ethic. Men felt the need, 
however, for a detailed presentation of the whole subject, giving 
a minute and exact analysis of all the natural virtues, social 
duties, opportunities, and obligations which were to be hallowed, 
Christianized, and filled with the new outlook on life. This alone 
was the real “ethic”, as early Lutheranism saw it. This “ethic”, 
however, was simply the Aristotelian scholastic ethic, revived by 
the Stoics and by Cicero, and renewed by the Humanists, which 
in its scholastic form had been re-edited by Melancthon (whose 
work was destined to influence thought for two hundred years 
to come), while at the same time it also made use of the Jesuit 
Neo-Scholasticism which had dealt with the same material in 
a more detailed way. The stock of ideas which constituted the 
intellectual capital of the “ethic” of both confessions was exactly 
the same; that is, if we only use the term “ethic” in its contem- 
porary meaning of the philosophical ethic; this “ethic”, in fact, 
was simply a purified mediaeval Aristotelianism, or the familiar 
range of ideas connected with Aristotle’s interpretation of Natural 
Law. Since the Natural Law is only Divinely proclaimed and 
summarized in the Decalogue, this “philosophical ethic” also 
could be developed upon the basis of the Decalogue without any 
loss of its purely philosophical and natural character. 2413 This 
ethic dealt with the conception of the Natural Moral Law, 
Natural Right, the Aristotelian conception of virtue, the four 
cardinal virtues — all on thoroughly traditional lines. Its aim was 
to show how knowledge of this kind was useful in the following 
ways: (1) it was a preparation for repentance; (2) as justitia 
civilis , i.e. as a loyal external discipline emptied of all spiritual 
content, it helped to preserve order; (3) it provided the basis of 
reason for the idea of the existence of God and of the moral 
government of the world ; and (4) finally, when this knowledge 
was inspired with a spiritual temper, it merged into the unity 
of the Christian idea of love. 

The other aspects of social life which really belong to the 
sphere of Natural Law — the Family, the State, division of labour, 
and economics — were only superficially touched by this ethic, and 
they were really worked out in the special forms of discipline 
which were constructed upon the basis of the Law of Nature 

* ua Modern writers and critics who do not know the origin or the significance 
of this group of ideas usually complain about the “still” confused mingling 
of philosophical and theological ethics. 



5*8 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

and of Positive Law — that is, in jurisprudence, the doctrine of the 
State, and political economy, and in the sections of dogmatics 
which had borrowed from them. Roman law, in particular, 
seemed to be a development both of the Decalogue and of the 
Law of Nature ; every time these materials were used, however, 
their connection with the positive law, in use at the time, also 
had to be considered. 

The resemblance to the Catholic ethic is obvious. In both 
instances the Ethos of real life is only constructed with the addi- 
tional aid of the range of ideas centring in Natural Law and of 
the ethical material of ancient philosophy. An ecclesiastical 
ethic which also covers the whole field of secular civilization still 
makes use of this complementary method, upon which the 
Early Church had already drawn for the same purpose, and 
which the Mediaeval Church had developed very fully along 
scholastic lines. In this question of dealing with a secular civiliza- 
tion which the Church had to accept and assimilate, Protestantism 
continued the fundamental tendencies of the Catholic tradition; 
just as she had done in the conception of the Church itself. At 
the same time the difference between Lutheranism and Catholi- 
cism in this respect is clear : Protestantism has no hierarchy which 
can legally and forcibly regulate the harmonious development 
and relation between the different stages; in the ethical sphere 
interpenetration has taken the place of an orderly succession of 
ascending stages. According to the new conceptions of Protestant- 
ism the supernatural is now immanent in the natural sphere ; this 
immanence, however, must not be understood in the sense of 
modern doctrines of Divine Immanence — it does not mean the 
Immanence of God in the world — but it is the Immanence of 
the Love of God which overcomes the world, in obedience to 
secular institutions — indifferent and sinfully corrupt in them- 
selves, but positively appointed by the Will of God — and the 
Immanence of love in the religious sense, present in all activity 
which conduces to material welfare and order, an activity which 
is the natural method appointed by God for the manifestation of 
love to humanity. The meaning and purpose of it all is not 
material progress, but the exercise of the obedience of faith 
(which renounces all caprice and self-will), and of humble and 
grateful love. 

Lutheranism and the Law of Nature 
We cannot, however, fully appreciate either the similarity or 
the difference between Catholicism and Lutheranism in this 



PROTESTANTISM 


529 


respect until we have made a special study of one point in which 
Lutheranism differs from the Catholic and from the Calvinistic 
ethic alike; (on this point, indeed, the Calvinistic ethic is finally 
and essentially in agreement with the Catholic ethic). This 
question is the peculiar Lutheran conception of the Law of 
Nature, which exists within the rational idea of Natural Law 
common to both confessions. 

In this question Luther struck out on a peculiar line of his 
own ^ 42 At first, it is true, he shared the traditional point of view 
with which we are already familiar, which indeed did not form 
part of the province of theology, but of reason and practical 
philosophy; in rejecting Roman theology and the Canon Law 
Luther did not need to reject the rest of the tradition as well. 
All he did was to separate the mediation elements from the rest, 
making a clear distinction between them and the Scriptural 
ethic of love; he restricted the former elements to the “official” 
sphere, the ordinary “calling”, to law and to the State, requiring 
that all should adapt themselves to the forms of life thus condi- 
tioned which are so harshly opposed to the ethic of love. In so 
doing, however, Luther had not merely re-ordered the relation 
of the Natural Law to the Church and the Gospel, but he had 
reinterpreted the Natural Law itself. From the very outset he 
explains the Law of Nature in an entirely conservative sense, 
which emphasizes solely the utilitarian expediency of the concrete 
order, in which the shaping of Society itself seems to have been 
produced by Providence in the natural development of history, 
and all order and welfare depend upon unconditional obedience 
towards the authorities which have come into being in the course 
of the historical process. This interpretation glorifies power for 
its own sake, which in fallen humanity has become the essence 
of law ; it therefore glorifies whatever authority may happen to 
be dominant at any given time. Even when this power is most 
scandalously abused its authority still holds good, and every act 
of resistance to this authority destroys the very conception of the 
social order based on Natural Law, and thus destroys the 
foundation of Society in general . 243 

In Luther’s innate conservatism, in his pietistic indifference 
towards external things from the Christian point of view, in his 
belief in an omnipresent Providence which moves and works 
behind human thought, in the comparison between social sub- 
ordination and the religious humility of absolute dependence 
upon the Grace of God — above all, in his deep sense of the opposi- 
842 See p. 856. 248 See p. 856. 

vol. n. p 



530 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

tion between the order of love and the order of law and the 
universal struggle for existence : in all these ways Luther instinc- 
tively regards Natural Law as the establishment of an unrestricted 
positive authority, effected by God through reason; no amount 
of experience of a refractory reality can shake him out of the 
belief that this authority is based upon reason and the Divine Will. 
This is why he opposes every attempt to reconstruct Society and 
mould it on rational lines, which is based on the interests and the 
reason of the isolated individual ; this is why he refuses to consider 
or permit any individual co-operation at all in the endeavour to 
build up a satisfying “organic" system which will include them 
all. In his theory, therefore, the idea of a social contract naturally 
disappears ; in it there is no room for the transference of power 
based on the explicit or implicit consent of those who are governed, 
nor for any “right of resistance 9 9 or revolution which extends 
farther than frank criticism, nor for any equalitarian conception 
of social human relationships, nor for any communistic ideal . 244 
This was already excluded from the Primitive State ; that glorifica- 
tion of power was already present in the nature of pure unclouded 
Reason; even in Paradise this meant authority and reverence 
within the family, and submission to circumstances and duties 
given by God. Sin has merely vastly increased the significance of 
that power, since the preservation of order is only possible if 
positive authority is maintained, which, however, has further been 
linked up with evil and selfishness. But even when this (evil and 
selfishness) has been admitted, the fact remains that authority 
must not be resisted. Non-resistance is, therefore, not primarily a 
demand of the Gospel, but a requirement of Natural Law, since 
according to this theory no one is fit to judge his own affairs, and 
every power which permits resistance destroys its own being, as 
Luther reiterated unceasingly when the peasants made their 
demands for reform. When, at a later date, a “right of resistance 99 
for the estates of the Empire was asserted, Luther rightly expressed 
the opinion that this demand did not accord with their conception 
of authority over the peasants. 244a 

At this point the course of mediaeval thought had displayed 
a good deal of uncertainty. The problem was this : if the Stoic- 
Rationalist ideas which had become an integral part both of 
Imperial and of Canon Law were logically developed, they led 
to the idea of a social contract, to the doctrine of the right of 

244 Ehrhardtypp. 309 and 310. Unfortunately E.’s work is very far from exhaustive. 
244a Cf. von Schubert : Beitr.zur ev. Bekenntnis- und Bundnisbildung , 1520-39 (?• /• 
Kirch. -Gesch.> XXX, p. 295). 



PROTESTANTISM 


53 * 

revolution and of tyrannicide, to the rational development of the 
State in accordance with the rights of the individual. If, on the 
other hand, Aristotle was taken as the guide, this led to the doc- 
trine that Society arose organically and inevitably out of Reason ; 
this meant that all that was natural and necessary was ascribed 
to Providence, in which the only right course was submission to 
the natural process which was directed by God, in which sinful 
extremes alone were to be avoided. 

If, however, it was felt that this Divine element in authority 
needed further support, emphasis was then laid on the Divine 
appointment of authority and on the mythological glorification 
of power — on the founding of States by means of the Babylonian 
confusion of tongues, on the Divine nature of the legislation in 
the Old Testament. When, however, on further reflection, men 
realized that all the institutions of fallen humanity were only 
relatively Divine, there arose the ideal of the Primitive State, with 
its equality, brotherly love, and community of possessions. The 
mediaeval doctrine of Natural Law moved uncertainly among 
these ideas, making various efforts to weld them into a coherent 
system . 245 

Within this confusion Luther had now created a stable order, 
even though it was very one-sided, and not always logically 
maintained. He achieved this by doing away with the Stoic and 
Rationalist elements entirely, regarding the natural development 
of actual authority as an institution of Providence to be revered 
unconditionally, teaching that this natural development was 
authenticated by Divine appointment and confirmation in the 
Old Testament; thus Luther came to teach a conservative 
authoritarian conception of the Law of Nature, which deduced 
from the conception of authority and its utility for human welfare 
the demand for an unconditional respect for authority as such. 
The fact that this authority has to use methods of severity and 
compulsion, law and dominion, is due to fallen humanity, and 
serves to keep sin in check. This point of view was combined with 
an attitude of contempt for the masses, amongst whom he thought 
it rare to find, not merely true Christians, but even wise and 
reasonable men. In fallen humanity the masses need to be guided 
and controlled ; to Luther, however, it seems probable that he felt 

145 These different elements are well put together in K. Kohler: Staatslehre der 
Vorreformatoren (Jahrbb.f. deutsche Theol., XIX ) : “The inconsistency of the latter 
(organic Aristotelian) view with the theory of a social contract which finally 
depends upon the arbitrary will of humanity does not seem to have entered 
So-and-so’s head” (p . 555). 



532 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

this to be essentially the need of humanity as such. For this 
development of authority is due precisely to reason. Luther, 
therefore, believes that peace and order, a slow process of organic 
development from the existing situation, is a better method of 
inducing prosperity and progress than a violent break with the 
old order and a fresh beginning. Since within the Christian sphere 
the Spirit has to work gradually from within outwards, reason 
ought to work thus within the natural sphere. All along Luther 
is opposed to revolutionary schemes which are based on an indi- 
vidualistic point of view, and he is in favour of an authority which 
controls, conditions, and gradually moulds them, even in case 
of necessity achieving its end by force. In this glorification of 
authority there were certain resemblances to the doctrine of 
Machiavelli, which the early Lutherans had already noted . 246 
The only difference was this : Luther lays the duty of the preserva- 
tion of the law of reason upon the ruling powers, and binds this 
in a Christian society to free obedience to the Gospel. Even at the 
present time the followers of Darwin, despotic politicians, and 
masterful men get on better with Lutheran conservatives than 
with the representatives of Liberal ethical individualism. The 
main features of the conservative doctrine of the State and of 
Society have been foreshadowed in Luther’s theory, and the 
“Christian world outlook” of our Conservatives in its most 
important political and social sections is based upon Luther’s 
positivist and realistic conception of Natural Law . 247 

Under the influence of the negotiations which led to the 
Schmalkaldic League it is true that Luther broke through this 
doctrine and asserted the “right of resistance”, not merely upon 
the ground of the Positive Law of the Empire, but also upon the 
ground of Natural Law. This, however, was clearly due to foreign 
influence, above all to the influence of Hesse and Strassburg, and 
a large number of his followers rejected his conclusions, using his 
very words to support their case. In the struggle between the 
citizens of Magdeburg and Charles V the theories about the 
“right of resistance” revived, but they speedily disappeared. In 
reality, they did not harmonize either with Luther’s opinions or 
with his logic. He manifested his own view of Natural Law in the 
declaration that the Greeks and the Romans did not know the 
true Natural Law, but that the Persians, the Tatars, and people 
of that kind 247a observed the Natural Law far better. 

846 See p. 857. 247 See p. 858. 

84 7a Cf. Cardauns, pp. 8-19. The passage about the Persians in Ob KriegsletUe , 
etc,, B,A., IV, 1, pp, 998-402, Unfortunately, Cardauns * treatment is not 



PROTESTANTISM 


533 

Although at this point Luther’s views had diverged far from 
Catholic Natural Law, in other important features, such as the 
mingling of morality and law, in the comparison of Natural Law 
with Christian morality, and with the emphasis to which that 
gives rise upon reasonableness and equity, which modifies formal 
law in favour of ethical judgment, he remained true to it. This 
modification, of course, does not apply to the law of the State, 
nor to the laws of punishment ; this, however, will have become 
clear in the preceding pages. Within the law of the State Luther’s 
rigid idea of Original Sin and his demand for severe discipline, 
his contempt for the masses, and his conception of the civil 
authority as the representative of Divine punishment and reward, 
inclined him to extreme severity, and he was urgent in recom- 
mending the exercise of penalties like breaking on the wheel, 
decapitation, and torture . 248 

Within the sphere of civil law, however, Luther desired to see 
the Natural Law administered with a leniency which takes all 
the various factors of motive, necessity, and circumstance into 
account. In his view the guiding principle of the Natural Law is 
that we should do to everyone as we would like them to do to us. 
In this respect love is also the meaning of Natural Law, and is 
thus conformed to Christian morality. This leads him to demand 
that Positive Law should adjust itself to Natural Law and to the 
Christian ideal, with which, in the last resort, it is identical . 249 
While in all questions of authority and control, of dominion and 
of subordination, his conception of Natural Law is a naturalistic 
recognition of the dominant authority and of prevailing distinc- 
tions, with an aristocratic emphasis upon the gulf which separates 

exhaustive. How fluctuating opinions were is shown by von Schubert: Beitr . 
Z . /. K.-G., XXX, pp. 271-316. The Natural Law of rational defence, the 
Natural Law of pure authority as it was worked out against the peasants, 
the Positive Law of the Empire, of an only conditional supremacy of the 
Emperor, and the Divine law of mere suffering and endurance, are here 
all mingled ; see MelancthorCs verdict, p. 313. 

248 Cf. the basing of the first great and independent working out of the law 
of punishment upon these Lutheran ideas by Ben. Carpzov in Stintzing: Geschichte 
der deutschen Rechtswissenschaft, II, 1684 , pp. 70-80. The great part which trial 
for witchcraft plays in this law of punishment goes back likewise to Luther’s 
faith in demons, for he could only explain to himself the evil of the world and 
its resistance to the Gospel from the working of the Devil. Luther, however, 
always fought against the fantastic eccentricities of the faith in witchcraft ; 
v. Kawerau in W. W., Berliner Ausgabe, IV, 1 , pp. 44 ff. 

249 On this point v. Kohler in the section Das Verhdltnis zum kanonischen Recht, 
pp. JU-132. Here the identity with the mediaeval point of view is rightly 
emphasized. For epikie or aequitdt,pp . 46 and 98. 



534 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

the rulers and the ruled, on the other hand, in all questions of 
personal behaviour and of merely civil conflict, his conception of 
Natural Law was one of reasonable equity, which was opposed 
to a strictly legal formalism ; it was, in fact, an attempt to reduce 
law, as far as possible, to the principles of human consideration 
for the suffering and the oppressed, and the deliberate ending of 
conflict. In this respect also the conservative theory of Society 
follows Luther even at the present day; in all human relation- 
ships which do not affect the problem of authority and domination 
it urges a policy of goodwill and justice, freed from the rigid 
formalism of law. This theory is averse to surrounding the indi- 
vidual with abstract legal guarantees, because this is the spirit 
of the individualistic-rational principle in general, but it likes to 
replace law by Christian consideration on patriarchal lines and 
personal fair dealing. In the sphere of authority Natural Law is 
compared with the Christian idea of authority, in the sphere of 
private property with the Christian idea of love. The harshness 
of the doctrine of authority is compensated by a Christian softening 
of the standpoint of law in private relations. This is the early 
Lutheran doctrine, and to-day it is still the conservative con- 
ception of law , 260 and in reality the Christian nature of morality 
is expressed more clearly in this than in the public law of 
authority; here also, however, it is a Christian piety strongly 
tinged with patriarchalism, which distinguishes it very clearly 
from the virile individualism and the corresponding legal con- 
sciousness of Calvinism. 

Since, however, Luther’s idea of Natural Law is that of the 
Divine activity expressed in reason, he loves to emphasize God 
as the Founder of these institutions, and wherever it is possible he 
tries to find proofs of their direct Divine appointment. 

When, however, he takes that line his assertions cease to have 
any element of Natural Law at all, and the mythical element 
predominates. Thus he asserts that the Family is an institution 
of Natural Law, but he also asserts that it was expressly instituted 
by God. Indirectly the State was instituted at the same time as 
the Family; but its Divine origin was also often confirmed in the 
Old Testament. The economic organization and labour were 
held to be due to the Divine Command at the expulsion of Adam 
and Eve from the Garden of Eden. In detail, too, he often sup- 
ports his statement by Old Testament examples; indeed, it often 
seems as though he had entirely forgotten his former insistence 
on the freedom of the Christian from the Jewish law, for he uses 

See p. 858 . 



PROTESTANTISM 


535 

the Old Testament as though it were a legal code. When he is 
confronted with problems connected with marriage and the 
question of serfdom he refers to the Mosaic Law, and his fatal 
appeal to the bigamy of the Old Testament in the case of the 
Landgrave of Hesse is well known. 

In all this, however, Luther still only considered the Mosaic 
Law to be identical with reason; he regarded it as the Divine 
confirmation or proclamation of reasonable rules and regulations, 
but not as the revealed Law of God. This leads, of course, to the 
production of a curious mingling of arguments drawn from the 
Bible and from the Law of Nature ; this mixture of arguments, 
however, only proves (and this is of fundamental importance 
for our inquiry) that the assumption of an inward unity and 
conformity of Natural Law with the Christian spirit is the under- 
lying idea; upon this alone the relative uniformity of early 
Lutheran culture is based, and to-day it still forms the basis of 
the Christian piety of the conservative section of the population, 
which includes some very un-Christian elements . 261 

While Luther thus often concealed his idea of Natural Law 
behind positive Scriptural statements, and further, when he was 
opposed by the jurists who naturally had to preserve the continuity 
of technical law, with much use of strong language again with- 
drew to the position which emphasized the contrast between law 
and Christian freedom, these ideas were trimmed and shaped 
and moulded into smoothness by Melancthon . 252 He was the 
Protestant doctor of Natural Law; further, his scheme was 
adopted by jurisprudence as a whole. Melancthon laid greater 
emphasis upon the philosophical character of Natural Law, and 
he strove so hard for reconciliation that the Lutheran tension 
between the Law and Christianity, between Reason and Revela- 
tion, was ultimately merged in the idea of a friendly harmony 
which has been Divinely ordained. From that time forward 
faith in this harmony, and the ideal of such an accord between 
natural assumptions and spiritual inspiration, became a peculiar 
feature of Lutheranism. In his ethical works and juridical 
speeches Melancthon expounded the conceptions of Natural Law 
with which we are familiar, in the classic formulas of Cicero, 
with some additional material drawn from Aristotle, upon whose 
Politks he also wrote a commentary. He explains the Natural 
Law according to Cicero in the light of the Decalogue, which he 
considers identical with it. This identification of the two enables 
him to introduce the religious elements which the pagans had 
151 Sec p. 859. 151 See p. 859. 



536 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

lost. The result of this is a conception of the State and of a legal 
right to inflict penalties, which is based upon the idea of reason 
as the support of discipline and of education against sin, as well 
as of the protection of order and the common weal. This theory 
also led to a conception of civil law which recognized in Roman 
Law the positive legal development of the Natural Law, which 
is identical with the Natural Law of the Decalogue and makes 
the Roman Law the objective legal standard for the jurists of 
the future in exactly the same way as the Bible is the objective 
standard for the theologians. 

Melancthon claims that the Decalogue is valid, not as the 
Jewish Law, but as the product of Natural Law, and, therefore, 
that the reasonable Roman Law is also the law for Christians, 
and not, as the Sectarians say, the Mosaic Law. To this written 
law he also relates the Aristotelian doctrine of the dominion of 
law in the State. Here also the Gospel is united with reason. At 
the same time the Natural Law leads to the organization of 
Society in classes and callings as well as to private property, 
which was indeed at first held to belong to the relative Natural 
Law of the fallen State ; now, however, it must be urged all the 
more decidedly that it is a Divine institution. 

All this shows that Melancthon was inclined to be more 
rationalistic than Luther. This accounts for the reappearance of 
the old rationalistic ideas of the consent of those who are governed 
to the ruling authority. At the same time, however, Melancthon 
argues that the State owes its authority to a Mandatum Dei , which 
was already in existence in Paradise when the authority of the 
family was instituted ; at this point, therefore, he enters into entire 
agreement with the Lutheran authoritative Law of Nature with 
its emphasis on compulsion and order. Melancthon lays still 
greater stress upon this idea by making the formal stringency of 
the existing legal administration far more binding, while he 
makes far less use of the idea of equity than Luther. 

On the other hand, Melancthon asserts the “right of resistance” 
far more broadly than Luther; this he does, however, only by 
appealing to the positive Roman Law, in which the Emperor 
declares that he desires to exercise his power with the consent of 
his subjects, and by an appeal to the German Law of the Empire, 
in which the liberty of a privileged class is justified in resisting an 
Emperor who breaks his contract with his subjects. Finally, 
against the worst injustices he recognizes the right to resist also 
as de jure naturae , and Luther accepted this reluctantly enough, 
commending the problem to the jurists and to reason. This, 



PROTESTANTISM 


537 

however, had very little effect upon the Lutheran interpretation 
of Natural Law. On the whole, Luther’s influence was the stronger 
of the two, and both in dogma and also in Natural Law Melanc- 
thon’s peculiarities disappeared. Although the Humanist admirer 
of Aristotle preferred the aristocratic city-republics to the absolu- 
tism which tended towards “Tyrannis”, with the decline of the 
cities these ideas also naturally disappeared from the political 
theory of Lutheranism. In reality Luther’s conception of authority 
was more suited to absolutism, and his dislike of the “Sakra- 
mentierer”* was equally a dislike of the republics of Upper 
Germany . 2623 

The whole system of later jurisprudence developed within the 
framework constructed by Melancthon, the only difference being 
that in matters affecting the legal administration of the State 
the conservative authoritative aspect was emphasized still more 
strongly, although the formulae of a tacit consent of the citizens 
to the ruling power were still reluctantly retained . 253 It was only 
in the seventeenth century that an actual constitutional law and 
a detailed political theory were really formulated ; until then the 
material was divided amongst dogmatics, philosophical ethics, 
interpretation of the politics of Aristotle, and the exposition of 
suitable passages in the Roman law, and it reproduced only the 
familiar ideas, with increasing emphasis on the Divine appoint- 
ment of the ruling authority, which corresponded to the increasing 
absolutism ; this also took place in the theories of the State evolved 
by Catholic and Anglican absolutism. The more exclusive con- 
stitutional law of the seventeenth century then turned towards 
the empirical law material. Thus, in principle, the conception of 
Luther and Melancthon remained, of the reference of the State 
equally to reason and to Divine appointment; and within the 
territorial State itself Bodin’s new theory of sovereignty was 
combined with the earlier doctrine of a humble and trustful 
surrender to the authority appointed by God. This meant that 
the elements of Natural Law in the theory were thrust more into 
the background, and were finally reduced to the bare statement 
of the Divine guidance of reason in the production of political 
authority. The more the school of Grotius developed a purely 
rational theory of Natural Law, severed from theology, the more 
stoutly the Lutherans maintained this theory of Divine appoint- 
ment; they assert that, although this “Divine appointment” takes 

* I.e. those who denied the Real Presence of Christ in the Sacrament of the 
Lord’s Supper. — Translator, 

852a See p. 860. 253 See p. 860. 



538 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

place indirectly, it is Divine all the same. The result is that they 
summarize their theory in this statement: the powers that be, 
just as they are, come from God. 

At a later date, Stahl’s theory of an irrational Natural Law 
instead of the rational Natural Law provided the modem Con- 
servative theory with a scientific foundation. The dominant 
system of Aristotelian-Scholastic metaphysics provided no scien- 
tific support for this theory, and indeed within the Lutheran 
orthodoxy of the day such support was not required. Pufendorf, 
who in his general outlook was a good Lutheran, and whose 
view of the positive value of the State and of civilization was 
merely more hopeful than that of Luther, sought to find a way 
of making a bridge over the gulf between the individualistic- 
rationalistic Natural Law of Grotius and the Lutheran realism 
and positivism of the idea of law and authority. This proved an 
almost impossible undertaking, however, partly because the 
Grotius’ school of thought outstripped his ideas altogether, and 
partly because the orthodox pessimism about sin and the later 
Lutheran doctrine of the Divine institution of the ruling powers 
were repelled by his theories. Thus Pufendorf made no permanent 
contribution to the Natural Law of the Church, and in these 
circles people were satisfied with a highly aphoristic theory and 
a theological-absolutist practice. When Christian Thomasius 
went over to the side of Pufendorf, the Danish Court chaplain 
wrote a pamphlet against him entitled The Interest of Princes 
in the True Religion . In it he exalted the Lutheran Church as 
the most secure support of the commonwealth, and urged the 
Royal House to consider that this dogma that all royal power 
comes directly from God is greatly to their advantage. At the 
same time he accused Calvinism and Catholicism of encouraging 
rebellion and “tumult” because they oppose this dogma. This, 
of course, is no longer genuine Lutheranism at all; it is simply 
an attempt to bolster up Absolutism with the aid of Lutheran 
doctrine. It must, however, be admitted that, to a great extent, 
this doctrine did lay itself open to such a construction . 264 

The “natural” doctrine of Society and of economics developed 
on similar lines. At first there was no need of any scientific theory 
at all, since existing conditions were quite obviously the expres- 
sion of Natural Law and of the guidance of Providence. All that 
was required was a general theological and ethical point of 
view, founded on principle, and with that a practical technique 
of government, which, in connection with the existing situation 

See p. 860. 



PROTESTANTISM 


539 

and the positive-legal conditions, made it possible to carry over 
the still strongly patrimonial administration of the State into 
a supremacy of the State, bureaucratically rationalized and 
financially secure. 

In so doing this patriarchal economic doctrine made use of 
the conservative Natural Law and theological ethical theories, 
exactly as the doctrine of the State had done. Thus the theory 
was developed in the closest connection with the likewise very 
aphoristic philosophy of the State and of the interpretation of 
Aristotle, which, in the old scholastic style, treated the State, 
Society, and economics solely from the point of view of ethics 
and theology; the practical instructions also were still full of 
Biblical and ancient Humanistic quotations, in which they 
expressed in theory the theological-juridical fundamental out- 
look. With the presupposition of sinful and corrupt Nature and 
of the providential reaction of Nature against this corruption, 
this is a religiously defined, relative physiocracy, a “natural ” 
economic doctrine which is based upon the conditions][of fallen 
humanity; in essentials itjis simply the continuation of the 
scholastic theory, which only revives Aristotle, and which, by 
means of a certain observation of reality by modern Humanists, 
has been made more practical. Above all, however, this Lutheran 
doctrine of Society and of economics was the source from which 
the Lutheran Natural Law received its bent towards a conserva- 
tive and authoritarian tendency, in close connection with its 
whole conception of the nature of authority and of supremacy . 256 

Thus in classical Lutheranism there is a voluntary agreement 
between the authorities in Church and State, in order that, 
together, they may realize the religious end of Christian Society. 
It represents the fusion of the natural, philosophical, and secular 
ethic with the Biblical, supernatural, and spiritual ethic, blending 
into a whole way of life, in which the natural forms of life are to 
be permeated with the religious spirit of love. This constitutes 
a uniform system of Christian civilization^ike that of the Catholi- 
cism of the Middle Ages. Similarly, this social system possesses 
the ideal of a uniform sociological fundamental theory; only, 
since the basis and meaning of the uniform system of life are now 
different, the sociological fundamental theory of Lutheranism is 
also different. This difference is obvious : the fundamental theory 
of Lutheranism has not been constructed upon the conception 
of the organism. 


848 Sec p. 86 1. 



540 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 


Social Theory of Lutheranism 

The social theory of the Middle Ages had expressed its Christian 
individualism thus : within every section of Society the individual 
was legally entitled to have his interests considered, in accordance 
with the standards of the class to which he belonged, while the 
regulation of the organism in accordance with these requirements 
was left to the supreme power of the Church. In Lutheranism, 
however, Christian individualism becomes purely subjective, 
with no legal claim on Society or on the Church, without any 
power of external realization, and at bottom both essentially 
and theoretically it has no sense of the need for fellowship, since 
it is only out of love that it submits to the life of the community 
at all. 

Thus Lutheran Christian individualism has retired behind 
the line of battle of all external events and outward activity, 
into a purely personal spirituality, into the citadel of a freedom 
which no events of the external order can touch, a position so 
impregnable that neither joy nor sorrow, the world or Society 
can capture it. This spirituality is based on nothing save the 
“Word”, which is guaranteed by the Church; it therefore 
regards the Church simply as the Herald of the Word, endowed 
with a purely spiritual miraculous converting power; it has no 
conception of the Church as an ethical organization of Christen- 
dom as a whole. Here, within the sanctuary of this spirituality, 
Lutheran individualism knows no bounds ; its only rule is that of 
faith and sacrament. On this exalted plane the Christian is king 
and lord over all things ; he has an invincible faith in Providence 
and an unshakable trust in God ; and the Christian spirit which 
he has received moulds his character in an atmosphere of entire 
spiritual freedom. However, as soon as the Christian believer 
turns from this spirituality to take his part in real life, he can only 
express his inner liberty through submission to the existing order, 
as a method of manifesting Christian love to the brethren, and 
to Society as a whole, or as something evil which has to be passively 
endured and accepted; the only exception which is here recog- 
nized is when the Christian is commanded to deny his faith — it 
then becomes his duty to resist. Unlimited in itself, this Christian 
individualism possesses no organ by which it can either express 
its own thoughts or secure its own existence, and its influence 
on the outside world is nil. To the extent, however, in which the 
Christian spirit does attempt to permeate the natural institutions 
of ordinary life, it does not appear outwardly as a fellowship of 



PROTESTANTISM 


54i 


individuals, formed on a religious basis, but as a spirit which 
seeks to absorb the whole complex of secular institutions and 
social life into love ; this spirit of love leads the Christian to 
submit unconditionally to the social order which had been 
established by God and by reason for the good of the whole; 
and it regards the Family, the State, Society in general, and all 
labour merely as methods of realizing and exercising the Christian 
spirit of love and obedience. Thus, when we recall the two elements 
of the fundamental theory of Catholicism, the organic and the 
patriarchal elements, we see that here the organic aspect has 
entirely disappeared. 

So far as real life is concerned, therefore, the patriarchal 
principle alone remains ; this, however, is now developed to its 
fullest extent, undeterred by the necessity for making any com- 
promise with the organic principle, while at the same time, in 
the demand for the religious spirit of love and obedience, it gains 
a fuller expression in theory. Thomist Patriarchalism, however, 
was always more of a passive acceptance of the various differences 
in rank and power, in authority over others and in wealth — a 
situation which it regarded as both a penalty and a remedy for 
sin; the organic principle within Thomism, on the other hand, 
laid an emphasis upon individualism which maintained the ideal 
of the freedom, equality, and fellowship of the Primitive State ; 
and, at least to some extent, the system of the Religious Orders 
actualized this genuinely Christian order. 

Lutheran Patriarchalism, however, more and more came to 
regard the jus naturale secundarium as a purely Divine institution, 
which the forgiven soul, happy and humble in its surrender to 
God, accepts unquestioningly, and as the wise order of reason, 
in obedience to which the natural welfare of man also is best 
secured ; to Christian love obedience to this Divine and reasonable 
order becomes a joyful duty. The same spirit is revealed in the 
fact that the comparison of existing conditions with a very dif- 
ferent ideal Primitive State is emphasized less and less by Lutheran 
thinkers, while increasing stress is laid on the “patriarchal” 
virtues, such as care and responsibility for others, trust and 
reverence, and these are made the sum-total of the whole ethical 
system, in so far as it refers to external social behaviour. As the 
relation of God to man is itself a patriarchal one, so also that of 
men to each other becomes the same. Since this fundamental 
theory can be realized most fully within the Family, which is 
necessarily based on authority and reverence, the terminology 
and the spirit in this fundamental theory are then exparftied 



542 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

from the Family until they cover the whole of the rest of 
life. 

The Prince becomes the “Father of his country”, and his 
subjects are the “children of the country” ; the lord of the manor 
is the “Father of the estate” who cares for his children and expects 
obedience from them, and in virtue of his inheritance as judge 
represents God to them, while the dependent peasants become 
the “children of the estate”, who serve their lord with respectful 
and cheerful obedience; the employer becomes the “house- 
father” who looks after the servants and maintains discipline 
within the household community, and the servants and wage- 
labourers become willing and grateful members of the household, 
who serve God in the person of the master of the house. 

Luther expounded this fundamental theory in a most excellent, 
clear, cordial, and powerful way in his two Catechisms. These 
two books formed the basis of Lutheran ethics, and by their 
means, through a process of infinite repetition, this theory of 
Patriarchalism was hammered into the minds of faithful Lutherans. 
When the Catechism was expounded the explanation of the 
Fourth Commandment became the centre of all social ethics, and 
its teaching again helped to illuminate “The Home Table — some 
texts for divers holy orders and estates, which may serve to 
admonish them respecting their offices and duties”.* 

Thus, down to the present day, through the Catechism 
Lutheran children are taught the main features of a patriarchal 
agrarian-ethic, in which they learn to “love and trust God above 
all things”, and also that it is their duty “neither to despise nor 
be angry with their parents and masters, but to hold them in 
love and esteem”. In the Catechism, too, the Lutheran child 
gives thanks to God that He “has created me and all other crea- 
tures, my body and soul, my eyes and ears and all my members, 
my reason and all my senses ; that He has given and still preserves 
unto me clothes and shoes, house and home, wife and child, 
fields and cattle, and all my goods; richly and daily He cares 
for me, providing me with all nourishment for the needs of my 
body and my life ; He protects me against all danger, and keeps 
and preserves me from all evil; and all out of pure, fatherly, 
Divine goodness and mercy ; with no merit or worthiness of my 
own ; for all that I am bound to thank and praise Him, to serve 
Him and obey Him ”. 266 Children of all classes learn this Cate- 
chism ; in the city and in the country town, in the prince’s castle 
and in the manufacturer’s villa, in the farmhouse and the 
• This book accompanied the Catechism. * 66 See p. 862. 



PROTESTANTISM 


543 

peasant’s cottage, in the tenements and model dwellings of our 
great manufacturing towns. It is an epitome of the whole of the 
Lutheran social ethic. 

This point of view throws a light upon all the social doctrines 
in particular: the Family, the State, economics, and Society. The 
various forms of social life which these doctrines express, which 
arise out of Natural Law, are merely so many temporary forms of 
social life. They are meant to serve as the sphere in which the 
religious spirit of love is to be manifested — that is, they provide 
scope for the practical exercise of the spirit which springs out of 
the certainty of a filial relationship with God, which is bestowed 
by grace. Thus they become sections of a life-curve which is 
penetrated through and through with the love of God. This is 
the reason why they are not an end in themselves, and why they 
may only be accepted in the spirit of obedience and surrender to 
God. Even as a means for the exercise of love they are not to be 
used in a humanitarian way ; they are only meant to serve as a 
means of shedding abroad the spirit of love in the way which 
God has ordained. This fundamental idea, however, did not 
develop quite smoothly. For the forms of social life which have 
arisen out of Natural Law are still meant to serve the ends of 
natural life, and their independent existence becomes increasingly 
obvious the more one enters into practical life. It then becomes 
clear that it is impossible to absorb these natural ends purely into 
the religious purpose of life. Further, the natural aims of life and 
their social forms of expression in the fallen State have received 
a character of law and force, of economic self-interest and of 
conflict, which in their very nature are opposed to the true ethic 
of love. These considerations, therefore, led to peculiar fluctua- 
tions and inconsistencies in the social doctrines of Lutheranism. 
Catholicism, in its graduated system, had felt the difficulties less 
acutely ; but Lutheranism, with its separation between the sacred 
and the secular, in a confused kind of way was bound to feel 
them more intensely. Even during his own lifetime Luther 
himself expressed them quite strongly. But in the period of 
Lutheran orthodoxy the doctrine of the Divine character of the 
natural order, of the duty of adjustment to the existing order, 
predominated to such an extent that these difficulties were felt 
no longer. Thus the final result was a terrible spiritual and 
intellectual sterility, which formed a glaring contrast to the 
social doctrines of Catholicism and of Calvinism . 257 It was, 

117 On this point v. Figgis: From Gerson to Grotius, pp. 62-107, in which Luther 
and Machiavelli are classed together. ^ 



544 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

therefore, not surprising that in the eighteenth century, when 
Lutheranism was faced by the whole new world of Western 
thought, its social theory broke down completely, although the 
practical situation remained unchanged. 

The Lutheranism of the Enlightenment produced the elemen- 
tary school, freedom of inquiry and liberty of conscience, the 
inwardness of ethical autonomy, and depth of feeling in philo- 
sophical speculation, but it changed nothing in the social doctrines. 
In practice even Kant, with his respect for authority, thought in 
these Lutheran categories. They then became official and secular 
in character . 2574 At the Prussian-German Restoration in the 
nineteenth century these theories were revived ; they then became 
a weapon in the hands of a ruling class and produced that blend 
of masculine hardness and class-conscious ruthlessness which 
distinguishes modern Lutheranism from the older kind. 

The Lutheran Ethic and the Family 

In Lutheranism, as in the Catholic tradition, the Family forms 
the starting-point of all social development. It owes this position 
to its origin, since it represents the earliest form of social life — 
it was established in Paradise or in the Primitive State, and was 
confirmed and re-ordered after the Fall, from which — either 
directly or indirectly — all other forms of social life proceed. To 
some extent the State is regarded as having been instituted along 
with the Family, although, on the other hand, it is also regarded 
as having been specially founded by God, after the peoples of 
the earth had been divided into different languages and nations ; 
in all this, however, the State is only conceived as the grouping 
of various scattered families under one head. The Family is also 
the starting-point of all economic conditions of management and 
service, in so far as the most closely knit domestic economy seems 
to be the ideal, and, actually, economic theory only thinks in 
terms of the one-family household, and of the household of 
the State, ruled by the Prince, which is conceived in a similar 
manner. The Family is the germ and the precursor of the Church, 
in so far as the religious fellowship within the home forms the 
real bond of unity within the Family, and Church-life is first estab- 
lished by the house-father through family prayers and instruc- 
tion in the Catechism. Finally, the Family is the archetype of all 
social organizations since it presents the original picture of those 
relations of authority and reverence which arise out of the 

* 87a Cf. Troeltsch: Das Historische in Kants Religionsphilosophie , 1904, pp. 37-42; 
Kalpeit: Kant und die Kirche , 1904 . 



PROTESTANTISM 


545 

natural organization. Thus it is only natural that Lutheran social 
philosophy should be permeated through and through with the 
spirit of the Family, understood in a monogamous patriarchal 
sense. 

The Family itself is an expression of the way in which the Law 
of Nature regulates and solves the sociological problems which 
arise out of the relation between the sexes. From the point of 
view of Natural Law its aim is the ordered union of the sexes, 
the ordered procreation of children, and the household which 
is formed by the several contributions of the various energies and 
powers mutually made, is the heart of all economic activity. 
But relationships of this kind, founded by Natural Law, become 
for the Christian also directly the form of the primary and most 
elementary religious exercise of love, since the relations between 
husband and wife, parents and children, provide the most im- 
mediate opportunity for the exercise of love, and in this relation- 
ship both a common self-surrender to God and the Divine 
commandment of love are to be put into practice. 

This means, certainly, that the sex ethic of Protestantism was 
very different from that of Catholicism. Luther’s own marriage 
meant more than a very manifest and concrete attempt to over- 
throw the ideal of the celibacy of the priesthood ; it was also the 
proclamation of a principle of sex ethics which regarded the sex- 
life as something normal, and which gave it an ethical character, 
making it a means of the most vital ethical and religious 
functions for all believers. Luther did not conceive the purpose 
of marriage solely from the point of view of the procreation and 
nurture of children, as so frequently happens when a fundamen- 
tally ascetic spirit is softened and adjusted to other ideals, as, 
for instance, in Puritanism. From his point of view the purpose 
of marriage consists in an independent value of its own, in the 
love to be enjoyed by married persons, in which, however, the 
specifically erotic element and the universal human element, 
intensified by the common domestic life, are not combined into a 
firm spiritual, ethical, and religious unity. 

Thus the monogamous family solves the sex-problem in general 
first of all in relation to the outside world. Sexual union before 
and outside of marriage is to be avoided, and all sexual intercourse 
is to be carried on within the limits of legitimate marriage. The 
natural conclusion to be drawn from this is the desirability of 
earlier marriage. Resolute faith in Providence sweeps away 
misgivings about the size of population, and all economic diffi- 
culties. Luther held that children should be brought into^he 

VOL. II. o 



546 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

world without any artificial restrictions whatever ; this is a positive 
duty, and the possibility of being able to support a family is 
certain because God wills it. In contrast with the Catholic ideal 
of chastity, celibacy is regarded as only commanded for excep- 
tional temperaments and circumstances — in general, however, it 
is vigorously rejected. The process of making marriage ethical 
from within, in the mutual relations between husband and wife, 
parents and children, is only achieved by the penetration of the 
whole with the religious spirit of love, which, given the existence 
of a personal, religiously deepened inclination, will regulate the 
sex relationships by mutual consideration for one another, which 
makes the parent-relationship the school of protective and educa- 
tive willing self-sacrifice, and the relationship of children to their 
parents one of trustful reverence and a humble spirit of obedience 
towards all who are set over them. This, of course, naturally 
implies the indissoluble nature of marriage, but only as an ethical 
and legal result; the sacramental character of marriage has 
disappeared. Therefore when separation is desired (and this is 
only permitted with great caution for any other cause save 
adultery) the innocent party is allowed to marry again. The 
fact that within marriage, both morally and legally, an extensive 
masculine domination of a patriarchal kind is taken for granted 
is due not merely to economic conditions, or to Catholic tradition ; 
it belongs to the very essence of Lutheranism, which looks upon 
the physical superiority of man as the expression of a superior 
relationship willed by God, and a stable order as the chief end 
of all social organizations. The house-father represents the law, 
and possesses unlimited power over others ; he is the breadwinner, 
the pastor, and the priest of his household. By submission to her 
husband the wife atones for Eve’s transgression; she ought, 
however, to be considered on a level of equality with him so far 
as religion is concerned; to some extent this modifies her sub- 
ordinate position. The modern individualistic view of marriage 
is impossible because the economic, legal, and also the ethical 
presuppositions do not yet exist. 

Marriage in the fallen state, however, is still not regarded as 
an institution which can be entirely justified without any further 
argument. For Luther sexual desire and the confusing passion 
which is bound up with it remain a sign of Original Sin ; in the 
Primitive State there was no sensuality, and the fact that sensuality 
cannot be avoided is to him the clearest proof of the universality 
of sin. Thus marriage as the organization of sensuality instituted 
by *God and reason is still at bottom only a frenum et medicina 



PROTESTANTISM 


547 

peccati , a concession to sin, which God winks at, and the sin which 
marriage inevitably incurs He restricts and heals. If, from that 
point of view, misgivings should still arise about marriage, 
Luther then appeals to the fact that it was positively founded 
and appointed by God, and he defines it simply as a duty in 
obedience to a Divine command. From that point of view, then, 
marriage is hallowed and protected against all scruples ; indeed, 
viewed from the Christian standpoint it is the most important 
and the noblest social service of a Christian. Later Lutheranism, 
it is true, did not give up the idea that “sexual desire” is the fruit 
of Original Sin ; but its scruples gradually decreased. Here, as in 
all other questions, it simply emphasized the fact of its Divine 
appointment, and thus swept away all difficulties, so that Christian 
marriage in accordance with Natural Law seemed to be a matter 
of simple obedience to a positive Divine Command, and hence- 
forth, just as in Catholicism, it was idealized as a symbol of the 
relation between Christ and the Church. Problems relating to 
marriage, therefore, lie solely within the sphere of marriage 
legislation, and the right relationship between the religious and 
the civil authority. Luther desired to hand over marriage 
legislation to the State, but instead it passed into the hands of 
the religious and civil authorities in the consistories — a clear 
sign of the fusion of sacred and secular functions in a Christian 
society which here prevailed. 

Thus in this conception of the Family the various constituent 
elements were in no way fully combined into a unity. Luther also 
was quite conscious of the fact that this ideal of the Family was 
a very high one, far removed from the actuality of life, with its 
“ wiisten Rotterei und Buberei” (wild disorder and knavery). Luther 
explains the fact that the reality approximates so little to this 
solution of the sociological sex-problem by saying that it is due 
to the corruption caused by sin, and to the specially evil character 
of these Last Days. He has no doubt at all that the ideal can be 
realized. The ideal only breaks down owing to the resistance of 
the Devil and the lusts of the flesh, and also to greed and luxury, 
which, also from this point of view, ought to be restricted by law, 
in order to maintain class barriers and to stabilize the demands 
of life . 258 

The Lutheran Ethic and the State 

The Lutheran conception of the State presents the same 
characteristics as that of the Family, and the difficulties which it 

*“ See p. 864. 



548 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

presents are regarded from the same point of view. 269 In each case 
the State has come into existence in very different ways — through 
creatures as “channels” and instruments of the Divine Reason, 
and in each case its existence has been confirmed and authorized 
by the Gospel, above all in the 13th chapter of the Epistle to the 
Romans. The State is a product of Reason, and is therefore, by 
its nature, restricted to the aims of mere Reason, the preservation 
of external discipline and order, and the securing of human 
well-being. It is the same “police” and utilitarian idea of the 
State as in Catholicism, only now, in accordance with the circum- 
stances, there is a greater emphasis upon unity of authority. The 
means which the State has at its disposal for this purpose is 
authority, which therefore forms its most peculiar attribute, 
which it always preserves, and which may not be destroyed by 
any of its subjects. It is, however, the duty of the State to use this 
authority according to the Divine Law of Nature and for the 
purpose of reason, and if the powers that be refuse to observe 
this Law, just as in scholasticism, they are to be regarded as 
“tyrants”, who may be deposed from their office. According to 
Luther’s own logical doctrine, however, the only resistance to 
these “tyrants” which he will countenance is that of passive 
resistance, or endurance, or in a case of religious persecution he 
would recommend those who are oppressed to go into exile. In 
this sense the State is always justified, both by Natural and by 
Divine Law, even among Turks and pagans; indeed, in its 
natural sense, it is even particularly excellent among pagans, 
and the ancient doctrine of the State and examples drawn from 
it can still be used to the profit of the State at the present day. 

To this extent the State is something really Divine. Now, 
however, it is its duty to establish order by force and violence 
as well as by law and justice, and this is completely opposed to 
the real Christian spirit of love. The Christian ought to love his 
enemies and to go to law as little as possible; indeed, at first 
Luther taught that no Christian should go to law at all ; later on 
he conceded the right to go to law as a means of self-protection 
against “knaves”, with whom it is impossible to come to an under- 
standing in a Christian way. In this concession, however, there 
is no ethical recognition of justice as such, whether in the form of 
law, or merely as a general sense of justice. Rather it is the duty 
of the Government to take the initiative in the administration of 
the law and of the police force, in order to prevent a Christian 
from being obliged to make too much use of the law for his own 

* 269 See p. 865. 



PROTESTANTISM 


549 


sake. There is just as little ethical value in patriotic and “Father- 
land” sentiments. In cases where the Government is unchristian 
a Christian must either refrain from resistance or the Government 
must be changed. The truly Christian ideal is that of a pure 
fellowship of love, apart from State or Law. This implies that the 
State — in spite of its Divine character and its basis in Reason 
— is still only an institution rendered necessary by and against 
sin, a product of the merely relative Natural Law, reacting against 
sin under the conditions of the fallen State. Here, then, there 
reappear all the Augustinian views about the State as the product 
of sin, which, however, can only be rightly understood if the 
State is regarded as a product of Reason working with concessions 
to sinful brutality and evil, and itself set up by Reason against sin. 

From this point of view, however, the State again seems to be 
something unchristian, directly opposed to a genuine Christian 
ethic, and it would seem to be quite natural and justifiable for 
Christian men to seek to contract out of the State, not only by 
refusing to claim the aid of the State in legal matters or to take 
part in military service, or in swearing an oath, etc., but also by 
refusing to take part in the official administration of the govern- 
ment, and in the execution of its laws. Faced by such scruples, 
however (just as in the case of the Family), Luther appeals with 
great emphasis to the belief that the powers that be are ordained 
by God, and confirmed in their position by Him. It is a duty 
of obedience towards God to exercise authority, to obey the 
Government, and to use authority for the purpose of justice ; God 
Himself bears the responsibility for His institutions, and does not 
intend them to be interfered with by human sophistry and 
argument. The practice of government and the administration 
of justice are offices appointed by Divine command, and Luther 
describes with great vigour the contrast between the system of 
law which is carried out from the ruling prince down to the 
gaoler and the hangman, in which the work of government, 
administration, and punishment, including hanging, breaking 
on the wheel, and beheading, is all a service to God, and the 
non-official purely personal morality, in which, on the other hand, 
the true service of God consists in loving one’s enemies, in 
sacrifice, renunciation and endurance, in loving care for others, 
and self-sacrifice. 

It is very evident that he delights in the paradox of these two 
ways of serving God, and he boasts with great satisfaction that 
no one has yet proved so clearly from the Scriptures the Divine 
Right of a government, which is independent, dominated no 



550 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Church, and bewildered by no scruples. It is at this point that 
Luther inserts the most characteristic and remarkable tenet in 
his whole system of ethics, the distinction between private and 
public morality, in which, in his own way, he had solved the great 
problem which had exercised the minds and hearts of the Christian 
thinkers of an earlier era. In this demand for obedience to a 
positive command of God all the Augustinian conceptions of the 
State disappear, and the State is regarded entirely as the Divinely- 
appointed authority based on reason, whose business it is to 
execute all the tasks which affect public order and the common 
weal; by that very fact the State is distinct from the Church, 
which is dependent solely upon spiritual influence and vital 
personal fellowship. 

From this point of view war also is justified. It may only be 
waged by the civil authority, for secular purposes, as part of its 
official duty, when it is necessary to protect the peace and welfare 
of its citizens against attack. Victory can only be expected if war 
is waged in self-defence. Further, war must be waged in a spirit 
of humility, ascribing nothing to one’s own efforts, but all to the 
Grace of God. This excludes, therefore, all ideas of “holy” wars 
or Crusades ; where religious interests are involved only spiritual 
weapons may be used, and even the war against the Turks may 
only be waged by the Emperor as one who is called to that duty, 
and then only in the secular interest of the protection of his 
people. This position, however, excludes all specific political 
thought and activity. Even a “secular” war must be waged for 
a righteous cause, and if a Prince should undertake an unjust 
oppressive war his subjects are to refuse to support him, accepting 
with Christian patience the suffering they will have to endure 
as the penalty for their disobedience. A just war also requires 
that those who take part in it should have the right moral and 
Christian spirit; they must prepare themselves by attendance 
at church, for God will not grant victory to the proud. In all this 
there is no question of treaties and political combinations. Every 
country stands alone, and defends itself when it is threatened, 
trusting in the providence of God. This is an extremely naive 
kind of political idea, dependent in particular instances upon 
politics of the prophetic moralizing kind. Luther is convinced 
that all wars which are not undertaken in this spirit are permitted 
to fail, and that Providence uses defeats as a rod of correction and 
as a religious method of education. Thus the thing Luther admires 
most in the Romans is that they were obliged to wage war; 
ever/ one wished to force himself on them and to gain a knight’s 



PROTESTANTISM 


55 * 


renown from them, so that they had to defend themselves ; even 
Hannibal failed because he began the war, “ for it is God who 
does it. He will have peace, and He is against those who begin 
war and break peace”. 

It is easy to see what a disastrous effect this kind of out- 
look would have upon Lutheranism in the political sphere, and 
although the Lutheran princes, diplomats and jurists, and later 
on even Luther himself, did not bind themselves to follow this 
policy, it was still everywhere a dangerous drag on Lutheran 
politics ; it determined the expansion and the fate of Lutheranism, 
which was unable to extend beyond the land of its birth. What 
a contrast was presented by Calvinist politics, with their treaties 
and alliances and their Wars of Religion . 260 

When, however, we inquire into the relation of the State to 
the Church, and to the life of the Christian community, we see 
the question from a fresh angle. For if the State is controlled by 
a Christian government, then it is no longer merely an institution 
based on Divine and Natural Law through the order of Creation, 
but it is one of the forms used for the realization of the Christian 
fellowship of love and redemption. This means that submission 
to its institutions and associations is a Christian duty of love to 
the whole of Society, and indeed one of the most necessary and 
immediate duties, since it is precisely the utilization of the forms 
of life within the State which helps our fellow-men more than 
the self-sought holiness of monastic separation from the world. 
Then it becomes especially the duty of the Government, as a 
service of love, to undertake the education and preservation of 
Society, Christian unity of faith, discipline, and order, and also 
to care for the Word of God, for purity and for the prosperity 
of the Church. The Government serves the Church freely, from 
love, creates its church-order and its financial basis, exercises 
the office of censor and defender of the Faith, and excludes from 
its sphere all expressions of false doctrine, measures which are not 
required of a non-Christian government. The Turks may tolerate 
several religions at the same time, but a Christian government 
must place itself at the disposal of the loving service of the Truth. 
Thus it will take upon itself, it is true, all kinds of secular matters, 
including education and the care of the poor, but it will deal 
with them all in a Christian spirit, and with consideration for the 
progress of the Christian life of faith. The religious end of Society, 
therefore, is exalted above the end of Natural Law, not, however, 
in the Catholic sense, with its graded organization, regulated in 

•••Seep. 865. 



552 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

case of need by the supreme authority of the Church, but in the 
sense of an agreement between the activity of the State and the 
Christian exercise of love . 261 Thus we have again reached an 
Augustinian idea, the idea of a Theocracy. Only this theocracy is 
not a Hierocracy, not the supremacy of the international hier- 
archy, and it is not a relationship which can be legally formulated ; 
but it is the free agreement in love between the purely spiritual 
Church built upon the Word, and the secular authority, freely 
serving the Church, receiving voluntary advice from the theo- 
logians; both Church and State, however, are controlled and 
impelled by the Word of God, and by its miraculous and 
spontaneous power, which achieves its own end. 

In this question, too, Luther was fully conscious that in spite 
of all his concessions to the State as an institution of fallen 
humanity, he was promulgating a highly idealistic doctrine, far 
removed from reality. We only have to read Luther’s Catechism 
to see how the Christian ruler will desire nothing save to use his 
office with all strictness, in might and right, as God’s representa- 
tive to serve the cause of love and faith ; and how, on the other 
hand, Christians ought to lead a humble and peaceful life, in 
unlimited love and readiness to help others, without legal 
proceedings or special privileges, without insistence on their 
formal rights, and with the greatest possible toleration of 
injustice. It is quite clear that this ideal of the State is super- 
idealistic, almost utopian, in a Christian sense. On the other 
hand, we only need to read his angry and vehement complaints 
of princes and jurists, feudal lords and magistrates, as well as, 
above all, his complaints of the masses, “so unteachable, so coarse 
and brutal”, to see that Luther was far removed from the 
opinion that the existing condition of things in the State corre- 
sponded to his ideal. However hard he tried, in contradistinction 
from the Baptists, to make his ideal fit into the conditions of 
actual life, it was as little at home in this coarse and brutal world 
as was his spiritual ideal of the Church, which made no provision 
for its extension. 

This was not due, as is often said, to Luther’s lack of political 
ability, a defect which might perhaps have been remedied. It 
is inherent in the religious idea itself, which cannot be combined 
with the political spirit. When a fusion of this kind does take 
place, the religious expression will also be different ; Calvinism is 
a good example of this fact. With the modern Conservatives, who 
are certainly not without the political spirit, the political element 

< - See p. 865. 



PROTESTANTISM 


553 

(which is founded upon the essence of a policy of force based 
on might) and the religious element (with its spirituality which 
finds its chief happiness in waiting on God) diverge so far in 
opposite directions that there is a complete severance and 
disharmony . 262 

In the Lutheranism of more recent times the tension between 
public and private morality disappeared more and more, and 
there arose that type which is usually described as Lutheran: 
that is, unconditional obedience towards the central government, 
and the subordinate officials, both of whom represent God, and 
only hold their office by virtue of God’s permission; the belief 
that these authorities are based on Natural and Divine Law, 
which appear more and more as the fundamental laws of a true 
Christian Society, and which co-operate without difficulty ; the 
duty of the Government to look after all secular and natural 
affairs, and, so far as it is possible, with its secular means, and in 
agreement with the ecclesiastical government, also to promote 
the Christian virtues ; the preservation of external peace at any 
price, and of internal peace by a thorough guardianship over the 
restricted understanding of its subjects. The sinful origin and the 
sinful character of law and of force disappeared in the harmony 
between the Natural and the Divine Law, and this harmony 
made possible an ideal of Christian Society, which, in itself, was 
quite possible to realize, although it was constantly being 
obscured by sin. In this ideal, revelation and natural science and 
reason unite to form one great ideal of human society. 

L. von Seckendorff gave classic expression to this ideal in the 
dedication of his Teutschen Fiirstenstaat : “The wisdom by which 
Kingdoms, Principalities, and lands are happily governed is, 
according to its origin Divine, in itself glorious and incomparable, 
and includes in its breadth and universality all that which in 
other sciences is found only in fragments. Within the sphere of 
each land it is the absolutely necessary sun, by means of which all 
is illumined, warmed, and nourished. It may be compared with 
an inexhaustible ocean into which all other wisdom and art 
flow, and in a high and secret manner, to the welfare of all, 
it is again spread abroad and shared throughout the whole land. 
It is a Paradise which is ever green with all the most beautiful 
and useful plants of the virtues and good ordinances, of which 
each in his time and place brings forth pleasant fruits. This 
wisdom King Solomon besought the only Wise God for his office 
of government, by which in addition he receiveth the greatest 

Sec p. 867. 



554 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

treasures and riches of the world also .” 263 The pessimism and 
idealism of original Lutheranism have disappeared, and the 
doctrine of society bears the traces of a hearty and inwardly 
strong, but homely and commonplace, paternal government. 

The Lutheran Ethic and Economic Questions 

Though, from the modern standpoint, the Lutheran doctrine 
of the State was to a large extent far more reactionary than the 
Thomist doctrine of the State, its economic ethic , 204 on the 
other hand, remained considerably closer to the average Catholic 
theory. It, however, also underwent great changes. These were 
mainly connected with the repression of monasticism, and of 
mendicancy, a practice which was closely connected with monas- 
ticism, and fostered by the charity of the cloister. Further, celibacy 
was considerably restricted, industry was urged upon all as a 
duty, property held in perpetual tenure (mortmain) was secu- 
larized, mass-benefices were abolished; above all the control of 
the Church in the sphere of economics was removed, which had 
brought questions like the fixing of a just price, and of usury, 
before the judgment seat of the confessional. All matters of that 
kind were now handed over to the secular authority entirely, 
and to Natural Law. The idea of Natural Law itself, however, 
whose main characteristics had already been regarded as in full 
harmony with the law of Christianity by the Middle Ages and 
by the Canon Law, was retained, so far as its positive content 
was concerned. The only difference was that that which previously 
had only been recommended to the layman in virtue of Natural 
Law, was extended to all without exception, without any quarter 
for beggars or for monasteries. The sphere which the Church had 
formerly protected was handed over entirely to the secular system 
of legislation, as something which was connected with the 
Natural Law in its harmony with the Christian Law. 

Thus we cannot be surprised that all the characteristic features 
of the mediaeval economic ethic reappear in Lutheranism ; the 
only changes are the necessary modifications caused by the social 
changes of the day . 285 

Labour with its toil and its cares is in itself contrary to nature. 
The fruitfulness of nature and the minerals in the mountains are 

IM See p. 868 . See p. 869. 

1## Here also Aristotle is the master, see Schmolltr , 470, also Melancthon: CR, XVI , 
427. It is “a natural doctrine of economics”. “They approach often very close 
to the physiocratic doctrines although they proceed from quite different pre- 
suppositions” (Schmolltr , 471). 



PROTESTANTISM 


555 


direct gifts of God to be humbly and gratefully received by man; 
the idea that these good things can only be appropriated if labour 
and technical skill are expended upon them, seems scarcely to 
have occurred to Luther. The fact that God has made the acquisi- 
tion of these good things dependent upon man’s toil simply means 
that God has instituted labour for educative reasons, as a training 
for humanity which had been corrupted by sin. Like the State, 
and the institution of marriage, labour is a remedium peccati; it 
belongs only to the relative Natural Law of the fallen State, and 
serves the ends of punishment and discipline ; essentially, therefore, 
its significance is ascetic . 286 For that very reason, however, it 
should be urged as a duty upon all who are able to work. Able- 
bodied beggars, idle monks, and lazy people who live on inherited 
incomes are an absolute contradiction to this Law of Nature. 
Private property, which is the product of labour, is also ordained 
by God; it also, however, owing to the Fall, is only a means of 
preserving discipline and order . 267 In special circumstances, as, 
for instance, in time of famine, or for widows who cannot work, 
righteousness allows man to return to the original love-commun- 
ism and to allow robbery from the baker, or a “ Notwiicherleiri ’ 
(compulsory bargain ). 268 The standard of private property ought 
not to exceed the requirements of one’s rank, yet pleasure in 
possessions, even in gold and silver, is allowed within the limits 
of a grateful frugality without any scrupulous consideration of 
the measure of one’s needs. Since, however, it is of the very 
essence of labour and of property to procure a man an income 
suitable to his rank, but not to exceed it, the traditional character 
of this economic ethic is obvious. The economic order consists 
essentially in this : to live within one’s own class, according to the 
social standards of that class, and to regard it as a just claim on 
the Government to be protected by it within this order. It is 
against all law, both Natural and Divine, to wish to rise in the 
world, to break through existing institutions on one’s own free 
initiative, to agitate and destroy Society by individual efforts, to 
improve one’s manner of life, or to improve one’s social position . 269 
Again, the forms of social organization which ought to be main- 
tained, and which, above all, have a right to be protected and 
morally recognized, are the classes which live most near to the 

### Cf. specially Brandenburgs 6; Schmoller , 474 and 478; Eck , 499. 

167 Passages from Luther and Melancthon in Schmoller , 703-708, 397; 
Uhlhom , 22. 

t## Eck : BA., IV, 1, p . 304; that is quite the Scholastic doctrine, see above, 
XXVIII, 63. It certainly does not quite agree with the rest of the Lutheran 
doctrine of the Primitive State. ##9 See p.^870. 



556 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

natural order : the main class of feudal and peasant agriculturists 
who, in direct contact with nature, produce goods without any 
intermediaries between the producer and the consumer ; the class 
of officials and soldiers who are needed for the natural task of 
caring for the common weal, to which belong the vassals who 
were liable to military service, the class of workmen in the towns 
who produce goods which cannot be made by the peasantry; 
day-labourers, servants, and other functionaries, who are to be 
exhorted to frugality and obedience; finally also the merchant, 
whose services are indispensable for exchange, who in addition 
to the net cost may raise the price to one which will secure his 
existence. The scholastic doctrine of the pretium justum , the 
recommendation of fixed prices for food-stuffs, the scholastic 
doctrine of the unfruitfulness of money, and the impossibility of 
selling time, were also combined with this point of view. In all 
this the continuation of the patristic and mediaeval prohibition of 
usury is taken for granted ; indeed it is demanded with increased 
urgency in opposition to the evasions introduced by later Scholas- 
ticism; only this ought to take place without revolution, since 
obligations of interest which have already been incurred are to 
remain as they are until the capital is either commuted or paid 
back. The system of guarantees and the system of credit are no 
less hotly attacked as an intrusion into the sphere which belongs 
to Divine Providence, and as frivolous presumption. These ideas 
almost entirely represent the consumer’s point of view. This is 
shown by the desire to establish the most direct connection 
possible between the gifts of nature, labour, and consumption, 
and the detestation of all complications which cannot be over- 
come. It is the standpoint of those who desire law and order and 
the maintenance of peace ; all labour organizations and all titles 
of possession are regarded as means of preserving a social order 
which is free from competition. This is required by the nature of 
things, it is, however, also the demand of morality , 270 in which 
Natural and Divine Law agree ; thus if this theory is carried out 
in practice everyone will gain a living, order and peace will be 
preserved, love will be exercised, natural distinctions maintained, 
while dependence on God and on nature will be accepted in the 
spirit of faith, and the welfare of the whole community will be 
furthered. 

870 On the “moral” tendency of this conservatism with an agrarian tendency, 
see Schmoller , 476; on the “naturalness” of the retention as far as possible of 
primitive methods of production and a closely knit domestic economy, see 
PP- # 7 $> 5641 Oncken, 131. 



PROTESTANTISM 


557 

The Christian sanction for this natural economic ethic consists 
in this : obedient service in the callings which have just been 
specified comes to be considered the first duty of a Christian, 
and the true and proper sphere for exercising the love of one’s 
neighbour. Since everyone ought to work and live on the proceeds 
of his labour, together with the members of his household, labour 
furthers the repose and harmony of the whole, and makes a most 
important contribution to the welfare both of the individual and 
of the community. The discharge of one’s duty by honest work 
is the best service a man can render to God, and the love of one’s 
neighbour which is exercised in the duties of one’s calling is 
better than charity, which exalts beggary, makes almsgiving a 
merit in the sight of God, while it is indifferent about the practical 
effect of almsgiving, gives too much to one and too little to 
another, while the whole idea is corrupted by the ideal of a 
holiness consisting in “good works ”. 271 This all implies an extra- 
ordinary intensification of the idea of the duty of labour, and an 
impulse to increased output. Further, in spite of all Luther’s 
preference for agricultural work, this is a civic idea and not a 
feudal one, since the feudal nobility, which, for many reasons, 
had been greatly strengthened by the Reformation, was still 
urged to recognize the duty of work, of looking after their own 
estates, or of princely official service. Both these elements were 
forced into existence by the course of events, but they were also 
a requirement of the economic ethic of the Reformation . 272 In all 
these respects, in spite of the fundamentally mediaeval view of 
the nature and ideal of economic life which has been retained, the 
new system itself is something quite different. The universal duty 
of work, the abolition of mortmain, the substitution for the 
charity which tried to deal with all social evils by a social policy 
of the State, and a system of philanthropy of Church and State 
combined, which would care for those who were really unable 
to work : these phenomena altered the whole outlook, and 
certainly later on these were the features to which the modern 
economic ethic was able to appeal. In itself, however, the spirit 
of the economic ethic of Lutheranism was thoroughly reactionary : 
it was a combination of Natural and Divine Law; it urged con- 
tentment with the simplest conditions, and a toleration of the 
existence minimum according to one’s class, accompanied at the 
same time by the readiness, in case of need, to renounce the right 
of holding property, a right which was only introduced by sin. 

271 On this Christian inspiration, Schmoller , 488 t 707; Uhlhom, jgff* 

272 See p. 870. x % 



558 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

But although this theory seems to present a very agreeable 
picture of the harmony between natural and Christian ethics, 
even here the element of conflict is present. The constant fight 
against self-interest, trust in one’s own strength, and confidence 
in one’s own achievements, the demand for a surrendered spirit 
when loss, scarcity, and distress prevail, since these things are 
divine penalties and means of discipline, the emphasis upon 
Providence which gives all without strain or affectation, the 
brotherly love which renounces all claim on possessions — all this 
goes far beyond the principles of the natural economic ethic, 
and approaches the evangelical radicalism of the persecuted and 
passively enduring sect. When it was suggested that if such 
principles were put into practice all economic life would be 
destroyed, Luther replied that it is the duty of the Government 
to prevent this, but that when this does not take place, the result 
must be endured as the nature of the world and the right of the 
Christian. Luther waged war not only on the forms of early 
capitalism and its social results which he could see quite plainly, 
and possibly even against special degenerations of the new 
economic organizations, but ultimately he was the champion of 
the Christian ethic of frugality and love, of faith in and surrender 
to Providence, against the never entirely restrained egotism and 
worldly self-confidence which are implied in all desire to possess 
property at all . 273 He was fighting against the new principle 
itself. It is only when, in so doing, he comes very close to the 
sectarian ethic that he again lays stress on the right to possess 
property and its uses, on the goodness of the Divine gifts, and the 
Divine authority of the Government — that is, of the whole organ- 
ized social system. Here again there are the same fluctuating 
points of view as there were in the questions of marriage and the 
State. The dualism of Luther’s ethical system is everywhere in 
evidence . 274 

It is only when we realize this that we see why Luther adhered 
so firmly to the economic ethic of the Middle Ages. It was not 
prejudice in favour of a prevailing economic theory, which 
everyone took for granted. Saxony had already developed 
beyond the economic system based on agriculture ; and it is just 
Luther’s passionate polemic, with its detailed enumeration of 
prevailing customs, which shows that he knew that he was hostile 
to the spirit of his age and not in agreement with it . 276 Nor was 
it simply a bias in favour of the Catholic and scholastic tradition, 


171 Sefe p. 870. 


* 74 See p. 871. 


,7i SchmolUr , #9. 



PROTESTANTISM 


559 


for whenever this conflicted with his principles he was clear- 
sighted enough and decidedly hostile ; indeed, in this he was not 
adhering to Catholic theology, but only to its economic ethic and 
to Natural Law. 

Luther believed that it was possible to maintain the content 
of mediaeval social teaching for reasons which may be analysed 
thus : just as Luther’s peculiar political conception of Natural 
Law and of force was the conscious, deliberate result of an 
individualistic, and yet realistic and religiously super-idealistic, 
point of view, so also his economic ethic of Natural Law and 
its connection with the Christian ethic was also consciously based 
on principle. Whereas in politics he consciously broke through 
the tradition of the patristic Natural Law of political rationalism, 
here, just as deliberately, he retained it. The reason was this : 
Luther was convinced in precisely the same way as were the 
Catholic ethical thinkers, that this mediaeval conception of 
the economic ethic was the only one which harmonized with 
the Christian’ ethic, that it alone could be combined with the 
Christian ethic of love, trust in God, and renunciation of the 
world. With the exception of Humanists trained in the economic 
politics of the towns like Pirckheimer, Peutinger, Machiavelli, 
and Vives, the majority of Luther’s contemporaries, without 
confessional distinctions, were on his side. The territorial and 
Imperial legislation also moved along similar lines and fought 
against the resistance of the towns. We have already seen that a 
Christian ethic which could accept the life of the world only 
became possible within the sphere of mediaeval society and the 
mediaeval system of economics — a system of economics which was 
based on agriculture and on the growth of the towns with their 
handicraftsmen. Luther believed that this still held good, and he 
desired to maintain the basis, upon which alone the realization 
of the Christian ethic had, until then, seemed possible. The 
heightened passion with which he asserted the theory, and the 
intensity of his ethical exhortations, was due to the fact that the 
new social type of the capitalistic cities and their social results 
now confronted this idea of a Christian Natural Law. This new 
type with its consequences of freely mobile individualism, of 
competition, of the calculating spirit which aims at increasing 
its possessions, with its complicated and incalculable connections 
between consumption and production, was in actual fact for the 
Christian ethic, at any rate for its essential fundamental idea*, 
a harsh opponent. 

Luther saw this very clearly, and it was from this point ofview 



5 6o THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

that he formulated his economic and ethical opposition, which, 
in this respect, entirely agreed with Catholicism . 276 

To this very day the social ideal and the economic ethic of the 
Lutheran Conservatives still perpetuate this point of view , 277 and 
in this respect they still have an affinity with the Catholic ethic, 
which, however, seeks to direct the democratic element (which 
it certainly recognizes far more clearly) into a new social fabric, 
and within the borders of a class framework determined by the 
Church. Luther’s ideas were the same as those which are still 
held to-day by Catholics, Conservatives, and middle-class people 
in general. Luther fought against monopolies and against joint- 
stock companies, against the demand for higher wages for day 
labourers and servants which was the result of the general rise 
in prices , 278 against the stipulations laid down by the latter , 279 
against the individualism which broke through class barriers and 
sumptuary laws, just as the Conservatives of the present day fight 
against the Stock Exchange, the greed of the masses, the right of 
the workmen to form trade unions, and against free competition. 

The difference between Luther and the Conservatives of the 
present day, however, lies in this : Luther had in mind essentially 
ethical and religious standards alone ; class feeling did not enter 
into the question at all ; in place of that he displayed a passionate 
intensity which made no effort to discover any possible scientific 
explanation of the type which he hated, nor did he try to under- 
stand the general reasons and necessities for the changes which 
he observed. From his naive point of view these changes were 
due to evil — “works of the devil” — or a Divine discipline for the 
wild and unruly Germans — or they were a foreshadowing of the 
End of all things . 280 Luther could not imagine that the universal 
general changes in the world situation might also cause changes 
in the economic and ethical sphere, and this is why he summoned 
the world back to the Natural and Divine Law. The new economic 
order is contrary to humility, to trust in God, to brotherly love, 
to Nature, and to God. He stated plainly that in his opinion it was 
now the duty of the Government, in co-operation with the influ- 
encing of opinion through church and school, to intervene. 

876 See p. 871. 

877 Cf. Oncken: /, p. 147, who refers to A*. L. von Haller and Adam Muller . 

878 Cf. Schmoller y 513. 878 Gf. Schmoller , 5/5. 

880 An example of the naive character of his arguments in Schmoller , p. 366: 
that seven, eight, nine, and ten per cent, are unchristian is proved by the 
fact “^Jhat robbers and usurers who take that rate of interest frequently die a 
violent death or otherwise perish miserably”. 



PROTESTANTISM 


561 


Social Ideal of Luther 

The whole social ideal of Luther — the organization and 
construction of Society in general — is finally explained by political 
and economic and ethical ideas. As in mediaeval Catholicism, it 
was the ideal of the social hierarchy, as a “cosmos of callings” ; 
the only difference is that the duty of the “calling” is now extended 
to all, which involves the direct incorporation of the idea of 
“the calling” into the very heart of Christian ethics. The “call- 
ings” are in part those which proceed from the economic organiza- 
tion of Society, in which a rigid guild organization would be 
desirable. In part they are vocations to the Church and to the 
work of education, to which (as is constantly repeated) it is a 
Christian duty to lead talented children. Then there are the 
callings of the prince, the noble, the official, the soldier, and, las>t 
of all, the surplus of those who cannot find a place within the 
established organization, but who can still be used to serve in 
various ways as they are needed . 281 Serfdom, which had not 
ceased to exist, and which was extended at the close of the six- 
teenth century, from this point of view was regarded in precisely 
the same way as slavery was regarded in the Early Church, as 
a class, that is, in which men may enjoy the inner liberty of 
Redemption, but in which they have no right to seek external 
legal freedom . 282 In Lutheranism there was no idea at all of any 
new anti-slavery movements, and even down to the present day 
neither agrarian nor industrial serfdom raises any kind of mis- 
giving in its mind. The reason for all this is perfectly clear. The 
social hierarchy does away with competition, so far as that is 
possible in the fallen state, and in so doing it harmonizes both 
with the ideal of love, and with the ideal of Natural Law which 
aims at law and order. It is in this sense that Stahl has made a 
new defence of the class theory as part of the theory of Christian 
Natural Law . 283 A blind faith in Providence assures the com- 
munity that a principle of this kind would meet all the needs of the 
whole population. This system can only be disturbed by unusual 
accidents and Divine chastisements ; when this happens those 
whose lives have been thrown out of gear by these events are 
commended to the care of Christian philanthropy, and to the 
care of the civil authority, firmly believing that these methods 
will suffice to heal all social evils . 284 At bottom, no one doubts that 
the Government can achieve all this, provided that it obeys con- 

181 See p. 871. 882 See p. 871. 288 See ft 872. 

184 Cf. von Seckendorff: Fiirstenstaat, p. 193. % 

VOL. n. H 



56a THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

scientiously both the Law of Nature and the Law of God : that is, 
the characteristic difference between this point of view and that 
of the present day. The reason for this lies partly in the fact that 
in reality conditions were — in a quite remarkable way — much 
simpler than they are now; partly, owing to the lack of all 
statistical information, there was a total absence of scientific 
knowledge of the complicated character of the social situation, 
which was conditioned by and dependent on so many different 
factors ; the right of location did not yet exist, and the problem 
of population had only just begun to appear as a subject for 
discussion. Hence a naive conception of that kind was possible. 
The later theological ethic therefore, on the side of its social 
theories, was simply concerned with the vocational system as a 
whole ; in particular it dealt only with the question of the family 
and the household, which, it felt, ought to constitute the chief 
sphere for the development of the ethical virtues of Christianity. 
The regulation of the whole is left to the Government, which, 
strongly supported by Lutheranism, takes supreme control. It 
is then the duty of the Government to see to it that in harmony 
with Christian and Natural Law the different classes are main- 
tained in their suitable way of living, that social evils are remedied, 
and that whatever progress is necessary, is achieved. These matters 
come under the province of political economy and police 
administration ; thus the Lutheran theory merges into mercan- 
tilism, since, where the good of the community is concerned, the 
Government is permitted to do that which is forbidden to the 
individual, that is, to gain an increase of property and profit, 
to initiate new industrial enterprises, monopolies and royalties, 
immunities, and alterations in the social structure and its com- 
pulsory character. In connection with this subject Seckendorff 
has given a classic description of the Christian “police”. 285 

Social Policy, Social Reform, 
and Philanthropy 

When we gather up all these various particulars and summarize 
them it then becomes possible to answer the question: to what 
extent did Lutheranism attempt to mould Society according to 
Christian ideals, or to introduce a scheme of social reform? The 
answer is simpler than we would expect when we consider that 
Lutheranism has been interwoven with an amazingly varied 
social history. Lutheranism has been mainly interwoven with a 
sociaJL process which extends from the advanced stage of the 

* #i4 See p. 87a. 



PROTESTANTISM 


563 

German civilization of the sixteenth century, through the desola- 
tion of the Thirty Years War, the formation of the German 
States, and finally, through the politics of the Enlightenment and 
the Restoration periods, down to the great social problems of the 
present day. The simplicity of the answer is due to the fact that 
down to the present time the Lutheran position is based essentially 
upon the religious theory of the purely spiritual nature and 
“inwardness” of the Church, while all external secular matters 
are handed over to reason, to the ruling Princes, to the civil 
authority. At the beginning, certainly, there was combined with 
that the assumption that Natural and Divine Law, both issuing 
from the same source, will always naturally supplement each 
other, and that a Christian government will always desire and 
be able to govern and to mould secular affairs in harmony with 
Natural and Divine Law, in the spirit of the religious and 
ethical ideal. 

The idea of moulding Society according to Christian ideals 
certainly existed ; but it was left entirely to the Government, to 
be carried out in accordance with natural reason, which har- 
monized with the Gospel and was adapted to the fallen state. 
When, however, the modern conception of Natural Law arose 
which differed from the Christian Natural Law of the fallen 
state and of its comparative harmony with reason, then certainly 
a new situation had been created. Lutheran thinkers found a 
solution by accepting the new Natural Law just as they had 
accepted the old, seconding the reforming activity of the State 
with a partially secularized religious enthusiasm: when, more- 
over, the political and social development, which had also been 
emancipated from this idea, passed into the modern conditions 
of the pure struggle for power and of competition, then the social 
theory of Lutheranism was in a position of great embarrassment ; 
henceforth it could only preach its doctrine, with scarcely a hope 
of realizing it, since, unlike Catholicism and Calvinism, Lutheran- 
ism possessed no organ by which it could put its theories into 
practice apart from the State, and the modern State, for its part, 
no longer feels itself— as in early Lutheranism — to be the secular 
aspect of the organism of Christian Society. This was the beginning 
of the social impotence of Lutheranism, in so far as it has not 
adopted Calvinistic and modem ideas. In its actual primitive 
sense it only finds support among the Conservatives; and it 
therefore combines its dogmatic renewal with the political and 
social views of the Conservatives. Its hopes of a social transforma- 
tion in accordance with Natural and Divine Law are pinnecl 90 



564 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

longer to the Christian State, but to the Christian Party. As we 
can understand very well, this brings Conservative Lutheranism 
into touch with the other Christian Party— against which it had 
once fought so ardently — that of Catholicism, in a community of 
“Christian world-outlook 5 ’, and of opposition to the modern 
militaristic and bureaucratic sovereign State, with its indifference 
towards the Church and religion in general. 

At first, however, Luther did not exhort the Church to this 
passive attitude in social questions. At the moment when the 
seething ferment of German life came into touch with the reform 
of religion, and when it seemed as though this combination were 
about to lead to the goal of a Christian commonwealth, renewed 
in its political, social, and Church-life, Luther, in his appeal To 
the Christian Nobility of the German Nation , outlined a programme of 
ecclesiastical and socio-political reform for the whole Empire, in 
which he had interwoven all the suggestions which had come 
from the opposition and the reform parties with his new ecclesi- 
astical ideal of a Church based upon the priesthood of all believers. 
In this treatise, however, Luther was carried farther than he 
intended by the impetus of the whole movement ; and even here 
his theory was foreshadowed, to this extent, that he does not 
suggest that the spiritual authority should bring about the 
reforms and thus impose on the nation a new Christian law, but 
that the princely rulers alone are to bring about the reforms 
outside the Church, in the strength of reason and love for the 
pure Gospel. 

“Reasonable Regents alongside of Holy Scripture 55 — these are 
the separate powers, which, however, each within its own sphere, 
work together for the reform “of the Body of Christ 55 . But an 
enthusiastic optimism still conceived both tasks as essentially 
united and destined to achieve a common victory . 286 After these 
preparations had been made a General Council would then 
finally take in hand the reform of Christendom as a whole. 
Nothing came of this idea of a collective reform, so in the times 
of ferment the Reformation movement turned to the particular 
local and communal authorities, which each in its own way 
undertook the work of “social betterment 55 , and during this 
experimental period they were supported by Luther’s “group- 
ideal 55 . The municipalities and the magistrates, who already 
possessed considerable ecclesiastical rights, and a tradition of a 

186 Cf. Brandenburg , pp. gff. ; for the origin of thoughts of reform in one who, 
until, then, had been exclusively occupied with theology see fV. Kdhler : L. 9 s 
Sohrijft an den Adel im Spiegel der Kultur - und Zeitgeschichte , 1895- 



PROTESTANTISM 


565 

kind of ethical “police” supervision, now issued new regulations, 
which made arrangements for the system of public worship, 
administration of the Poor Law, and the organization of the 
police force in the new Protestant sense. The Wittenberg Ordin- 
ance of January 1522, and the Leisnig Ordinance of 1523, were 
endeavours (which have often been imitated) to institute a 
Christian social order which was to use the money formerly 
locked up in endowments and benefices for the benefit of church 
and school, for poor relief in general, and also in time of famine, 
and which desired to leave the administration of these funds in 
the hands of elected stewards of Church revenues. These “ordin- 
ances” were based on similar police organizations in the towns, 
which had previously exercised similar powers, but they were 
coloured by the evangelical Protestant Church spirit, and this 
ecclesiastical flavour certainly entitled them to be described as 
Christian Socialism on local and communal lines. These “ordin- 
ances” were, however, Utopian and visionary, and they were never 
carried out in practice. 287 Indeed, under the influence of the 
disillusionment of the Peasants’ War, and with the possibility 
which had now arisen of instituting a new order on territorial and 
not on local lines, Luther turned away from the dubious “group- 
ideal” altogether, and henceforth, in accordance with his essential 
main idea, he handed over all political and social matters, as 
external secular affairs, entirely to the Government, to reason, 
and to the jurists, that triad which he praised as much as he 
scolded it! With his eyes open Luther now maintained that the 
Church ought to dominate solely the purely spiritual spheres of 
edification and instruction. Under the influence of the Gospel, he 
argued, a Christian Government should then be able to settle 
all social questions which appeared on the horizon of that day 
on its own authority. These social questions were mainly con- 
cerned with the problem of the support of those who, for some 
reason or another, were unable to earn their living within the 
social hierarchy, conceived as a system of “callings”. 

#87 Cf. Uhlhorn , III, 33-51; Barge: Karlstadt , I, 352 , 382-386; above all, L. 
Feuchtwanger : Geschichte der sozialen Politik und des Armenwesens im Zeitalter der 
Reformation , Berliner Diss., igo8 , and its continuation in the Jahrbuchfur Gesetz - 
gebung, Verwaltung, und Volkswirtschaft, igog , XXXIII. In essentials I follow 
Feuchtwanger , who very considerably supplements and corrects the work of 
Barge ; cf. the analyses of the Wittenberger “ Beutelordnung ”, of the “ Ordnung der 
Stadt Wittenberg ”, and of the Leipziger “ Kas tenor dnung”, Diss.,pp. g-16. Cf. also 
K. Milller: Luther und Karlstadt , igoj (Appendix), and Barge: Die alteste evangelische 
Armenordnung , Hist . Vierteljahrsschrift , XI, igo8, pp. igs-225, and ITheolog. 
Jahresbericht , XXVIII , p. 530 . • 



566 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

This might have been the end of all direct ecclesiastical social 
activity, and the beginning of a policy of purely secular social 
welfare and care of the poor. The territorial Princes, however, 
whose authority was still far from being centralized, and the 
communes (free cities) which were burdened with heavy tasks, 
undertook this vocation very imperfectly. Luther’s helpers there- 
fore intervened, above all Bugenhagen, who was a good organizer, 
and they took over the task of the care of the sick and the poor, 
which lay so near to the heart of the Church. This service was 
undertaken, however, no longer in the Utopian, Christian- 
Socialist spirit of the “Ordinances” of Wittenberg and Leisnig, 
but — and in this matter it was essentially the towns which were 
concerned— in a very matter-of-fact combination of communal- 
police activity and the ecclesiastical activity of pastoral work and 
of charity. In accordance with municipal organizations for the 
care of the poor in the towns, and under the stimulus of the 
reform of the Poor Law by Ludovico Vives, which started in 
Belgium, the means were created out of endowments, the poor 
were controlled by the co-operation of the spiritual and the 
secular authorities, vagabondage was restricted, hospitals were 
created, and a fixed system of book-keeping was introduced in 
which particular care was taken to avoid the confusion caused 
by mixing up these accounts with those which belonged to the 
administration of the Church and to education. In the end, 
however, these new “ordinances” for administering the funds 
from the “common chest” were not carried out permanently. 
This was partially due to the fact that the problems connected 
with the Poor Law had been underestimated, and partially also 
to their failure to centralize the endowment monies which they 
did control ; another cause was the lack of voluntary officials who 
could serve in turn upon the board of administration ; above all, 
however, the new religion itself was too much engrossed with the 
personal interior life, too much imbued with the idea that every- 
one ought to work, and too much alienated from the old ideal of 
charity, to succeed in creating the necessary new methods. Thus 
the Lutheran “Chests” ( Kasten or funds) merely became meagre 
funds in support of the poor alongside of other similar institu- 
tions . 288 

Thus, in this form also, ecclesiastical Socialism came to nothing, 
and the task of caring for the common weal was entrusted to the 
various governments, which were becoming more and more 

,M Cf. JJhlhom, III, 102-140, and Feuchtwanger: Geschichte der sozialen Politik tmd 
des*Armenwesens im Zeitalter der Reformation , Berliner Diss ., 1908. 



PROTESTANTISM 


567 

centralized, and were increasingly taking control of all the 
interests within their sphere; these governments, however, felt 
that the ecclesiastical arrangements for poor relief relieved them 
of responsibility, and they therefore did nothing on their side. 
But, still, the permanent principle had been finally formulated : 
that all secular and political affairs, and therefore also the question 
of social welfare, belong to the province of the Government, while 
the Church is concerned solely with the salvation of the soul and 
the interior life of personal piety. 

Thus the Lutheran social programme merged into the social 
politics of patriarchal mercantilism. Then, when the State 
accepted the modern movement of thought, and moved away 
from a patriarchal Absolutism to an Absolutism of the Enlighten- 
ment, the whole system of Christian social effort slipped into the 
modern policy of social welfare, and Lutheranism lost all inner 
connection with, and all influence upon, the Government, which 
was certainly far from being a “Christian” government. 

The more, however, that the social policy became purely 
secular, and the more clear it became that a purely class and 
vocational system does not enable everyone to gain their liveli- 
hood, but that it was always surrounded by a multitude of people 
who had become declassis , and of people in distress, and especially 
when the more restless social movement of modern life brought 
bewilderment and confusion into many lives, Lutheranism was 
obliged to give up its attitude of simple trust in Providence and 
in the vocational system ; and the Christian desires to express love 
which it did possess were again exercised in the form of voluntary 
philanthropy, in institutions, fellowships, clubs, and charities. 
Under the influence of Pietism, Lutheranism returned to the 
religious-social policy of charity, without the glorification of 
mendicancy, and at first without permitting this practice of 
charity to have any connection with the Church ; in every other 
respect, however, this meant the resumption of the charity of 
Catholicism and of the Early Christian Church . 289 This has been 
the position ever since, and, under English influences, during the 
nineteenth century, as the “Innere Mission” (Home Mission) 
movement, this Christian social service has developed and 
flourished in a quite remarkable way. Orthodox ecclesiastical 
Lutheranism has only taken part in this movement in a rather 
hesitating way, but it has to-day finally become fairly sympathetic 
to it as a whole. Strict Lutheranism, which was renewed at the 
time of the Restoration and which has since then been dominant, 

See p. 873. * 



568 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

refused to entertain any further ideas of social reform. It has 
maintained the position which Stahl represented, i.e. that the 
social order should be entrusted to a Christian Government, 
whose duty it should be to ensure the maintenance of the class 
organization of callings with the restriction of the modem life 
movement. Wichern’s attempt to go beyond the mere exercise of 
charity and to introduce a Christian social reform from the side 
of the Church, and in the grand manner to combine organically 
an ecclesiastical religious philanthropy with the social policy of 
the State, broke down because Lutheranism was unprepared, 
inwardly, for action of this kind, and also because his ideas were 
captured by the Conservative reactionary party . 290 The trans- 
formation of the programme of Wichern by Stocker only led to 
the demand for a greater independence and power for the Church, 
and thus to an imitation of modern Catholic social reform ; other- 
wise, so far as the general social ideal was concerned, it was 
obliged to connect itself with Conservative and middle-class 
principles in the true Lutheran sense; its rejection by the Con- 
servatives finally drove it back into very small groups . 291 

Thus, down to the present time, the Lutheran Church has 
never advanced farther than the renewed ideal of charity ; it has 
never made any effort to initiate a real social transformation at 
all. Most Lutherans simply repeat the old doctrine of the inward- 
ness of the Church and of the duty of leaving all external matters 
of legislation and social welfare to the State . 292 Others, like the 
Christian Socialists of the Naumann school, discard the principles 
of Lutheranism altogether, and feel forced to return to the 
general political, economic, and social foundations of present-day 
Society . 293 Others, like those who represent the point of view of 
the Evangelical Social Congress, fully aware that the situation 
has entirely changed, discuss from differing points of view the 
possibility of striking out along new paths . 294 

Wherever the earlier Lutheranism is still a real force — among 
the Conservatives, that is to say — all social reform consists in 
breaking up the rationalistic, individualistic nature of modern 
Society, and in the revival of a society organized on aristocratic 
lines, bound together by class bonds, i.e. in the struggle against 
the Liberal world-outlook, and against the creations of Liberalism 
in the political, economic, and social sphere ; alongside of this, 
then, the “Innere Mission” (Home Mission) may indeed exercise 
its charitable activity among the poor and the sick, but it must 
,t0 Seep. 873. 191 See p. 874. t9% See p. 874. 



PROTESTANTISM 


569 

guard against any possibility of shattering the idea of authority . 296 
Within these limits the “Innere Mission * 5 has certainly achieved 
splendid things, although the Christian-social element certainly 
predominates less within it than the propaganda and the evangel- 
istic element . 2964 

The Lutheran Ethio 
and the General Situation 

This completes the analysis of Lutheranism. Now, however, we 
have to answer the final question: to what extent are these 
social doctrines the reflection of existing political and social 
conditions? So far as the actual ideal is concerned which floated 
before the minds of Lutheran thinkers, we must give a directly 
negative reply to this question. The social doctrines of Lutheran- 
ism are, like the whole of Lutheran piety, a genuine branch of the 
whole Christian religion and ethic of love, which either rejects or 
is indifferent to the world, with its law, property, might, and 
force, and of that monotheism which proclaims that the religious 
aims of the personality united to God are the only true and lasting 
values of life, and from that derives the idea of the union of man- 
kind in love, through the common exercise of these values. To a 
far greater extent than Catholicism, certainly, Protestantism has 
accepted the life of the world, and it is therefore similarly deter- 
mined by the spirit of general social development, which forced 
itself upon the attention of the Church and found itself in a 
situation in which this was possible without any particular 
difficulty. In so doing, however, Protestantism has carefully 
preserved the dualism of the Christian ideal which arises out of 
this conception, and which, in contrast with Catholicism, it has 
both deepened and intensified. Since Protestantism supported the 
mediaeval ideal of a social hierarchy and the anti-capitalistic 
spirit, expressed in agrarian and middle-class ways of living, along 
with a patriarchalism based on authority and reverence, as the 
right way of reconciling both sides, it drew its conclusions from 
the ethical and religious ideal, and not from the circumstances 
which happened to prevail at the time. If we reflect upon Luther’s 
idealistic plans, and remember his bitter complaints of the non- 
Christian character even of the new Protestant evangelical world, 
we receive far more the impression of a Christian Utopia than 
of the justification and glorification of existing conditions, and not 
without reason. One of the finest and most original Lutheran 

"•Seep. 875. v . 

s»u Qf t Schafer : Leitfaden der inner en Mission 8 , 1893, and Uhlhom: Liebestatigkeit . 



570 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

thinkers, J. V. Andrea, has described Luther’s social ideal (in 
imitation of Sir Thomas More and Campanella) in a Utopia, 
called Christianopolis . 296 

Whenever the social doctrines of Lutheranism are treated 
solely as the religious sanction of the existing situation, as often 
happens in orthodox Lutheranism, this always means that 
Lutheran thought has been weakened and despiritualized ; the 
main impulse of the real Lutheran ethic in its mystics and spiritual 
thinkers, in its ethical reformers, and finally in the Pietists, has 
always reacted against this tendency with great vigour. By the 
very vigour of its protest, however, this opposition often lost its 
connection with the real leading ideas of Lutheranism, and 
landed in the other extreme of asceticism. The same applies to 
the exaltation of Luther’s doctrine of the “calling”, which is a 
favourite idea of writers of modern books on the subject, which 
they try to interpret as a certain religious consecration and sanc- 
tion of modern civilization. It is not due to thoughtlessness, 
therefore, when the idea is suggested that modern civilization 
means essentially an anti-Catholic freedom from sacerdotalism 
and from monasticism, and that otherwise it is a conservative 
middle-class restriction or weakening of the modern life-move- 
ment . 297 

The religious and ethical ideas of Lutheranism are not a 
glorification and intensification of definite class and power 
interests by means of a world outlook based upon those interests. 
This might perhaps apply to the peculiarly irrational idea of 
Natural Law which enabled Lutheranism to accept the existing 
conditions of authority, regarding the Law of Nature as though 
these conditions of authority, together with sin and inequality, 
were all part of the unchanging Divine Order, to which the soul 
(which remains inwardly free) gives itself up to labour and to 
endure. The reason for this lay, at least originally, and in Luther 
himself, not in any kind of class interest, but in the authoritative 
conservative temperament of Luther himself, and in his peculiarly 
penetrating conception of the nature of authority and power, 
as well as the essential inequality of the fundamental elements in 
all human social groupings. In this he is only perpetrating the 

Cf. Joh. Val. Andreae: Reipublicae Christianopolitanae description Strassburg , i6ig. 
The spirit of the whole is decided Lutheran. The communism is taken over 
from the Utopias of the Humanists (private property and the aristocratic 
constitution are carefully maintained), but the whole is balanced by the 
principles of Lutheranism ; cf. also E. Ehrhardt: Un Roman Social Protestant au 
jybns s i£i e , Paris y Fischbacher , 1908. 1,7 See p. 876. 



PROTESTANTISM 


57i 

patriarchal side of the scholastic Natural Law , 298 while he discards 
the individualistic rationalistic elements. This, however, is the 
reason why Luther also called these elements directly unchristian 
and the product of sin, and he only recognized them as a Divine 
institution within the sphere of sinful reason, under the impression 
of their unalterable nature and their absolute necessity. He was 
only able to combine this idea of Natural Law with his own 
general Christian idea by inculcating the spirit of humility, trust 
in God, readiness to suffer, and the fact that man, owing to the 
taint of Original Sin, deserves to be punished. When, later on, 
this idea of Natural Law was used simply to justify existing 
conditions, and the chief heirs of the Lutheran spirit at the 
present day, the Conservatives, developed this Natural Law into 
an aristocratic naturalism which is related to Darwin’s doctrine 
of selection and to Nietzsche’s ethic of the Super-Man, these are 
certainly applications of the idea in the interest of political and 
social domination, in which they display their flagrant opposi- 
tion to the real Christian ideas and their “class” spirit. Further, 
this inconsistency is not usually apparent to most people, since 
they conclude that the non-Christian character of those prin- 
ciples is due to the situation created by sin, and therefore they 
do not merely retain them in spite of their unchristian character, 
but they are convinced that they ought to use them, as results of 
inequality and means of repression willed by God against the 
individualistic atomistic evil . 299 This theory also undoubtedly 
contains right views about the “nature” of man, and it contains 
no less incontrovertible ethical values in the ideas of obedience and 
of authority, just as in patriarchalism itself. 299 * Thus here also the 
ultimate cause is the old ideological basis, which only nowadays is 
so visibly useful to “the sectional interests” and is now associated 
with them to make some thoroughly impure combinations. 

It is more difficult to answer the opposite question: What 
influence has Lutheranism had upon social history? Here, from 
the very outset, we must distinguish between the effects of its 
spiritual individualism, which manifest themselves plainly in the 
spiritual and ethical development of German culture right down 
to Kant and Goethe, and which has left traces of its influence in 
the idea and development of family life, and in the realm of 
political, social, and economic institutions . 300 It is essentially the 
latter with which we are here concerned. 

Cf. above, pp. 285-288, 

1,9 Cf. the numerous illustrations from modern Conservative liteAture in 
Stillich, pp. 30-50. ,Ma See p. 876. 300 See p. $76. 



572 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

The gist of the matter is this: in itself the late mediaeval 
tendency in the development of the State and the general social 
classification was not altered by Lutheranism. The only changes 
were the disappearance of the priesthood, which was replaced 
by the Protestant ministry, as well as the abolition of the supreme 
control by the Church, and the establishment of the system of 
purely State control which took its place ; the process of secular- 
ization and the abolition of monasticism were also changes which 
cut deeply into the social fabric, but they did not initiate new 
social developments. The social fabric was more profoundly 
affected by the rise of a Humanistic educated class, which was 
encouraged by the didactic character of the new religion, and its 
close connection with education ; yet this was rather an effect of 
Humanism combined with the Reform Movement than an effect 
produced by the religious spirit itself . 801 

Its political influence was more central. This does not mean 
that Lutheranism developed a new idea of the State, or even 
created a new State; but, by its renunciation of ecclesiastical 
independence, by its deification of the Government and its loyal 
passivity, it provided a most favourable setting for the develop- 
ment of the territorial State, which was then engaged in the 
process of self-development. It smoothed the way for territorial 
absolutism; to the feudal lords of the manor it made easier the 
development of the manorial estate with its privileges and the 
growth of a new kind of serfdom , 302 and it fostered the patriarchal 
attitude and the corporate class spirit. 

In relation with foreign countries, however, the same Lutheran 
spirit hindered the action and expansion of the various States, 
and finally caused terrible defeats. Its only service to the actual 
modern State has been to encourage the spirit of absolutism; 
once that was supreme, however, it became strong enough to 
strike out on a modern line of its own, and it has thus gone far 
beyond the Lutheran principles of peace, protection, and punish- 
ment based on Natural Law as well as the duty of the Govern- 
ment to promote Christian charity. 

The influence of Lutheranism in the economic sphere has been 
equally indirect. Here its essential spirit is that of traditionalism 
and agrarian middle-class production, which, by means of 
corporate solidarity, excludes competition, as far as possible 

#01 Cf. Wittich : Deutsche und FranzHsische Kultur im Elsass , igoo , a work which goes 
far beyond its explicit subject. 

802 On 4 his point, see detailed illustrations in Drews: Der Einfluss der Gesell- 
schqftlichen %ustande. 



PROTESTANTISM 


573 

combining simplicity in one’s requirements with simplicity of the 
conditions of production and consumption. Since it also abolished 
mendicancy, urged the masses to work, and by its individualism 
stimulated individuals, even on the non-religious side, and 
created a certain elasticity of mind by its system of education 
(which at first certainly only affected the middle classes), it has, in 
spite of everything, helped to develop economic life in a more 
vital way. Here, however, also the chief element in the whole 
process was the making of the secular authority independent, 
which, entrusted with social welfare and exalted to supreme 
power, introduced Western methods of production, and in so doing 
it profited by the fact that the Lutheran sections of the popula- 
tion were more inclined to work hard than the rest. Otherwise it 
was not for nothing that mercantilistic rulers introduced Calvinist 
or Pietist settlers wherever they wished to raise the level of trade 
or manufactures. The modern economic situation — even in the 
modest range which it had attained in Germany until the nine- 
teenth century — has been created by the State, and is not due 
to the influence of Lutheranism . 303 Lutheranism opposed the 
modern development of the State only one degree less ardently 
than Catholicism. 

Finally, so far as its main social tendencies are concerned, and 
its theoretical conception of Society, Lutheranism has always 
represented the principle of patriarchalism and conservatism. 
This was caused in part by the fact that the fundamental religious 
temper of trust in God and distrust of human effort and industry, 
the relation of the sense of sin with suffering and endurance, in 
itself tended to foster a conservative spirit, and in part by the 
fact that the bases of the earlier social constitution, with its class 
organization and the greater simplicity of the relation to the 
Divine gifts of Nature, are firmly retained by Lutheranism as the 
presupposition of its ethical ideals. Thus Lutheranism is inclined 
to endure existing conditions humbly and patiently, even when 
they are bad, and to glorify them when they agree with those 
earlier ideals. If, speaking generally, the Protestant countries are 
the most progressive at the present time, we must not forget, 
on the other hand, that during the period when the Protestant 
churches were being formed the mother-lands of modern civiliza- 
tion — Italy, France, and Spain — were Catholic, and that their 
exhaustion has no connection with their Catholicism — that, thus, 
on the other hand, the Protestant countries too, and especially the 
Lutheran, cannot in any case ascribe their present position 

808 See p. 877. 



574 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

primarily to their religious bases, however important these may be 
in particular . 804 

The passivity of Lutheranism involved the habit of falling back 
upon whatever power happens to be dominant at the time. When 
it was suggested that this attitude left Christians at the mercy of 
every rogue and brutal tyrant, Luther replied that the Govern- 
ment ought to see that this did not happen, and that if it failed to 
prevent it, then certainly the Christian must simply suffer for it. 
Thus everywhere Lutheranism came under the influence of the 
dominant authority. The yielding spirit of its wholly interior 
spirituality adapted itself to the dominant authority of the day. 
This meant, however, that the form Lutheranism took was con- 
trolled by the various forms of government with which it was 
connected. It had no theoretical tendency towards monarchism or 
absolutism at all 805 ; this theory was only an invention of the 
modern Conservatives. It was only because absolutism and the 
system of manorial estates arose in Central and North Germany 
that it there developed the loyal spirit which characterizes 
Ostelbiertum .* In the Imperial towns it glorified aristocratic- 
republican rule. In Wiirttemberg, where there was no corre- 
sponding nobility, although it held the ruling prince in all honour, 
it did not hinder bourgeois and peasant democratic ideas, but 
even fused itself with them. In the military national State of 
Sweden it justified the aggressive policy of Gustavus Adolfus, and 
in the class struggles in the Austrian territories it justified the rise 
of the Lutheran nobility 306 ; in Denmark and Norway a very 
firmly established peasant democracy is to-day united most closely 

304 Cf. on the whole subject, Troeltsch: Die Bedeutung des Protestantismus fur die 
Entstehung der modernen Welt , igo6 (see also Hist. %eitschrift , 1905). Haendtke 
shows the severance of general civilization from the specific Lutheran presup- 
positions while retaining their formulas. 

805 Cf. Brandenburg , p. 18. Luther replied to the question why God has created 
authorities of so many different kinds by saying: “Is God obliged to give 
chapter and verse to such useless fools why He wants to have it thus?” Also 
radical monarchical Divine Right as is taught by Horn in his Politicorum pars 
architectonica de civitate Traj. a. Rh., 1664 (analysed by von Gierke: Althusius , a 
p. jo f.) is not genuinely Lutheran, but it has grown up out of opposition to 
the Calvinistic doctrine of contract and is filled with the ideas of princely 
absolutism. 

* Translator. — I.e. the Nationalist spirit, which is the distinctive feature 
of the landed aristocracy in the agricultural districts east of the Elbe. 

806 Thus, for example, Bernhard von Weimar was able to justify from the religious 
point of view his brigandage as “a royal calling” ( Haendtke f p . 19). Gustavus 
Adolfus was politically an admirer of the quite un-Lutheran Hugo Grotius , 
whose jfoief work he always carried about with him ; H. G. : Recht des Krieges und 
Friedens y Phil . Bibl. /j, p. 8. 



PROTESTANTISM 


575 

with a sturdy Lutheranism, which is certainly tinged with Pietism ; 
and in America the most orthodox Lutheranism one can imagine 
flourishes under the wing of democracy. 

We must, however, admit that by its very nature Lutheranism 
adapts itself most easily to political conditions of a monarchical 
and aristocratic kind, and to an economic social situation which 
is predominantly agrarian and middle class. Hence it has found 
its strongest form of expression in the politics and world-outlook 
of the Prussian and German Conservatives, through whom to-day 
Lutheranism still helps to determine the destinies of the German 
people. 

Social and Political Significance of Lutheranism 

In the aggressive position which, after the eighteenth century 
had culminated in the French Revolution, the older spiritual 
forces again adopted towards the modern world, and in which 
they, with the union of ideological and practical politico-social 
powers, advanced victoriously against the new world, the restora- 
tion of Prussian-German Lutheranism was one of the most im- 
portant events in social history . 307 It united with the reactionary 
movement the monarchical ideas of agrarian patriarchalism, 
of the militaristic love of power ; it gave an ideal to the political 
Restoration and its ethical support. For this reason, then, it in its 
turn was supported by the social and political forces of reaction, 
by all the means of power at their disposal. Finally, Lutheranism 
of this type hallowed the realistic sense of power, and the 
ethical virtues of obedience, reverence, and respect for authority, 
which are indispensable to Prussian militarism. Thus Christianity 
and a Conservative political attitude became identified with each 
other, as well as piety and love of power, purity of doctrine, and 
the glorification of war and the aristocratic standpoint. Thus all 
attempts at Church reform were suppressed along with the world 
of Liberal thought; the representatives of modern social and 
spiritual tendencies were forced into an attitude of strong hostility 
to the Church, and all whose sympathies were Christian and 
religious were enlisted on the Conservative side. As an essential 
element in the forces of the Restoration, Lutheranism played an 
important part in the political and military development of 
German Prussia which arose out of the forces of the Restoration ; 
and it was thus in violent opposition to all those other elements 
which worked together to produce a new Germany, the demo- 
cratic-union elements and modem social and economic Vnove- 

»” Sec p. 878. , 



576 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

ments. Along with the international Catholic Restoration policy 
which was akin to it, and yet so very different from it, and with 
which it is in contact, sometimes friendly, sometimes hostile — 
Lutheranism occupies the key position of the mpst difficult and 
pregnant problems affecting the life of Germany, and does its 
part towards widening the gulf between the forces which support 
the patriarchalism of the Restoration and those which support 
the cause of democracy and progress, a gulf in which all moderate 
attempts at reconciliation are drowned ; the longing to bridge over 
this gulf in Germany with a Christian-Social programme was 
an idealistic and praiseworthy but fleeting and swiftly refuted 
dream. 

For the great majority of orthodox Christians in Germany the 
traditions and the spiritual constitution of Lutheranism made any 
such reconciliation impossible; and on the other hand, the un- 
restrained hatred towards the Church which characterized all 
progressive and democratic elements belonging to that group of 
movements also made any kind of union impossible. Thus Luther- 
anism naturally does little towards building up a new social 
structure. In the main its efforts are confined to the philanthropic 
activity of the Home Mission Movement ; otherwise its tendency 
is to alleviate but not to re-create. Wherever the Christian-Social 
ethic and social policy strikes out in another direction we may be 
sure that other influences are at work than those of genuine 
Lutheranism. As a rule these influences are due to Calvinism, and 
thus we come to the second great confessional structure of Pro- 
testantism: Calvinism. 


3. CALVINISM 

Calvinism and Lutheranism contrasted 

After a period of initial success Lutheranism ceased to advance. 
This must be attributed, in the main, to its stress on personal 
piety, its acceptance of the existing situation, its acquiescence 
in the objectivity of the means of grace, as well as to its lack 
of capacity for ecclesiastical organization, and its non-political 
outlook. It was the destiny of Calvinism to extend the Reforma- 
tion of the Church throughout Western Europe, and thence out 
into the New World, and, actually, Calvinism is the chief force 
in the Protestant world to-day. 

Tty, primary reason for this wide-spread extension of Calvinism 
was the fact that it gained a footing among the Western nations 



PROTESTANTISM 


577 


at a time when they were passing through a great process of 
political development. There is, however, a deeper reason, and 
one which lies within the essence of Calvinism itself, which 
explains why it almost or entirely crowded out the rudimentary 
beginnings of Lutheranism and of the Anabaptist movement, 
which were also present in those lands. This deeper reason lies 
in the active character of Calvinism, in its power for forming 
Churches, in its international contacts, and its conscious impulse 
towards expansion, and, most of all, in its capacity to penetrate 
the political and economic movements of Western nations with its 
religious ideal, a capacity which Lutheranism lacked from the 
very beginning . 308 

Thus the social doctrines of Calvinism and its conception of 
the Church also differed considerably from those of Lutheran- 
ism. In course of time this difference became more and more 
pronounced, with the result that at the present day Calvinism 
feels itself to be the only Christian ecclesiastical body which is in 
agreement with the modern democratic and capitalistic develop- 
ment, and, moreover, the only one which is suited to it . 300 In 
spite of the fact that originally it was very closely connected 
with Lutheranism, Calvinism — while retaining its orthodoxy — 
has gradually become the very opposite of Lutheranism, with 
its State Church character, its institutionalism, and its conser- 
vatism. 

From the political and social point of view the significance of 
Lutheranism for the modern history of civilization lies in its 
connection with the reactionary parties; from the religious and 
scientific standpoint its significance lies in the development of a 
philosophical theology, which is blended with a religious mysti- 
cism and “inward” spirituality, but which, from the ethical 
point of view, is quite remote from the problems of modern 
political and social life. 

Calvinism, on the other hand (in more recent times under 
the influence of Pietism and Methodism to which it is closely 
akin), has, upon the whole, maintained its unphilosophical 
theology, or at least after the disturbances of the Enlighten- 
ment it rediscovered it. In its close connection with English and 
American racial peculiarities and institutions, however, it has 
merged with and to some extent produced that political and 
social way of life which may be described as “Americanism”. 
It is obvious that to-day this “Americanism” has an independent 
existence, which is almost entirely divorced from a religioi^ basis 


•°* See p. 879. 
VOL. 11. 


909 See p. 879. 


1 



578 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

of any kind . 810 Calvinism has, however, also had a reflex influence 
upon the Continent of Europe. It has influenced Lutheranism 
not only in the conception and constitution of the Church, in 
the life of Christian social activity and fellowship initiated by 
the Church, in Home Missions, in Pietism, but, as a universal 
spiritual force, the type of humanity which it produces affects 
the whole of European civilization ; for the most part, however, 
this civilization is entirely unconscious of its original connection 
with Calvinism. During this process of development, Calvinism 
came into touch with the sects, which, as will become evident 
later on, tended to approach Calvinism along their own line. 
Together with the sects, and in co-operation with political and 
social conditions, Calvinism has produced that particular type 
of humanity which has just been described. This will become 
fully evident when we have studied the question of the sect- 
type within the sphere of Protestantism. Yet it is important to 
call attention to this fact here, in order that we may take into 
account that particular point in Calvinism at which, in its main 
ideas, it came into closer or more permanent touch with the 
sect-type than was the case with Luther (of course, I am alluding 
only to his earlier period). 

Calvinism has developed into a very widespread movement, 
which has expanded far beyond its beginnings at Geneva. In 
order to understand Calvinism, therefore, our primary task is to 
distinguish the primitive Calvinism of Geneva from its later 
forms of development. At the outset, however, we must ask the 
following questions. To what extent are these later develop- 
ments the logical outcome of primitive Calvinism? How far do 
they transcend it? and what were the causes which led to this 
development? 

In such great questions, which are connected with the whole 
history of civilization, from the very outset it is clear that develop- 
ments of that kind were not influenced merely by the logical 
dialectic and impelling energy of the religious idea, but also by 
the particular historical situation at any given time. On the other 
hand, Calvinism is such a magnificent austere intellectual system 
that we arc bound to try to discover the inner intellectual connec- 
tion which either persists through all these changes or is restored 
by them . 811 

810 On this point cf. Rauschenbusch: Christianity and the Social Crisis , New York, igo 8 . 
Hundeshagen describes the astonishment of an American student who thought 
that in Germany Christianity was a science, while in America it was a practical 
matter. 811 See p. 879. 



PROTESTANTISM 


579 


Primitive Calvinism 

Thus our first task is to analyse the distinctive religious content 
of primitive Calvinism, upon which was logically constructed 
the edifice of its conception of the Church, its ethic, and its social 
ideals. Only when that has been accomplished can we inquire 
into the later development of Calvinism, and the changes which 
have taken place in later Calvinism, in the political, economic, 
social, and ecclesiastico-political sphere. 

Primitive Calvinism is the daughter of Lutheranism. Originally 
it had no other desire than to be purely Lutheran, both from the 
theological and the religious point of view, part of a great united 
Protestant body, able to absorb all fanatical movements into 
its own life. In its second phase, under the influence of Bucer, 
it assimilated the element of truth contained in the Anabaptist 
movement, i.e. the practical social development of the con- 
gregation, and in so doing it also came into contact with the 
Reformation in Switzerland. Early Calvinism secured the 
Lutheran doctrine of the sacraments against Zwingli by making 
certain concessions, and yet it preserved their original meaning 
intact. Finally, in union with the Upper Germans, it completed 
the strict purification of public worship from all Catholic cere- 
monies, at which point it came into agreement with Zwingli ; all 
it aimed at, however, in this connection, was to carry out more 
logically Luther’s principle of obedience to the Word of God. 
While Calvin was insisting on the strictest purity and unity of 
doctrine in Geneva itself, he still believed that by making certain 
concessions on questions which were not vital to the main principle 
he would be able to unite the various countries and Churches in 
one great united Protestant body. It was only the resistance 
of German Lutheranism, and the independence of Anglicanism, 
which forced Calvinism to become an independent Protestant 
Church . 312 

Thus, the central element in Calvin’s theology and piety was 
of Lutheran origin. Calvin always laid great stress upon his 
agreement with Luther, and upon his personal relations with 
him. He considered Luther the Reformer par excellence , but he 
was not greatly attracted by Zwingli, and he treated him with 
reserve. Calvin owed his conversion essentially to Lutheran 
influences, and he also made use of Lutheran literature. So far 
as the other influences in his life are concerned — the Humanistic 
theology of the Reform, the Swiss purification of the Ghurch, 

See p. 880. 



580 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

and the ecclesiastical-social reform and union policy of Strass- 
burg — he himself ascribed all that was really essential to Luther. 
His Lutheranism was certainly of the Upper German, and 
particularly of the Strassburg, kind, coloured by Bucer’s union 
tendencies, the conditions in the city itself, the competition of the 
Anabaptists, and the influence of the neighbouring inhabitants 
of Zurich, but it was Lutheranism none the less. 

The fundamental doctrines of Luther were therefore also 
the fundamental doctrines of Galvin. Calvin held firmly the 
Lutheran doctrines of justification and sanctification; indeed, 
of all the Reformers, he actually expressed them in their purest 
systematic form. Over against the absolute corruption caused by 
sin and the helplessness of the natural man, he proclaims the 
certainty of the forgiveness of sins and of the Divine Mercy freely 
given by God in Christ, and the transformation of the soul into 
joyful communion with God, with moral power and strength to 
undertake active labour in the service of God. Further, just as 
with Luther, this doctrine of justification and sanctification is 
firmly embodied in the framework of the idea of the Church. 
It is only completed through the agency of the Church as an 
organ of salvation, endowed with the objective means of grace 
in the Word and the sacraments; everywhere the Church only 
produces subjective and personal religious life by means of the 
Scriptures, and of the Christ revealed in Scriptures. 

The main features of the Calvinistic religious system may then 
be summed up as follows: a strict insistence upon the Church 
as the organ which mediates salvation ; a very strong and definite 
emphasis upon the sacraments as objective Divine means of grace; 
the fact of the vital connection between Calvinism and the 
Primitive Church (contrasted with the apostasy of the Papacy) ; 
the logical establishment of the Church upon the Bible, as the 
supernatural element which creates faith, and also proves its 
supernatural origin by creating fellowship ; the catholicity of the 
Church wherever the Word and the sacraments have been 
preserved, even under the veil of error and false ceremonies; a 
universal and uniform dominion of the truth of the Church within 
the sphere which it can win and control ; the theocratic union of 
Church and State, and the compulsory enforcement of the “pure 
doctrine”, at least externally ; the closest union between Church 
and State, while allowing each to retain its fundamentally distinct 
character ; the acceptance of secular culture and the penetration 
of the^system of “callings” belonging to the realm of Natural 
Law, with the Christian spirit ; the identification of the Decalogue 



PROTESTANTISM 581 

with the Law of Nature and the approximation of positive law 
to both ; and, last of all, its conception of the Church itself. 

All these ideas Calvin adopted as finished products, and his 
system was therefore free from the fluctuations amidst which 
Luther first of all worked out these conceptions, and he shaped 
them with the doctrinaire logic which is peculiar to men of a 
second generation, due to their sense of possessing a secure 
inheritance . 313 

Distinctive Features of Primitive Calvinism 

Thus all the distinctive features of Calvinism have only been 
evolved out of the main stock of the ideal which it holds in 
common with Lutheranism. That, however, does not imply 
that these features are unimportant; on the contrary, they are 
original, and of the highest significance. These peculiarly Calvin- 
istic elements turned the religious thought of Protestantism into 
a new channel, and it is not difficult to understand why this new 
tendency was finally rejected by Lutheranism, whose outlook 
was so entirely different. The essential differences lie within the 
sphere of the Idea of God, of the fundamental, religious, and 
ethical attitude which that involves, and finally in the sphere of 
the peculiar conception of social duty which this implies. 

(I) Doctrine of Predestination 

The first distinctive feature of Calvinism, and the most im- 
portant one, is the idea of predestination, the famous central 
doctrine of Calvinism. It is the expression — gradually formulated 
and finally strongly emphasized — of Calvin’s peculiar idea of 
God. In this matter also Galvin is the disciple of Luther, and the 
doctrine of predestination is primarily only the logical and 
systematic emphasis upon the main aspect of Lutheran doctrine, 
which is also a central point in Pauline doctrine, and which, 
in his strict obedience to the Bible, he regarded as a directly 
obligatory article of faith. It constitutes that particular element 
in Lutheran doctrine by which the purity of the Reformed 
Faith was protected against any admixture with the alloy of 
human ideas and opinions. Faith is not a human faculty at all, 
it is a perception given by God as an absolute miracle ; at the 
same time the human element in the shape of all human “merit” 
and all “natural” human activity is excluded, while the emphasis 
on “grace” in a religion based on faith is fully preserved. 

Thus, at first sight, Calvin’s doctrine of predestination ^seems 

«*See p. 881. 


» 



582 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

to owe its significance only to the inferior acuteness of a disciple 
who has systematized his master’s teaching and has thus mani- 
fested the driving force of the motive behind the whole system. 
But Calvin was more than a disciple or a mere imitator of Luther. 

Behind his doctrine of predestination there lay also that idea 
of God which was the peculiar element in his own personal piety. 
In the idea of predestination Calvin is not merely trying to 
discover and formulate the absolute miracle of salvation, its 
supernatural character, and the fact that it is a pure gift of free 
grace (its “givenness”) ; he is also trying to express the character 
of God as absolute sovereign will. 

Calvin’s idea of grace is that of pure unmerited grace, and is 
not in any way concerned with any thought of justice which the 
creature, in its misery, might desire to claim from the Lord of the 
World. It is the Nature of God to give salvation to some without 
any merit on their part, purely out of His own freewill and choice, 
and to prepare destruction for others on account of their sinfulness. 
No one has any right either to boast or to complain. Just as no 
one can choose whether he will be a human being or an animal, 
so no one has any right to claim to belong to the “elect” rather 
than to the “damned”. God’s majestic sovereign will is the 
supreme cause, the supreme standard. The reasons and norms 
which do exist gain their significance only from God; there are 
none which can be applied to Him, or to which He must bow. 
In entire and arbitrary freedom He lays down the law for Him- 
self; and this law is the law of His own glory which is served both 
by the gratitude of the undeserved bliss of the elect and by the 
misery of the merited despair of the damned. This means that 
no longer, as in Lutheranism, is the idea of Love at the centre of 
the conception of God, but the idea of Majesty, in which the 
impartation and influence of the Love of God is only regarded as 
a method of revealing the Majesty of God. According to this 
conception God did not create the world out of a sense of need 
for the responsive love of His creatures ; His world-plan has not 
been disturbed by the freewill of the creature, and salvation 
does not consist in the restoration of universal beatitude to all 
creatures through the miracle of redemption. Rather it is the 
inscrutable Will of God which is the basis of the world, and the 
cause of its whole course. God ordained the sin of Adam, and 
he makes use both of sinners and of those who are justified in 
His world-economy ; the elect are a symbol of His mercy, which 
bestows all that is good merely through the exercise of His Will, 
and the damned serve as a symbol of His wrath against all that is 



PROTESTANTISM 


5B3 

unhallowed and evil. To Calvin the chief point is not the self- 
centred personal salvation of the creature, and the universality 
of the Divine Will of Love, but it is the Glory of God, which is 
equally exalted in the holy activity of the elect and in the futile 
rage of the reprobate. In His Gospel God offers His grace to all, 
but in the same Gospel He proclaims the duality of His counsel 
of election and of reprobation, to which reason must submit 
without making any attempts to harmonize these two aspects of 
the truth. 

Luther also had thus distinguished between the hidden and 
the revealed God, but in the end Luther held to the revealed God 
of the New Testament, and gave up speculation. Calvin retained 
it, and in so doing he transformed the whole idea of God . 314 

This new conception of God contains a wealth of implications. 
From the outset it frees Calvinism from all the problems of the 
Theodicy which weigh so heavily upon Lutheranism, and which, 
while holding fast to the universality of the will of grace, lead 
again and again to the problem of the righteousness of God, 
and make salvation dependent upon the receptive will of the 
creature. Within this conception there is room for different 
purposes of God to exist alongside of each other; He reveals 
Himself in the Gratia universalis , in all the gifts of reason, and in 
the beauty of the world, in the elect and in the non-elect, and in 
all these gifts He does not need to limit His purpose solely to 
redemption; He reveals Himself in pains and penalties, which 
are not merely means of education, purification, and expansion, 
but which are decreed by His Sovereign Will in order to represent 
His wrath, to steel the courage of His saints, and to prove the 
nothingness of the material world ; He reveals Himself most 
intimately, though not exclusively, in the bliss of those who are 
justified, who may have unlimited confidence in God, who, 
however, must also serve Him without reserve. 

Although in his correspondence Calvin expounds with ardour 
the ways of Divine Providence, this does not mean that he is 
trying to “justify the ways of God to men” ; his aim is simply to 
prove how God is guiding, testing, and saving the Church; to 
heroism of this kind suffering, in itself, is no problem at all . 315 
This idea of God is not drawn from the Old Testament, except, 
perhaps, indirectly through Paul. It is the unique product of 
Calvin’s own mind, to which, certainly, certain elements in the 
thought of the Old Testament were congenial. 

A further result of this conception of God is the practical and 
814 See p. 883. 815 See p. 883. 



584 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

ethical intention which it gives to the idea of justification ; for 
justification does not mean a quietistic repose in thankful happi- 
ness, but a method of activity and a spur to action. The Will, 
with which the soul has to do, is active ; it is not simply the Mercy 
which forgives sins. God creates, and grants in election, the 
assurance of the forgiveness of sins, in order that the soul which 
has been set free from guilt may serve Him as an instrument 
of His Will. Through justification the elect are made members 
of the Body of Christ, penetrated with the active spirit of Christ ; 
they become Christ’s warriors and champions, subjects in His 
Kingdom. The proof of justification does not consist in inwardness 
and depth of feeling, but in energy and the logical result of action. 
In Lutheranism the real proof and verification of justification is 
that happiness which the world cannot give, which reaches its 
highest point in close connection with the Christ who substantially 
unites Himself in the Eucharist with the believer in the Unio mystica , 
in a mystical union with God. 

In Calvinism, with its emphasis upon the transcendence of God, 
such a proof could not be imagined ; union with God can only be 
understood in the sense of surrender to the electing and renewing 
will of God, and as an activity of the ever active (“ actuosen ”) God 
in the believer, which indeed in the Eucharist results in an 
actual union with the exalted Christ, but only in spirit, since 
communion with Christ is not one of substance at all, but it 
means being absorbed into the active and effectual spirit of 
Christ. “ Finitum non est capax infinite is the principle of Calvinism, 
and that gives both to the idea of justification and to that of faith 
a different psychological meaning: instead of the characteristic 
of happiness in the grace of God which forgives sins, we find the 
certainty of belonging to the elect, and a spirit of active energy . 316 

It is impossible to describe here in further detail the way in 
which these views changed the whole colour of the body of 
theology which Calvinism held in common with Lutheranism . 317 
It is, however, significant that from this time forward the whole 
body of doctrine, the “pure doctrine” itself, in spite of its ortho- 
doxy, gained a quite different position in the whole intellectual 
system. To the Lutheran, salvation and blessedness become 
objective in the “pure doctrine” (which alone can produce these 
effects), which is also the heart of the ecclesiastical institution, 

816 This characteristic, above all, has been very well developed by Schnecken - 
burger and continued by Max Weber: Archiv. XXI y pp. 21-25. 

817 This has been done in a masterly way, although perhaps almost too com- 
pletely, by Schneckenburger . 



PROTESTANTISM 


585 

and the one objective element in Christianity. To the Calvinist, 
in addition to the “pure doctrine”, there is the moral law, as 
the expression of grace and discipline, as the expression of the 
active Divine Will. To the Calvinist the creative centre of the 
Church is the “pure doctrine 5 ’, combined with a Divinely revealed 
discipline. In Calvin’s mind God cannot reveal Himself solely 
in purity of doctrine; He must also manifest His active and 
creative nature as an energy of will. Purity of doctrine, therefore, 
is not, as in Lutheranism, the exclusive concern of the Church, 
since, to the Lutheran, purity of doctrine guarantees purity of 
faith, and with this all else comes naturally. The “pure doctrine” 
is not an end in itself, but, just as faith is the presupposition of 
right action, so also pure doctrine is only a presupposition and 
a means to some further end. That means certainly that, as 
well as the systematic statement of aim which characterises 
Calvinism, there is also a theoretical development in doctrine 
which extends beyond the requirements of Lutheranism; but 
the doctrine which is developed, in spite of all its system and its 
comprehensiveness, still remains a means to an end, the pre- 
supposition of that which is really valuable — of Christian conduct. 
This explains why Calvinism, with its severe logic and its accept- 
ance of the culture of Western Europe, maintains a far higher 
intellectual standard than Lutheranism, and yet lays far less 
emphasis on doctrine and on system. To Calvin, God is irrational 
in the sense that He is not to be measured by the standards of 
human reason and logic. God, he teaches, gave us reason to 
aid us in our work in the world, and for the glory of God. Thus 
the keenest and the most cultivated intellect, and the clearest 
formulation of doctrine, are only of use as tools for purposes which 
are above the grasp of the intellect and as a preparation for 
action . 318 

Finally, we must note yet another ultimate effect of this idea 
of God which has had a considerable influence upon practical 
ethics: the altered conception of the Bible, the source of, and 
the authority for, the “pure doctrine”. The sovereign Will of God 
made known in election, and in the preparation of a community 
of the elect, does not manifest itself merely in the spirit of love 
and in the atoning sacrifice of the love of Christ, which, as the 
very heart of the Bible, is seized and isolated by the faith which 
experiences its power in such a way that the rest of the Bible 
seems comparatively insignificant, or at least it merely serves the 
purpose of pointing forward to Christ. Rather the revelation of 

818 See p. 883. 



586 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

the sovereign predestination of God is, as a whole, a positive 
revelation of will, a law of faith and of morals. Since the predomi- 
nant idea in the Calvinistic conception of God is not love, but 
majesty, holiness, sovereign power, and grace, so also the Bible is 
regarded less as a means of attaining the assurance of the love 
of God which forgives sins than a manifestation which should 
create a community in which the glory of God will be realized, 
which will also result in the overthrow of evil men and of repro- 
bates. To Protestants of the second generation it seemed quite 
natural to give the Bible an abstract independent position ; this 
was a logical effect of Luther’s attitude to the Bible, in which it 
constituted the final court of appeal. In Calvinism, therefore, 
the Bible, regarded as that which had been founded by the anti- 
rational positive Will of God, then became, further, a law, 
whose aim and nature were of equal value in every part, in 
which both the Old Testament and the New Testament bear the 
common official character of revelation, and in which the only 
distinction between them lies in the fact that certain Old Testa- 
ment elements have been explicitly discarded by the New Testa- 
ment. In Calvinism, therefore, the Old Testament attains a higher 
and more independent position. 

Since the Calvinistic Idea of God is in many ways similar to 
the Idea ofjahweh whose Being is Will, the necessities of practical 
life led to an increasing use of the Old Testament, as we shall see 
directly. This development, however, meant that the Calvinistic 
Theocracy became a Divine covenant with the Church upon the 
basis of revelation, in which the State is to serve the Church after 
the manner of the Kings of Israel, and in which public life is 
controlled by the pastors after the manner of the Prophets. Thus 
wc may sum up the Gospel of Calvin in the following terms : a 
new Israel has been born, a new holy city has been founded, 
established upon the Divine Law, which has been deepened by 
the spirit of the New Testament, directed by the Will and the 
Grace of God which deals out punishments and rewards, elected 
to be the organ for the glorification of Christ, the God-man, in 
whom the hidden electing will has become flesh, with power to 
create the community of the Church. 

Here, as at several other points, there emerges a certain resem- 
blance to the Baptists, which will occupy our attention a good 
deal from time to time. The Calvinistic doctrines of predestina- 
tion and salvation are, of course, poles apart from the Baptist 
doctrine of freedom, but the idea of the Bible which produces 
the idea of predestination comes very near to the Baptist concep- 



PROTESTANTISM 


587 

tion of the Bible. The Baptists held the same view of the Bible as 
the moral law, and they also considered the constitution of the 
Primitive Church to be the ideal Church constitution. The basis 
of Calvin’s argument is certainly very different from that of the 
Baptists. He does not share their desire to found a new and entirely 
different religious community instead of the Church. His one 
desire was to effect a radical reform of the Church in harmony 
with the teaching of the Scriptures, and for this he found Scrip- 
tural authority in a conception of God which was directed at the 
same time towards the creation of a Church which is Scriptural, 
pure, and holy. In so doing, however, he went beyond the idea 
of the Church as the organ of salvation, based purely upon itself, 
and came into contact with the leading ideas of the Baptist 
movement. He came very near to their Scriptural purism. The 
Lutherans were only interested in the Bible to the extent in which 
it was concerned with the Church as the organ of grace, the 
forgiveness of sins, and the work of Christ upon which all this is 
based, and in this respect certainly they often used the Bible as 
a law which regulates doctrine. Beyond that point, however, 
they felt no need to make it into a law. Calvinism, however, did 
feel this need. It extended the authority of the Bible over a 
wider field, and in the process it transformed the whole concep- 
tion of the Bible into an infallible authority for all the problems 
and needs of the Church. Lutheranism controlled the doctrine 
which it had evolved out of inward experience by the Bible; 
Calvinism sought to renew the whole of Christianity, in doctrine 
and the Church, in ethics and in dogma, solely through the Bible. 
Its greater reforming radicalism was due to this fact, and to 
the active character of its religion, which was based upon the 
doctrine of election . 319 

(II) Individualism 

Thus as Calvinism has developed the Lutheran doctrine of 
predestination, and of the idea of God, in a fresh light, the same 
development also took place in its second distinctive character- 
istic — that of religious individualism. Luther was always ultimately 
concerned with the individual’s assurance of salvation, and his 
happiness, flowing from the forgiveness of sins ; everything else, 
however, is merely the overflow which radiates from union with 
God, it is only a natural result, not an essential end. 

Calvin’s view is different. He also emphasizes the need for 
inwardness and the purely personal individual character of all 

»• See p. 884. 



588 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

piety. He also rejects a faith that is based merely on dogma and 
authority, and discards all ideas of sacramentarian magic; he 
also teaches that the new life must spring from faith. But since 
to him the central point of religion is not the blessedness of the 
creature, but the Glory of God, so also the glorification of God in 
action is the real test of individual personal reality in religion. 
In Calvin’s view the individual is not satisfied with mere repose 
in his own happiness, or perhaps with giving himself to others 
in loving personal service; further, he is not satisfied with an 
attitude of mere passive endurance and toleration of the world 
in which he lives, without entering fully into its life. He feels that, 
on the contrary, the whole meaning of life consists precisely in 
entering into these circumstances, and, while inwardly rising 
above them, in shaping them into an expression of the Divine 
Will. In conflict and in labour the individual takes up the task 
of the sanctification of the world, always with the certainty, 
however, that he will not lose himself in the life of the world ; for 
indeed in everything the individual is only working out the 
meaning of election, which indeed consists in being strengthened 
to perform actions of this kind. 

Within Lutheranism a position of this kind would be untenable, 
for Lutheranism believes that it is possible to fall away from the 
state of grace. This is the point at which there is the greatest 
divergence of opinion between the two aspects of religious indi- 
vidualism, which characterize the Protestant religion of faith 
and sentiment. Lutheranism does not think out the doctrine of 
predestination to its logical conclusion, i.e. the impossibility of 
losing the state of grace. The reason for this lies in the fact that 
from the very outset the one aim of Lutheranism is to secure the 
monergism of grace in all that is good, while it teaches that evil 
is due to the human will alone. Thus the supreme concern of the 
Lutheran is the preservation of faith and of the state of grace, a 
constantly renewed effort to maintain intact the purity and 
stability of a faith which is independent of “works” or “merit”. 
Hence all the emphasis is placed upon the cultivation of the emo- 
tional life of the individual, on the maintenance of the sense of 
an unmerited happiness, and the Christian ethic is regarded 
merely as the preservation of the state of grace, which can be 
lost either by falling into grave sin, or by relying upon one’s own 
strength. 

Calvinism, however, does not believe that the individual can 
ever lose the state of grace, and therefore it has no trace of this 
fear of losing grace. Hence it does not need to lower the tone of 



PROTESTANTISM 


589 

the religious life to the level of self-preservation in the state of 
grace, and it feels that a constant preoccupation with personal 
moods and feelings is entirely unnecessary. The Calvinist knows 
that his calling and election are sure, and that therefore he is 
free to give all his attention to the effort to mould the world and 
society according to the Will of God. He does not need to cling 
to God lest he should lose Him ; on the contrary, he knows that 
he himself is absolutely dependent upon God’s sustaining grace. 
His duty, therefore, is not to preserve the “new creation” in its 
intimacy with God, but to reveal it. 

Thus from all sides the individualism of the “Reformed”* 
Church was impelled towards activity ; the individual was drawn 
irresistibly into a whole-hearted absorption in the tasks of service 
to the world and to society, to a life of unceasing, penetrating, 
and formative labour. This does not mean merely that Galvin- 
istic individualism in its austerity and reserve is more firmly 
established upon a basis of religious metaphysics ; still more im- 
portant is the fact that it does not suffer from constant breakdowns 
and reactions like those which characterize the Lutheran way 
of life, and rivet the attention of Lutheranism again and again 
simply to the fact of the forgiveness of sins. Calvinism organizes 
the work of preservation logically and systematically, straight- 
forwardly and with a clear aim in view. Above all, however, 
this specifically Calvinistic individualism possesses this peculiar 
characteristic that in its refusal to expand on the emotional side, 
and in its habit of placing confidence in God in the foreground 
and all human relations in the background, in going out of itself 
it always directs its attention towards concrete aims and purposes. 
Cfalvin’s correspondence reveals an amazing objectivity and 
personal reserve, combined with an unceasing gathering together 
of all for the purposes of the Christian community. As an “elect” 
person the individual has no value of his own, but as an instru- 
ment, to be used for the tasks of the Kingdom of God, his value is 
immense. 

This individualism differs not only from Catholic and Lutheran 
individualism, but also from the optimistic, rationalistic indi- 
vidualism of the Enlightenment. Founded upon a crushing sense 
of sin, and a pessimistic condemnation of the world, without 
colour or emotional satisfaction, it is an individualism based 
upon the certainty of election, the sense of responsibility and of 
the obligation to render personal service under the Lordship of 

* The term * ‘Reformed* * is used throughout this book in the technical sense of 
“Calvinistic. — Translator’s Note. 

4 

4 



590 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Christ. It finds its expression in the thoughtful and self-conscious 
type of Calvinistic piety, in the systematic spirit of self-control, 
and in its independence of all that is “creaturely”. The value of 
the individual depends wholly upon the merciful grace of election, 
and it may give honour to none save God alone. This leads to 
the result that against a background of the severest self-con- 
demnation there stands out in clear relief in Calvinism the sense 
of being a spiritual aristocracy ; this produces a detached and 
aloof manner of handling all that is secular and creaturely, solely 
with reference to their secular purposes, which extends into all 
merely secular and natural personal relationships. 

Calvin’s successors, however — both in the sphere of theology 
and of practical pastoral work — were soon faced with this ques- 
tion, which became more and more insistent as time went on: 
How is it possible to be certain that one is of the number of the 
elect? From the time of Beza the current reply was that the fact 
of election was proved by good works, which are outward signs of 
the inward state of grace. This idea, which was developed more 
and more explicitly as time went on, drove the individual (who, 
in Lutheranism could rely on the objective means of grace) to 
the practice of self-examination and to systematic concentration 
on his own independent achievement. This tended to make the 
individual increasingly egocentric, and it also produced a strained 
intensity in the pursuit Of the utmost possible perfection. Under 
certain circumstances this spirit approaches legalism and per- 
fectionism; ultimately, although the effect of election is most 
strictly bound up with the Church, the Scriptures, and the Sacra- 
ments, it makes the individual independent of the Church, and 
assurance, like election, becomes entirely a matter for the indi- 
vidual to ascertain. Without intending to do so, however, this 
individualism had developed an individualistic independence of 
the Church, which bore some resemblance to the individualism 
of the sect-type. The severe self-control, based on the standard 
of the Bible, which is characteristic of Calvinism, is also akin to 
the sect-type, in spite of the fact that the whole idea is steeped 
in the ideas of the Church and of grace ; this self-control is attained 
again and again by ascribing all individual personality and its 
achievements to the working out of predestination . 320 

(Ill) The “Holy Community” 

The third distinctive characteristic of Calvinism — the central 
significance of the idea of a society, and the task of the restoration 

880 See p. 884. 



PROTESTANTISM 


59i 


of a holy community, of a Christocracy in which God is glorified 
in all its activity, both sacred and secular — seems to be opposed 
to this kind of individualism. This idea of a “holy community”, 
however, has not been evolved out of the conception of the Church 
and of grace, like the Lutheran ecclesiastical idea ; on the contrary, 
it springs out of the same principle which appears to give inde- 
pendence to the individual, namely, out of the ethical duty of the 
preservation and making effective of election, and out of the 
abstract exaltation of the Scriptures. 

To Calvin the Church is not merely an organ of salvation 
which provides the objective means of grace, from which every- 
thing else should develop as a logical result, and from the stand- 
point of which the ungodliness of the world must be supported in 
patience and humility. The organ of salvation ought rather at the 
same time to provide the means of sanctification; it ought to 
prove itself effective in the Christianizing of the community, by 
placing the whole range of life under the control of Christian 
regulations and Christian purposes. At the same time it ought 
to develop the necessary organs by means of which the com- 
munity can be moulded by the Divine Spirit and the Divine Word, 
in every aspect of life : in Church and State, in the family and in 
society, in economic life, and in all personal relationships, both 
public and private. 

This theory represents the final development of ideas, which 
Luther had suggested during the years of ferment and of local 
reforms, but which he was obliged to drop for lack of real Christians 
to carry them out. Calvin’s aim, however, was somewhat different 
from that of Luther ; it was also more practicable. In this question 
'Luther, with his emphasis upon freedom and personality, was 
mainly concerned with the logical results of the principle of the 
priesthood of all believers — i.e. with the autonomous adminis- 
tration and self-government of the community ; the community 
could, of course, at the same time evolve the means of self-control 
and discipline, but all was to be done in complete freedom. But, 
just because his main concern was the universal priesthood of 
believers, he drew back from realizing his principle through the 
revolutionary democratic movement, and contented himself 
merely with ensuring the proclamation of pure doctrine by de- 
pendence upon the territorial Princes. Calvin, however, was not 
concerned with the priesthood of believers, but with making the 
control and the purity of the Church effective . 821 He was so 

82J Cf. Rieker , pp. 133 ff, (he is very good on this point) ; also Kostlin: Stud, und 
Krit ., 1 868, p. 483. 



59a THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

deeply convinced that this was necessary that he did not doubt 
that, just as in the case of doctrine, the Scriptures would provide 
him with the necessary support and counsel. Thus, in precisely 
the same way that Luther deduced his doctrine from the Bible, 
Calvin also evolved his theory of the constitution and Christian 
organization of the Church from the Scriptures. In his view the 
Holy Scriptures contained, in addition to the doctrines of justifica- 
tion and predestination, the constitution of the Church in the 
famous four orders: pastors, teachers or theoretical theologians, 
deacons or those who relieved the wants of the poor, and the 
board of discipline, which was to be composed of ministers, and 
elected representatives of the local congregations or elders. The 
fact that Calvin made the ethical interest of sanctification and the 
exhortations of Scripture the starting-point for his theory instead 
of the requirements of the priesthood of believers, secured his 
religious system against all democratic and revolutionary excesses, 
and against the perils of religious subjectivity. The participation 
of the congregation which was possible within these limits, in 
the choice of a pastor proposed to them by the ecclesiastical 
collegium, in the choice of deacons, elders, and administrators of 
discipline, made room within the ecclesiastical system itself for 
those ideas of the universal priesthood, and of personal religion, 
which could then be allowed to continue without harm, and with- 
out any danger of being diverted into secular and democratic 
channels. In Luther’s theory ethics and Church organization were 
not based upon Scriptural doctrine, but everything was left to 
free development; further, Luther could not admit that the 
ethical end was more important than the happiness of justifica- 
tion ; these two facts made it impossible for him to find a way out 
of the difficulty along Calvin’s lines. Luther was obliged to give 
up his idea of the Church which he had evolved solely from the 
standpoint of the priesthood of all believers, and revert to the 
objective institution of the ministry of the Word, which was merely 
menaced, and not furthered, by handing over questions of 
organization and discipline to the local congregations. Calvin, 
however, saw no difficulty in this question at all. From his point 
of view the task of the Church and the constitution of the Church 
supplemented each other admirably, since the same Word which 
bore witness to the faith as doctrine effected agreement to the 
moral and constitutional ordinances, and thus from the outset 
the universal priesthood was placed under effective control 
without being abolished . 322 

saa This j s told j n detail by Hundeshagen and Choisjy . 



PROTESTANTISM 


593 


Calvinism and the Anabaptist Movement 

At this point, however, the resemblance between Calvinism 
and the sect-type becomes very evident. It is here no longer 
merely an instinctive resemblance which occurs more or less 
through the influence of the Bible, and which also appeared in 
Luther’s suggestions for a congregational ideal comprising smaller 
groups of earnest Christians. Rather there is here, through the 
Strassburg Reformers and through Bucer, a special connection 
with the Anabaptists. Since the Strassburg Reformers, by insti- 
tuting the right of excommunication, and by undertaking the 
supervision of morals, admitted that the Baptists possessed one 
element of truth in which they were apparently justified, and as 
they tried to take the wind out of the sails of the Baptists by 
instituting an austere organization of the Church for the purpose 
of sanctification, Calvin then convinced himself that these claims 
were both Christian and Scriptural. In addition, they fitted in 
quite well with his whole conception of the Christian Faith 
and of predestination, which was directed entirely towards 
activity . 323 

Thus in Calvinism there appear a number of important 
characteristics which are common both to the Calvinistic and to 
the Baptist ideal of the Church as a society. Pre-eminent among 
these characteristics are the right of excommunication, and the 
conception of the Lord’s Supper as the fellowship of genuine and 
believing Christians, from whom unbelievers are to be kept 
separate. No one is admitted to Communion without being 
subjected to a thorough process of strict examination and discip- 
line. Thus the Lord’s Supper becomes more than the objective 
assurance of salvation through the forgiveness of sins ; it becomes 
also the occasion for the official inspection and purification of the 
congregation. This latter element constitutes a complete departure 
from the Lutheran point of view. 

The celebration of the Communion becomes the central point 
of the life of the congregation. The purity of the body of com- 
municants remains a subject of the most earnest care, and leads 
to scruples and fear of the Sacrament; in the end it often even 
led to the formation of separatist movements. While Lutheranism 
handed over to the secular authority the right of excommunica- 
tion and the control of morals, the Calvinist community exercised 
that authority itself, only at a later date restricting itself to spiritual 
penalties alone. 


3S8 See p. 885. 



594 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

The Lutheran preparation for the Communion was personal 
auricular confession and absolution ; the Communion itself was 
the fulfilment of the blessedness of forgiveness with the Real 
Presence of the Body and Blood of Christ, which can be enjoyed 
in isolation apart from a general celebration in church. The 
Calvinist preparation, on the contrary, took the form of searching 
inquiry through pastoral visitation, and a careful purging of the 
roll of communicants, and the Lord’s Supper was regarded as 
having no meaning excepting as an act of the whole congregation. 
The same thing applies to Baptism. It also is an act of the whole 
congregation, and signifies the consecration of the child to the 
Church ; in the Dutch and Rhenish churches full church-member- 
ship was only permitted after the candidate had passed through 
a thorough course of instruction as a catechumen. Baptism is 
regarded as the recognition of the presumed state of election, 
and is a sign of the candidate’s obligations towards the congrega- 
tion, but it is not a vehicle of grace. Hence there arose, now and 
again, misgivings about the rite of Baptism, and especially about 
the baptismal formula, in so far as it attributes a Christian 
character to the child instead of the mere obligation to become a 
Christian. It is evident that this point of view of baptism is nearer 
to the teaching of the Baptists than to that of Lutherans and 
Catholics . 324 

Again, in the process of sanctification, both of individuals and 
of the Church as a whole, the Divine Law was regarded both as 
a method of control and as the rule of life. In Lutheranism the 
moral law of Scripture was regarded as having been instituted 
solely in order to produce conviction of sin, to be applied to the 
souls of those who are “justified” only in so far as the “old man” 
has not yet been subdued, while the moral achievement itself 
issues from faith alone, apart from the law; and the Decalogue, 
interpreted in the spirit of Christ, is used only as a Christian 
exhortation in popular religious instruction. In Calvinism, how- 
ever, the Law was regarded rather as a positive Christian moral 
law, as the standard of personal and congregational discipline, as 
the rule of life required for that sanctification which flows from 
the grace of election, and of its realization through the activity of 
the Holy Ghost. 

In Calvinism severe Scriptural legalism in morality prevailed, 
just as in the Baptist community ; this legalism was expressed in 
self-examination, in Church discipline, and in self-conquest for 
the sake of sanctification. The Baptist idea of the content of the 

See p. 886. 



PROTESTANTISM 


595 


Law was, however, very different from that of Calvinism ; this 
will soon become evident . 325 

Combined with this legalism is the further idea of a continuous 
progress in sanctification, which in genuine Calvinism, it is true, 
does not lead to actual perfection, but to a comparative and partial 
kind of perfection. The Lutheran idea of perfection meant no more 
than the qualitative perfection of the “justified” ; it did not think 
of sanctification as a gradual growth in actual holiness. The 
Calvinistic idea was that of a relative “Perfectionism”, and only 
among the Baptists do we find something similar; for this idea 
has no connection with the Catholic doctrine of an intermittent 
process of sanctification, which is continually being affected both 
by mortal sin and by the sacramental inflow of grace. It is an 
active ideal of holiness, resulting from the fundamental Calvinistic 
idea of activity, and of the Scriptural doctrine of victory over sin, 
which belongs inevitably to the ideal of the Holy Community . 826 

Finally, however, the analogy is most complete in the Christ- 
ology of Calvinism. It is true that it maintains the primitive 
doctrine of the Two Natures, and the Pauline-Scholastic doctrine 
of Substitution and Satisfaction, as strictly and firmly as the 
Lutherans and the Catholics. But Calvinistic theology does not 
believe that the primary significance of Christianity consists 
simply in this : that in the Atoning Death of Christ the wrath of 
God is extinguished, and the bliss of justification is secured, and 
that this, believingly accepted, in itself actually constitutes the 
whole status of the Christian, which, mediated solely through the 
Word and the Church, will spontaneously create all the desired 
spiritual results amid the continual resistance of the flesh and 
of sin. In Calvinism, however, as among the Baptists, Christ is 
rather the Lawgiver, the Example, and, above all, the Lord and 
Head of the Church, which undertakes to follow Him, and which 
through the Holy Spirit is drawn by Him into His dynamic 
power. In Calvinistic theology, within the doctrine of the Two 
Natures, a relative independence is assigned to the Human Christ, 
through which He gains salvation through obedience. Since, 
then, the power of this work of Christ is imparted to believers in 
Christ by the Holy Spirit, Christ is thus an Example of unfailing 
325 See p. 886. 

328 On this progress in sanctification and relative Perfectionism, see Schnecken - 
burger , 7 , 45, 78 ff., and 166 ff. It is the preparatory stage for Methodism, as 
Schneckenburger likes to point out ; see also Heppe: Geschichte des Pietismus und der 
Mystik in der reformierten Kir che f 1879, pp, 49, 126, 419, who shows the transition to 
Puritanism and Pietism. Wemle: Der Christ und die Siinde bei Paulus is also useful ; 
this book deals with the Scriptural basis of Perfectionism. 



596 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

faithfulness and holiness, the Law-giver of the Christian rule of 
sanctification, the guarantee before God for those who follow Him, 
and who receive into their souls the activity of His Will. Whereas 
from the Lutheran point of view, through the union of the Divine 
and Human Natures in Christ in the Word and the Sacrament, 
He is the visible embodiment of the forgiveness of sins, and along 
with forgiveness He gives Himself and all His benefits to faith, 
from the Calvinistic point of view Christ is the Lord and Head 
of the Church, who has bound Himself to her through His Act 
of Redemption, and He Himself is incomplete until the Church 
is perfected in holiness, in a bliss which will be consummated in 
the life beyond the grave. 

From the Lutheran standpoint the Unio Mystica with Christ is 
a substantial indwelling, with a fullness of blessing which con- 
stitutes the happiness of faith ; from the Calvinistic point of view 
it is the relation of the members to the Head, who rules and 
instructs them, and brings them to fruition through the gradual 
sanctifying power of the Holy Spirit which awakens faith. 

Thus, both in the formulation of the doctrine of the Two 
Natures and in that of the Atonement, the Calvinistic point of 
view reveals an extensive approximation to the Baptist idea of 
Christ as Lawgiver, Example, and Head of the Church, who 
will only attain His maturity in the future Kingdom of God. 
There is, of course, no trace of the Baptist tendency to reject 
the doctrine of the Atonement, but, all the same, the Atonement 
is regarded more as a means of creating the Church than as 
the decisive act (complete within itself) which turns away 
the Divine Wrath and fills the ecclesiastical treasury with 
Grace . 327 

Only when this doctrinal standpoint had been attained did it 
become possible for the Christian Church to accept the Calvinistic 
idea of a Covenant. The Church is based upon a Covenant between 
God in Christ and the body of believers, in which God undertakes 
to fulfil His Promise of Grace and the Church undertakes to yield 
obedience to Him. This idea is thoroughly non-Lutheran, and 
bears a close resemblance to the separatist ideas which led 
earnest Christians of a certain narrow type to form sectarian 
groups of their own. Thus in each parish there was actually a 
double roll of Church membership ; on the one side there were 
the true, genuine, faithful, and active Christians, and on the other 
those who were merely nominal and worldly. Thus the effect of 
Calvinism was the separation of the pure body of communicants 

887 See p. 886. 



PROTESTANTISM 


597 

from the impure ; in fact it produced the distinction between an 
open and a closed community, which reminds us of the separation 
between the world and the “saints” set up by the sect. The true 
covenant-members are distinguished from the Church which 
includes the reprobate . 828 

This line of development shows that instinctively Calvinism 
has logically developed the ideas implicit in the Anabaptist ideal 
of a holy community, which it accepts and acknowledges as 
Scriptural, and in so doing it has developed the analogies with 
this ideal in various directions. These analogies, however, were 
strictly limited by the ecclesiastical spirit of a Christian national 
and State Church, which admits the necessity for various stages 
of human experience, and by the idea of pure grace which excludes 
every kind of human initiative. 

First of all, the Christian moral law and the holiness of the 
Church are conceived in such a way that precisely those demands 
of the Baptists which were most striking to the outside observer — 
abstention from official position, from positions of authority, 
from law, oath, war, and also their communism — were unhesitat- 
ingly rejected, and it was asserted that within the sphere of 
relative Natural Law which is adapted to fallen humanity, from 
the Christian point of view, all these things are permitted and 
commanded. Although, under the influence of Pietism, the later 
Calvinism now and again had misgivings even about these very 
questions, yet Calvin himself, and the whole of orthodox Calvinism, 
joyfully accepted the world, and placed these very things at the 
disposal of the “holy community”. If, then, we attempt to draw 
comparisons between Calvinism and the sect-type at all, the 
resemblances will be found to be more in the direction of the 
aggressive reforming sects, with their “Holy Wars”, than in that 
of the sects which practise non-resistance and endure persecution. 
In reality, however, to a far greater extent, the underlying current 
of thought in Calvinism was influenced by the general stream of 
ecclesiastical thought; we shall see later on how this ecclesiastical 
outlook was balanced by the demand for a specifically Christian 
holiness. 

Secondly, the whole legal spirit, the appeal to personal resolu- 
tion, the thought of Christ as the great Exemplar, and of the Law 
of Christ, the idea of a Covenant and of a fellowship of believers 
in Christ, is not conceived indeterminately as subordination, 
confession of faith, and personal fellowship as in the Anabaptist 
movement, which always fought hard against the doctrine of 

»« See p. 886. 



598 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Predestination, but as the effect of election produced by God 
through the Spirit. 

The impression that Calvinism fosters an atomistic individual- 
ism, in which the community merely consists of the sum of the 
individuals composing it, is only a superficial idea, which fastens on 
the external process through which this society is built up. In 
reality it is truer to say that all proceeds from the effectual grace 
of election, and that all the rest — Unio cum Christo , the Covenant 
of the Church with God, the deliberate emphasis on good works, 
the law, and fidelity to law, self-examination and ethical improve- 
ment — is effected by Christ, the God-Man who by means of 
His Divine Nature effects all this through His human Nature 
and the Holy Spirit. Obedience and the imitation of Christ, the 
covenant relationship and Christocracy — in reality, all that means 
insitio in Corpus Christi : this activity has only been awakened by 
the fact of election. Nothing is left to individual initiative save the 
recognition that these achievements are signs and tokens of 
the presence of the Spirit ; human initiative itself, however, is the 
work of the Spirit, and the very fact of its presence shows 
that it is due to the operation of Christ . 329 Under these circum- 
stances, even the separation between the children of this world 
and the saints is conceived differently from the idea of the Ana- 
baptists. Since in dealing with one’s fellow-men, at least, it is 
impossible to distinguish outwardly the elect from the reprobate, 
everyone is to be considered and exhorted as belonging to the 
elect, while on the other hand the reprobates, at least outwardly, 
are to be disciplined by the Church, to prevent them from becoming 
a stumbling-block, and in order that, outwardly at least, they 
may give glory to God. Both groups are to be included in an 
ecclesiastical civil commonwealth, and are to be kept in the fear 
of God by the State and by the Church. The Final Judgment 
alone will effect the separation between them. In the visible 
Church men are not to make any difference between the invisible 
community of the elect, which it contains, and the reprobate. 
Therefore, until Calvinism came under the influence of Pietism, 
it did not attempt to separate the wheat from the tares . 330 

Above all, however, Calvinism differed fundamentally from 
the Anabaptist movement in its ideal of the Law of Christ, which 
— so far as its content is concerned — governs the holy community. 

822 On this point see especially Schneckenburger in the chapter on the Unio 
mystica , /, 2 ig. Since the Church, the Word, and the means of grace belong 
to the methods of working out predestination, along this line also the ecclesi- 
astical idea itself is included. 880 See p. 887. 



PROTESTANTISM 


599 


In this matter, as we have seen already, not only did Calvinism 
not shrink from taking part in the institutions of relative Natural 
Law belonging to fallen human nature, but it felt no need at all to 
adjust its ethical ideal to the law of Christ in the New Testament, 
or the Sermon on the Mount. At this point Calvin diverged from 
the sect-ideal far more widely than Luther, in the sense of a prac- 
tical understanding of life. While, on the one hand, Calvin went 
farther than Luther by adopting and establishing the ideal of 
the Holy Community, and the disciplinary organizations which 
maintain it, on the other hand, at the very point where Luther 
followed the sect-ideal by his recognition of the ethic of the 
Sermon on the Mount as the really inward and personal ethic 
of Christianity, Calvin felt no sympathy for it at all, nor had he 
any sense of its connection with the rest of the Bible. Since in 
Calvin’s conception of God the idea of free omnipotence and 
sovereign glory transcended the idea of love, so also, from the 
outset, in his conception of the Christian moral law, the thought 
of the glory of God outweighed the thought of the claims of a 
brotherly love which would overcome all conflict and all law 
through communion with God. In contrast with Lutheranism 
nothing stands out so characteristically in Calvin’s ethic as the 
absence of any sense of the need to justify and balance the radical 
ethic of love of the Sermon on the Mount over against the claims 
of the social ethic of the practical life of politics and of Society. 
Throughout Calvin’s correspondence, in which he gives his 
judgment on a countless number of ethical cases, there is not 
even a suspicion of that individualistic morality with its hostility 
t0 9 the world, and its opposition to an official morality which it 
is forced to accept. Wholly instinctively, and with piercing insight, 
Calvin singles out of the Christian morality of love the religious 
element of activity for the glory of God, and of sanctification for 
God and for His Purpose, which has always distinguished Calvin- 
ism from any mere sentimentality and humanitarianism. Without 
hesitation he regards everything as commanded and permitted 
which can serve the glory of God — and by that he means that the 
Church is to be set up, maintained, and kept pure as a community 
of saints closely connected with the State and with Society. When 
it is claimed that the Christian ought to renounce authority and 
law, wealth and possessions, rewards and worldly honours, Calvin 
takes care to explain that this renunciation only applies within 
certain limits — that is, that a renunciation of this kind must be 
solely designed to serve the spirit of holiness and brotherly love, 
but that it must not be permitted in any way to endanger the 

N 



600 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

glory of God Himself. Where this is concerned, all those methods 
are not merely permitted, they are commanded ; of course it is 
understood that they are to be exercised within the limits of 
sincerity, personal gentleness, and disinterested enthusiasm for the 
cause, without any hatred or injury to individuals. Without further 
argument he interprets the Sermon on the Mount in this sense ; 
above all he bases his argument repeatedly upon the Old Testa- 
ment (which cannot fail to harmonize with the Sermon on the 
Mount, since the Bible is a unity), upon the reforms and the 
policy of the kings who “feared the Lord”, on the Decalogue, 
on the later ethic of Judaism, on David and the Psalms. 

The result of all that is undertaken must always be committed 
into God’s keeping, but the believer is entitled to use every 
legitimate method, and he may connect it directly with the re- 
ligious end in view, without appealing to the support of an alien 
official morality. This idea of an official morality has only been 
retained in so far as Galvin gives a prominent place to all those 
who, by virtue of their calling and their official position, are 
called to use law and authority, to an active participation in 
political and military affairs. In such cases, however, a direct 
religious value is assigned to their activity, without any sense of 
conflict, or need for the reconciliation of opposing ideas. Calvin 
himself writes and acts like a most practised and accomplished 
politician, and like a military strategist who has weighed all the 
risks. In all this, certainly, all that is left to the masses is obedience 
to their leaders, without any scruples about their Christian right 
to use force and violence for the glory of God. 

Further, Calvin was not opposed to private property nor Jo 
the endeavour to acquire wealth, provided that all is done honestly, 
moderately, and united with a generous charitable activity. It 
all serves the good of the community (of the Church), of the State, 
and thus the glory of God ; it is only a question of defining its 
limits ; in itself it is no problem at all. Only upon this assumption 
can we understand Calvin’s strong attraction to the Old Testa- 
ment. Only when the New Testament ethic is thus fused with 
that of the Old Testament, as Calvin has done, only when the 
Love of God is conceived as the Will which elects certain souls, 
and when love to God is regarded essentially as the sanctification 
of the life of the individual and of Society for the sake of God, 
does such an interpretation of the New Testament become possible. 

Calvin adopted this position entirely instinctively. He had no 
quarrel with the Lutheran ethic; he was simply acting on his 
conviction that such a position was only the logical result of 
/ 



PROTESTANTISM 


601 


his genuine Reformation exaltation of the Bible, in the belief 
that an ethic of this kind also harmonized with the genuine 
Reformation predestinarian conception of God. As in increasing 
measure Luther had already appealed to the Old Testament in 
order to justify his intramundane ethic of vocation (“the calling”), 
so Galvin also adopted this position. Here also he believed that 
he was only developing common principles of the Reformation 
more strictly and practically. We must remember, too, that Calvin 
had never passed through the school of monasticism. 

Thus he found it possible to make an ethic of sanctification the 
underlying basis of Church discipline and of the development of 
the State, which in its severity might be compared with that of 
the Baptists, without making the radical ethic of love of the 
Sermon on the Mount into a universal law, since this would be 
impossible for Society as a whole. This is the actual source of the 
alleged “Old Testament” character of Calvinism. It is the same 
instinct which, at an earlier historical stage, had impelled the 
type of the aggressive reforming sect towards the Old Testament, 
its “holy wars” and its covenants. This phenomenon is not a 
revival of Jewish legalism, but of the Old Testament concern 
with the practical life of the nation. Nor has this ideal of the holy 
community anything to do with reactions towards Catholicism. 
It is the sect-ideal, united, however, with the idea of the Church 
as an institution, brought within the bounds of practical possi- 
bility by an extensive application of Old Testament principles; in 
all other respects it is a most active and vital form of Protestantism. 
Compared with Luther’s teaching about the duty of love and 
gatience and the endurance of suffering, it is certainly a more 
practical and opportunist point of view. But since everywhere its 
aim is simply to work for the glory of God and of the Church, 
with an entire renunciation of all self-interest, it is not a deprecia- 
tion of Christian morality to the average level ; rather it is an 
emphasis upon that other element in the Christian ethic which 
is bound up with it, of that fearless heroism which will dare and 
achieve anything for the glory of God . 331 

Again, if men hold the view that the glory of God is furthered 
by the institution of a holy community, and not merely by the 
preservation of personal religion, then this superior heroism will 
no longer be merely passive but active and organizing, and it 
must seize the means that it needs in order to achieve its purpose. 
This, however, is precisely the nature of the Calvinistic ethic, 
which, while it has exercised the severest self-repression, has 

831 See p. 887. 



602 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

indeed achieved great things, even when it made use of secular 
institutions for the Kingdom of God. In Calvin’s view the glory 
of God is not advanced by the repeated surrender of the sinner 
to the forgiving love of God, but in the evolution of the holy 
community, by means of self-surrender to God and to His 
commands . 332 

It is thus quite easy to understand the emphasis which Calvin- 
ism lays on fellowship, in the inclusive sense of a State Church 
association for Christian sanctification, in accordance with the 
example, law, and lordship of Christ. This is an interesting pheno- 
menon, taken in conjunction with its peculiarly accentuated 
stress on independence and individualism. 

The sectarian ideals which had been absorbed from the New 
Testament and from the Anabaptist criticism of the Reforma- 
tion were thus fused with the idea of the Church as an organ of 
grace, and merged in the idea of predestination, which by its 
active character intensified the sectarian ideal, and yet kept the 
balance by its emphasis on the ideal of the Church. This fact, 
however, explains why, throughout Calvinism, we see a twofold 
tendency, which aims at the active formation of a society, and 
also at personal achievement, combined with a methodical, 
rational method and a completeness of action, all of which are 
directed towards the goal of the happiness of the future life. This 
leads Calvinism everywhere to an organized and aggressive effort 
to form associations, to a systematic endeavour to mould the life 
of Society as a whole, to a kind of “Christian Socialism”. This 
“Christian Socialism” certainly is not primarily concerned (like 
its modern counterpart) with the material, economic preliminary 
conditions of higher intellectual culture, neither has it, of course, 
anything at all to do with the modern class problems which have 
been created by Capitalism and Industrialism ; but it lays down 
the principle that the Church ought to be interested in all sides 
of life, and it neither isolates the religious element over against 
the other elements, like Lutheranism, nor does it permit this 
sense of collective responsibility to express itself merely in par- 
ticular institutions and occasional intervention in affairs, as in 
Catholicism . 333 

The Ethic of Calvinism 

This brings us to the fourth point : the peculiar ethic of Calvin- 
ism. At first Calvin simply continued Luther’s point of view — that 
is, he evolved ethical principles from the spirit of faith ; the only 
888 See p. 887. 888 See p. 890. 



PROTESTANTISM 


603 

difference he made was that he applied this principle more 
systematically and more clearly. In so doing, however, the whole 
idea of ethics was altered ; instead of being merely the result of 
justification by faith it became the end. This transformation, 
of course, was one which could take place very easily on the 
assumption of the doctrine of predestination, without any reaction 
in the direction of a system of “good works” and merit. Further, 
the standard of Christian ethical behaviour has become more 
definite in outline, for from the very outset the Holy Spirit provides 
a clear and definite standard in the moral law of Scripture : the 
Decalogue, interpreted in the sense of the whole range of Scrip- 
tural ideas, and identified with the natural moral law. At this 
point, indeed, Lutheranism also had not been able to limit its 
ethical theory to one of obedience to spontaneous impulse in 
behaviour; it did admit that the Decalogue was the expression 
of the Divine Will with regard to moral impulse. Calvinism also 
adopted all the following ideas from Lutheranism: Luther’s 
theory of the Decalogue, of the two Tables of the Law, of the 
identity between the Divine and Natural Law, and the Christian 
interpretation of the Decalogue as a law of spirit and of freedom, 
which depends upon the power of the Holy Spirit in order to 
realize it in life. Calvin, however, gave the Decalogue a firmer 
position in the system, since to him the usus legis was not a problem 
bristling with difficulties, but a coherent fundamental theory. 
Why should the Holy Spirit dispense with that clarity in ethics 
which He reveals in doctrine? The Bible itself lays stress on 
ethics as well as on doctrine. In the mind of Calvin this does not 
signify a reaction towards heteronomy or legalism, since in this 
law it is only the content of faith in its ethical aspect which is 
manifested, and since the value of the moral achievement does 
not consist in particular actions, but in the spirit generated by 
faith in the whole personality, in the total change of heart effected 
by conversion . 334 By means of the Decalogue the Holy Spirit 
solely enlightens the elect about those regulating principles of 
action which lead to the realization of the Kingdom of Christ, 
which cannot be left to the mercy of mere instinctive, unen- 
lightened natural feeling. In this respect also Calvin is only the 
systematic thinker and practical organizer ; at this point, however, 
he leaves the idealistic freedom of Luther behind and moves 
towards the average constraint of the human sense of the need for 
authority. 

334 Cf. Lobstein , pp. 58-60 \ the Decalogue as little heteronomous as the natural 
moral law, both means of the moralizing and Christianizing of Society. 



604 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

The following features also are peculiar to the Calvinistic ethic : 
the doctrine of final perseverance, or the impossibility of losing 
the state of grace, which creates a uniform permanent state of 
moral achievement and assurance, in place of the Lutheran idea 
of the possibility of falling away from grace and the renewal of 
justification ; then there is the doctrine of a progressive sanctifica- 
tion, which teaches that the germ of the grace of election becomes 
increasingly conscious, and that it develops more and more into 
a mature Christian experience; this is an absolute contrast to 
the Lutheran suspicion of the whole idea of progress, and to its 
connection with preparation for Heaven. It is these distinctive 
features in the thought of Calvinism which have produced those 
systematic, rational, inclusive, and progressive elements which 
characterize its personal and its social ethic, creating an ethical 
ideal which is not merely an ideal for the achievement of indi- 
vidual Christian character, but one which covers the whole 
life of the world with an all-embracing religious purpose. The 
natural result of all this is seen in the more closely knit, com- 
prehensive, and penetrating energy of the Calvinistic social 
doctrines. By treating moral progress and achievement as 
practical proofs of the state of grace the Calvinist ethic was 
extraordinarily intensified and also externalized, yet at the same 
time it also became more accessible to the average attainment 
of mankind . 335 

Yet all these peculiar aspects of the Calvinist ethic, with their 
influence on character, in spite of their effectiveness, were still 
rather external. Far more important is their unique content: 
the ascetic outlook which was produced by the direction of purpose 
towards the future life, and by the austere separation between 
God and the creature; this asceticism also included the most 
positive kind of work within this world itself. This is one of the 
most creative elements of the Calvinistic ethic, since it has deter- 
mined the whole way of life which is peculiar to the nations who 
have been bred in the atmosphere of Calvinism . 836 As has been 
already shown, in itself asceticism only becomes connected with 
Christianity through the pessimistic doctrine of Original Sin, 
which depreciates the value of the life of the world in comparison 
with the world of redemption and of salvation, and which at the 

835 Cf. Lobstein , pp. 75-78 : no conversion conflict as in Lutheranism, but 
development within and through the community for the community. Other- 
wise, see above, all Schneckenburger , whose analysis of this ethic is particularly 
masterly, whereas the dogmatic analysis tends to modernize too much. 

838 See p. 890. 



PROTESTANTISM 


605 

same time desires to control the life of the flesh and of the senses 
by means of a rational system of discipline. The Gospel outlook 
transcended the things of time and sense, and expected the coming 
of the Kingdom of God upon earth ; it did not renounce the world, 
nor did it develop a systematic discipline of the life of the senses. 
Asceticism only found its way into Christianity when the idea 
arose that the world was permanently lost and steeped in Original 
Sin, and when the Kingdom of God came to be viewed as some- 
thing belonging to the future life. 

From the very beginning asceticism had a dual significance: 
on the one hand it was a metaphysical condemnation of the world, 
and on the other it was a rational discipline of the senses. It was 
possible for both these elements to unite ; it was also possible for 
them to exist separately. It was quite possible for ascetic world- 
denial to develop into Antinomianism, and ascetic discipline was 
quite capable of developing into a severe austere eudaemonistic 
legalism, with its eye fixed on future rewards. Both kinds of 
asceticism were practised within Catholicism. Catholicism, above 
all, felt the difficulty of making room for ascetic morality along- 
side of the unavoidable necessities of life in the world. It found 
the solution of the problem in its dualistic theory of morality, 
and in the full meaning of the word it placed asceticism alongside 
of and above the life of the world, which only recognizes ascetic 
obligations now and again, and within practicable limits. Catholic 
asceticism was, and still is, a form of life which existed alongside 
of and above the average conditions of life in the world, cultivated 
particularly in monasteries and confraternities and among the 
clergy. 

Protestantism, however, discarded that dualism, and laid upon 
all alike the duty of permeating the life of the world with the 
spirit of world-renunciation and victory over the world. Its ideal 
was one of spiritual detachment from the things of this world, 
combined with victory over the world, while remaining within it. 
Thus it intensified the moral demand by making it apply to all 
alike, and it intensified the pessimistic doctrine of Original Sin in 
its desire to make the idea of conversion and of redemption 
dominant over the whole of existence. Thus to a certain extent 
Protestantism maintained asceticism, but only in the form of 
an asceticism within the life of the world. Within this sphere 
of general agreement, however, Lutheranism and Calvinism 
developed along very different lines. They divided between them 
the two fundamentally different aspects of asceticism which have 
already been mentioned : the spirit of metaphysical depreciation 



606 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

of this sinful world, and the systematic discipline of the senses. 
Lutheranism depreciated this world, mourning over it as a “vale 
of tears”, but so far as everything else was concerned the Lutheran, 
happy in the assurance of justification, and nourished by the 
Presence of Christ in the sacraments, let things remain as they 
were, quite happy and confident, accepting the world as he found 
it, exhibiting Christian love in faithfulness to the duties of his 
calling, leaving results to God, and incidentally thankfully 
rejoicing in the Divine glory of creation which breaks through the 
shadows cast by this sinful world. In this attitude there are traces 
of the mystical Neo-Platonic depreciation of the senses and of the 
finite, which had already played a prominent part in Catholicism, 
and incidentally there appeared also, in connection with the 
freedom of the Spirit from the world — in sharp contrast with the 
legalism of the “Reformed” churches— the antinomian result. 
Here also Lutheranism, which is happy in the midst of wretched- 
ness, is entirely illogical ; it takes impressions just as they come, 
both the misery and vexation of the world, and also thankful 
enjoyment of the gifts of God ; neither the one nor the other really 
matter, since through justification by faith the world has been 
overcome. 

The Calvinist’s attitude towards the world is quite different. 
He finds it impossible to deny the world in theory and enjoy it in 
practice. This lack of system is contrary to his reflective and 
logical mind. He cannot leave the world alone in all its horror 
and comfort himself with the thought of a “finished salvation”. 
That kind of Quietism is totally opposed to his impulse towards 
activity, and the idea of a “finished salvation” is opposed to his 
orientation towards the aim of a salvation which is yet to be 
attained. With his deep sense of the gulf which separates the 
omnipotence of God from the nothingness of the creature any 
attempt to find satisfaction in creatures, even of a passing kind, 
would mean a deification of the creature. The creature in itself 
is only a means; it is never a Divinely complete end in itself. 
Moreover, to the Calvinist the sinful creaturely world is an 
abomination which he must oppose with all his might, and which 
he feels he must overcome. Thus he knows he must go to work 
thoughtfully, systematically, and progressively to overcome the 
tendency to deify the creature, and all the sin which clings to the 
senses and to self-love. In view, however, of his Protestant estimate 
of the secular life, and of his ideal of a Holy Community summed 
up in the form of a State Church, he can only overcome the world 
by at the same time recognizing the value of its life. 



PROTESTANTISM 607 

Calvinism, therefore, creates an intramundane asceticism 
which logically and comprehensively recognizes all secular means, 
but which reduces them to means only, without any value in 
themselves, in order that by the use of all the means available 
the Holy Community may be created. The method by which 
all that is secular is reduced to the level of a mere means is a 
rigorous discipline of the instinctive life, a destruction of all 
merely instinctive feeling, and the limitation of the sense-life to 
that which is necessary and useful, the practice of self-discipline 
and self-control in order to lead a holy life in obedience to the 
Law of God. 

These are the ideas which lie behind that combination of 
practical sense and cool utilitarianism with an other-worldly aim, 
of systematic conscious effort united with an utter absence of 
interest in the results of effort, which is a distinctive character- 
istic of Calvinism, and in which all the qualities which have 
already been described are merged. 

This peculiar combination of ideas produces a keen interest in 
politics, but not for the sake of the State ; it produces active indus- 
try within the economic sphere, but not for the sake of wealth ; it 
produces an eager social organization, but its aim is not material 
happiness; it produces unceasing labour, ever disciplining the 
senses, but none of this effort is for the sake of the object of all 
this industry. The one main controlling idea and purpose of this 
ethic is to glorify God, to produce the Holy Community, to 
attain that salvation which in election is held up as the aim; 
to this one idea all the other formal peculiarities of Calvinism are 
subordinate. 

Only when we see Calvinism from this angle can we grasp the 
full significance of Calvinistic legalism, and its resemblance to 
Catholic disciplinary asceticism which has often been remarked, 
even to the point of a righteousness consisting in “works” and 
the desire for reward. In pure Calvinism, however, all these 
weaknesses are obviated by the ideas of grace and predestination, 
which, on the other hand, fostered this tendency to legalism by 
its teaching about good works as the signs of election. 

It is well known that Calvin’s judgment in these questions was 
comparatively free from prejudice), and that he knew how to 
appraise the values of civilization in the Gratia universalis , which 
also lays hold on the reprobate making them capable of higher 
achievements, and thus also revealing the beauty of the world. 
This Gratia universalis , however, which softens the ascetic tendency, 
is still only a foreign body in the system, introduced under the 



6o8 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

pressure of practical life and under the influence of ancient 
classical culture. When the problem is viewed in the light of 
Christianity — and that is the decisive point — there Calvin also 
ceased to assign any positive value to creaturely achievement 
and earthly glory; all are regarded simply as a means for 
establishing the dominion of Christ. The Gratia universalis , regarded 
in the light of a civilization which is not controlled by the 
dominion of Christ, is valid only for the reprobate and the 
unconverted. The elect and the converted, on the contrary, use 
their possessions solely for the purposes of religion. Calvin permits 
joy, it is true, but only in a very restricted way, as a necessary 
and useful relaxation . 337 

Moreover, as will easily be understood, later Calvinism intensi- 
fied and systematized Calvin’s rigorism to a pitch of Puritanical 
legalism and purely utilitarian restraint, which stands out in 
sharp contrast from Lutheranism, which in this respect is most 
illogical. It would be wrong to try to find in this development a 
trace of the influence, whether past or present, of Catholicism, 
which, indeed, scarcely bears any trace at all of this kind of 
asceticism within the ordinary life of the world. It is the very 
essence of the genuine Calvinistic spirit, and it has bred that sober, 
utilitarian, energetic, and methodical purposive humanism which 
labours on earth for a heavenly reward, which in its secular form 
is only too well known to us to-day. Calvin’s own attitude, and 
the spiritual counsel he gives in his letters, provide the most 
magnificent example of an ascetic and utilitarian ethic of this 
kind. In his case, however, this way of life was still penetrated by 
a genuine religious dignity and majesty, with a sense of responsi- 
bility and of a wide range of thought, with the consciousness of 
the greatness of the ultimate End. Thus his ethical system and his 
methodical habit of mind never became petty ; on the contrary, it 
was characterized by the highest sense of duty towards an objective 
task in life, which does not consider the feelings and inclina- 
tions of the individual, but which concentrates entirely upon 
work for God. In the greatness of genuine Calvinism there is 
always an undertone of this kind. But in periods of peace and 
relaxation, under the influence of the human tendency to sink 
to the average level, and in connection with the bourgeois life of 
business, this spirit becomes rather self-righteous and Pharisaical, 
very full of the consciousness of belonging to the number of the 
elect and expecting the heavenly reward. These sentiments found 
apparent support in the Old Testament, and, not without reason, 

187 See p. 892. 



PROTESTANTISM 


609 

the Puritans have been often regarded as Jewish Christians. While 
the passivity and happy surrender of Lutheranism, combined 
with its emotional warmth and naivete, with its tendency to 
give rein to natural impulses, has left its mark, in the form both 
of a dependent spirit and of geniality, upon large sections of 
German civilization right down to the present day, the school 
of Calvin, on the other hand, has bred in the Calvinistic nations 
a habit of personal reserve, positive restraint, aggressive initiative, 
and a reasoned logic of the aim of action . 338 

Since, however the sphere of one’s calling provided both scope 
and a method of discipline for this intramundane asceticism, 
the idea of the “calling” itself here gained a new and specially 
emphasized significance, which distinguished it not only from the 
Catholic, but also from the Lutheran conception. This concep- 
tion provides the transition to modern vocational humanism. 
The Early Church, in its defensive attitude towards the world, 
tolerated the natural organization of labour and the various 
degrees of Society, regarding them as matters of indifference so 
far as the question of salvation was concerned ; it had only excluded 
certain callings from those in which Christians might take part, 
on account of their incompatibility with the Christian Faith . 339 
The mediaeval period brought the natural lower grade of secular 
work and the natural social organization into an inner connection 
with the spiritual sphere of the Church, but it still regarded it all 
as a providential classification on the basis of Natural Law, upon 
which real religious achievements still had to be built up, but 
which was not binding for the heroes of the religious life, the 
vicarious representatives and authors of the essential Christian 
spirit . 340 At this point it was Protestantism alone which drew 
Nature and Grace together, since in its view the redeeming Will 
of Grace both gave each man his secular task in the World 
and made it the normal sphere, necessary for everyone, for the 
exercise of the spirit inspired by Divine Grace. 

From the economic and social point of view the consequences 
of this conception of the “calling” were extraordinary. It raised 
the ordinary work of one’s profession (within one’s vocation) 
and the ardour with which secular work was prosecuted to the 
level of a religious duty in itself; from a mere method of providing 
for material needs it became an end in itself, providing scope for 
the exercise of faith within the labour of the “calling”. That gave 
rise to that ideal of work for work’s sake which forms the intel- 
lectual and moral assumption which lies behind the modem 
338 See p. 893. 389 Cf. above, pp . 118-127. 340 Cf. above, pp. 2Q3-2Q6. 

VOL. II. L 



6io THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 


bourgeois way of life . 341 Within Lutheranism, however, the 
consequences of this conception only had a limited influence. 
It is only in Calvinism that their full and strictly logical 
effect appears. Luther’s view of vocation agreed with that 
of Paul, the Early Church, and the Middle Ages. To him the 
“calling” was simply the sphere of activity in which one was set, 
and in which it was a duty to remain. He could see no meaning 
or Divine sanction in the idea of a holiness which was higher 
than the ordinary ethic of a Christian vocation. Although at the 
same time Luther pointed out that it is precisely through the 
ordered work of one’s calling, and the intricate network of mutual 
service that the preservation of the whole community is effected, 
and with that peace, order, and prosperity, he attributes it all 
to the wise ordering and the kindly guidance of Providence, and 
not to deliberate human initiative. The vocational system was 
not consciously designed and developed for the purposes of the 
holy community and of Christian Society, but it was accepted 
as a Divine arrangement. The individual, moreover, regarded his 
work, not as a suitable way of contributing to the uplift of Society 
as a whole, but as his appointed destiny, which he received from 
the hands of God. That is why it was possible for the Lutheran 
to regard the work of his vocation in an entirely traditional and 
reactionary way — as the duty of remaining within the traditional 
way of earning a living which belongs to one’s position in Society. 
This point of view coincides with the traditional Catholic view. 
Christian morality was exercised in vocatione but not per voca- 
tionem , 842 It is just at this point, however, that the difference 
between Lutheranism and Calvinism is most manifest. Calvinism 
aimed consciously and systematically at the creation of a Holy 
Community . 343 It co-ordinated the activity of the individual 
and of the community into a conscious and systematic form. 
And since the Church as a whole could not be fully constituted 
without the help of the political and economic service of the secu- 
lar community, it was urged that all callings ought to be ordered, 
purified, and enkindled as means for attaining the ends of the 
Holy Community. Thus the ideal was now no longer one of 
surrender to a static vocational system, directed by Providence, 

841 On this point cf. especially Max Weber , who also analyses in detail the 
linguistic origin of the Protestant conception of the “calling” from i Cor. vii. 20, 
in connection with Eccles. xi. 20-21. 

842 On this point cf. Weber: Archiv. XXI, 16-17; Lobstein , i43ff. 

843 Here I would mention once more Eger's excellent book, Luthers Lehre vom 
Beruf ; see also above, pp. 361-364, 



PROTESTANTISM 


611 


but the free use of vocational work as the method of realizing the 
purpose of the Holy Community. The varied secular callings 
do not simply constitute the existing framework within which 
brotherly love is exercised and faith is preserved, but they are 
means to be handled with freedom, through whose thoughtful 
and wise use love alone becomes possible and faith a real thing. 
From this there results a freer conception of the system of callings, 
a far-reaching consideration for that which is practically possible 
and suitable, a deliberate increasing of the intensity of labour. 
To what extent this rationality and mobility of the conception 
of vocation was carried through in detail, in the presence of the 
opposing conception of life with its “guild” and “police” spirit, 
is quite another question. The instances of ecclesiastical social 
politics in Geneva which will be cited farther on, however, 
display considerable freedom of movement. 

There is also another element which ought to be taken into 
account, the significance of which will also only become fully 
evident at a later stage. It is this : one of the special tasks of the 
Holy Community was that of ascetic self-discipline in work, an 
ascetic abstention from all worldly distractions in order to attend 
to the duties of one’s calling, the renunciation of the utilization of 
the profit gained by one’s labour for personal enjoyment; this 
kind of asceticism produced, as an important by-product, that 
ideal of hard work, of the prosecution of work for its own sake, as 
a duty in itself, which is anything but a natural attitude of mind, 
and which can only be understood in the light of a religious energy 
which can thoroughly transform the natural instinctive life. Once 
this psychological state of mind has been created, it can then, 
through a process of metamorphosis of purpose, be detached 
from its original meaning and placed at the disposal of other ideas ; 
in various ways this process often takes place at the present day. 
It is, however, precisely at this point that we can observe the 
difference between nations which have been educated on Catholic, 
Lutheran, or Calvinist lines. 

To people who have been educated on Calvinistic principles 
the lazy habit of living on an inherited income seems a downright 
sin ; to follow a calling which has no definite end and which yields 
no material profit seems a foolish waste of time and energy, and 
failure to make full use of chances of gaining material profit 
seems like indifference towards God. From the Calvinistic point 
of view laziness is the most dangerous vice ; it is hurtful to the 
soul from the standpoint of ascetic discipline, and harmful to the 
community from the standpoint of social utilitarianism. In this 



612 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

matter, however, Calvin himself did not perceive the full logical 
result of his idea. His strongly aristocratic outlook, and his con- 
nection with the French nobles, gave him a more broad-minded 
and understanding conception of the services rendered by various 
callings. 

Huguenot Calvinism, within which the aristocratic element 
predominated, was at first quite different in character; it only 
became bourgeois after it had been disarmed and fettered; in 
any case it was this development which made it more difficult 
for the nobles to join the movement. The permanent remnant of 
the Huguenot movement, and the Huguenot emigrants, certainly 
display quite plainly that interest in trade and commerce which 
is characteristic of a bourgeois society. In the last resort, however, 
a bourgeois development of this kind was bound to take place as 
a result of Calvin’s social ethic as well as of his ascetic rigorism. 
It reached its full development in the bourgeois atmosphere of 
the Calvinism of the Lower Rhine and of the Netherlands. 
That was the kind of society which provided a congenial soil for 
this religious ethic, just as the dualistic ethic of Catholicism suited 
the graduated social system of mediaeval society. Just as the 
agrarian-feudal and mediaeval city conception of life formed 
the basis of mediaeval Christian civilization, and made the latter 
possible, and was in return strengthened and permeated by it, 
so the nascent bourgeois world was inwardly related to the ethic 
of Calvinism, and in return it was religiously strengthened and 
moulded by it into a spiritual and ethical force which was indepen- 
dent of all mere fluctuations in sentiment and opinion . 344 

Up to this point we have been dealing solely with the question 
of the supernatural, spiritual ethic, which is produced by the grace 
of election. This ethic, however, needed support in the natural 
or universal ethic of civilization, such as the ethic of the Catholic 
Church had already long possessed; all that Lutheranism had 
done was to regulate afresh the relation between the two. This 
function was exercised by the conceptions (with which we have 
already dealt several times) of the moral Natural Law and of the 
Law of Nature. It is precisely at this point, however, that there 
emerges an important peculiarity of Calvinism. In the actual 
wording of this theory Calvin certainly does not seem to be 
using any different formulas from those employed by Luther and 
Melancthon about the absolute Natural Law of the Primitive State, 
and the relative Natural Law of the present day, adapted to the 
conditions of fallen humanity . 345 Calvin speaks just as they did 
844 See p. 894. 344 See p. 895. 



PROTESTANTISM 


613 

about the identity of the Natural Law with the Decalogue, in 
which, not only the Decalogue, but the whole Old Testament 
Law and the history of Israel appear as illustrations of the Natural 
Law ; 846 of the application of the Christian spirit to the social 
institutions of the Natural Law, and of the corresponding division 
of the Decalogue into two Tables, one of which concerns spiritual 
and religious matters, and the other, the concerns of secular 
morality ; 347 the argument that Positive Law is an application of 
Natural Law, conditioned and altered by time and circumstances, 
according to which the positive element in the Law of Moses 
(Mosaic Code) and in Roman Law, and also in the present law 
of the State, in civil and in criminal law, is to be understood as 
the evolution of the Law of Nature, conditioned by time and 
place . 348 Up to this point Calvin’s ideas seem to coincide exactly 
with the Lutheran conception. Further, Calvin agrees with Luther 
in a very strict demand for respect for authority, even in cases 
where those who wield authority are not particularly estimable. 
The same applies to Calvin’s exhortations to frugality, modesty, 
and adaptation to existing circumstances and situations. Calvin’s 
position seems to have been directly nearer to Luther’s positively 
authoritative conception of the Law of Nature than to the ration- 
alistic conception of Melancthon ; Luther’s ideas were certainly 
in closer agreement with his personal instincts than Melanc- 
thon’s . 349 In spite of that, however, it is precisely at this point 
that we can discern a great difference between Calvin’s position 
as a whole and that of Luther and Lutheranism. 

This distinction appears first of all in two apparently external 
points. The first point is that Calvin emphasized the difference 
between absolute and relative Natural Law far less than Luther. 
He continually describes the Decalogue and the Natural Law as 
the eternal unchangeable rules of the Divine moral law; the 
modification of the law by the fact of sin is only alluded to inci- 
dentally, it is never dealt with in principle. The State in particular, 
in the chief passages in which Calvin refers to it, is never regarded 
as a mere antidote to the fallen State and a penalty for evil, but 
it is always chiefly regarded as a good and holy institution, 
appointed by God Himself. Nor is there ever any suggestion that 
the original communism of love had been modified and trans- 
formed into the institution of private property ; private property 
likewise seems to be a directly Divine institution . 850 Far less 
emphasis is laid, therefore, upon the contrast between the Primi- 

846 See p. 896. 847 See p. 896. 848 See p. 896. 

848 See p.897. 880 See p.898. 



614 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

tive State and the fallen State [probably this was due to the 
influence of the doctrine of Predestination] — rather, from the 
outset political and economic institutions are regarded as Divine 
institutions for the purpose of preserving social peace and harmony. 
The Augustinian influences which had coloured the Lutheran 
ethic of the State and of economics, which indeed even in Luther 
belonged rather to his earlier period, have practically disap- 
peared entirely; in Calvin’s mind the problem is simply this: 
how can these Divine institutions most usefully be moulded to 
serve the ends of a Christian society? 

It is the same thing with the second point : Calvin’s conception 
of the relation between the First and Second Tables of the 
Decalogue. It is well known that Calvin makes the First Table 
include four instead of three commandments, by reckoning the 
command against image-worship as a commandment in itself; 
to make things right he runs the Ninth and Tenth Commandments 
into one. This is a feature of every Calvinist catechism. The deeper 
significance of this change, however, lies in the fact that now the 
general meaning of the First Table is not the demand for a spiritual 
union with God, detached from and superior to the world, out 
of whose interior depths alone goodness streams forth, but it is 
that of a commandment which inculcates purity of worship 
apart from pictures, magic, or ritual ceremonies, and lays great 
stress on strict Sabbath observance. This entirely changes the 
meaning of the First Table; it places purism of temper and of 
worship on exactly the same plane as that of unconditional obedi- 
ence. Hence the Lutheran tension between the absolute religious 
morality of love of the First Table, and the social demands on 
justice, compulsion, and force of the Second Table, disappears 
altogether. 

So far as Calvin, like Luther, describes spirituality as that 
spirit which alone produces obedience to the Second Table of 
the Law, inspiring it with the Christian spirit, he considers that 
this spirituality consists in the radical severity and emotional 
moderation of motive which springs from the “vision of the true 
God, reverenced and recognized”, and not in the pure, loving 
disposition which is opposed to the whole order of law . 351 Thus, 
in connection with the “Two Tables”, we see the same process 
at work as there was in the question of the distinction between 
a “private” and a “public” ethic; while in Luther the differences 
had already receded behind the formal character of a demand, 
in Calvin they had altogether disappeared. 

881 See p. 898. 



PROTESTANTISM 


615 

There is, however, more in this than a mere wholesale adoption 
of Luther’s later teaching which obliterated these distinctions. 
A completely different spirit now prevails. Calvin scarcely ever 
presents the products of relative Natural Law in the Family, in 
the State, in Society, and in the sphere of economics as concessions 
to the fact of sin, which must simply be tolerated ; almost always 
he alludes to them as useful institutions for attacking evil, for 
the furtherance of good, and for the realization of the glory of 
God. From Calvin’s point of view the objections of the Anabaptists, 
which Luther partially accepted, in the distinction which he 
drew between private and public morality, and to which he only 
added the reservation that the Gospel must not be turned into a 
Law, seemed to be simply unpractical and fantastic nonsense. 
Calvin’s one reply is to set against the views of the Anabaptists 
the statement that the Divine Law cannot be divided, that whether 
it be expressed in the Old Testament or in the New it is all one. 
He adds that in his opinion their demands are against common 
sense, since if they were realized they would do away with the 
Law of Nature as well. Calvin regards the absolute Law of Nature 
so little as the real standard, and takes for granted that the relative 
Natural Law is a Divine institution, that he lays all the emphasis 
on that which is practical, possible, and suitable. The result of this 
attitude, however, is that the institution of the State and of Law 
both can and must be adapted to the two following ends : (1) the 
religious purpose of the maintenance of true religion; and (2) the 
social and utilitarian end of the promotion of peace, order, and 
prosperity. These two points are all that really matter; both, 
however, are primarily the concern of the Government. Calvin 
entirely excludes any idea of forming Society rationally on the 
basis of the individuals which compose it, or from the point of 
view of the “man in the street ”. 362 But, even so, the intellectual 
atmosphere in which Calvin’s ideas of the State, of Law, and of 
Economics are bathed is impregnated with a spirit of logical 
purpose and rationality, which seems to have no connection with 
the Lutheran attitude of pessimism 353 and mere toleration of all 
these things. Further, however, Calvin is very cautious and 
non-committal in his expression of opinion about the positive 
forms of the State, since in them he perceives the idea of the State 
conceived in terms of Natural Law, shaped by Positive Law in 

8 52 Inst., IV, 20, 31 : “Quibus nullum aliud quam parendi et patiendi datum 
est mandatum; de privatis hominibus semper loquor.” IV, 20, 8: “Et sane 
valde otiosum esset, quis potissimus sit politiae in eo quo vivunt loco futurus 
status, a privatis hominibus disputari” ! 853 See p. 898. 



616 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

accordance with the historical situation, with national character- 
istics, and with political necessity. These forms of the State, 
however, correspond mostly nearly to the Law of Nature in which 
it is possible to control and direct the governing authority in the 
right path, as, for instance, monarchies with various social ranks 
and legally empowered counsellors, aristocracies in which a 
mutual influence is exerted upon the rulers, and, above all, 
republics with a graded system of authority. This is the famous 
theory of the “right of resistance” and of reform which belongs 
to the magistrate inferieurs , who, if the supreme authority fails in its 
duty, hold a Divine Commission, which entitles them to intervene 
for the good of Society and the truth of religion. The private 
individual alone is forbidden to interfere in public affairs; his 
only duty is to suffer and obey. The official courts, however, are 
authorized to make criticisms and to suggest reforms; they can 
thus work towards the goal of a society framed and ordered 
according to reason and to Nature. These views, however, breathe 
into the whole a spirit which desires to see Society shaped and 
moulded for a definite purpose, and a spirit which can criticise 
law and authority according to the eternal standards of Divine 
and Natural Law. Thus that claim which Luther only reluctantly 
admitted later on as part of the positive German law of the Empire, 
and which he always limited to the defence of religion against 
foreign aggression, seemed to Calvin to belong from the very 
beginning to the requirements of Natural Law, embracing the 
whole rational ethical formation of the State, because it is this 
which best develops a system of Positive Law, which provides the 
necessary subordinate powers for the control and reprimand of 
the supreme authority . 354 Although this theory still gives no place 
in the political scheme to the private individual, the wall of 
partition which prevents him from co-operating in the attempt 
to introduce an ideal order of the State has worn very thin, and 
will fall the moment that all the official courts cease to function. 
In reality Calvin’s idea of Natural Law is nearer to the Catholic 
idea of Natural Law than it is to the Lutheran conception from 
which it started. In particular it has no trace of that specifically 
Lutheran anti-rationalism, that glorification of authority for its 
own sake, as the form which the structure of Society has developed 
under the influence of sin, which it is possible for God-fearing 
princes to use, with the blessing of God, for the good of the Church, 
but which, as a rule, is only to be patiently endured, with all the 
suffering this involves, as the very opposite of love. As we shall 

954 See p. 899. 



PROTESTANTISM 


617 

see later on, circumstances intensified this distinction, and it 
assumed a fundamental significance for the whole history of the 
development of Calvinism. 

Social Theory of Calvinism 

Finally, however, an Ethos of this kind means— and here we 
come to the fifth point — the unified society, the Corpus Christianum , 
which is built up by the joint influence — different yet not divided 
— of the sacred and the secular authority. As in Catholicism and 
in Lutheranism, so also here, the dominant idea is that of a 
Christian civilization, of a Christian society, of a compulsory 
unity of Faith . 355 In Lutheranism this idea is conceived as the 
voluntary charitable service of the authority instituted by Natural 
Law, directed towards the ends of justice, natural peace and order, 
placed at the disposal of the purely spiritual organ of salvation, 
which must be endowed by the State with its legislative organs, 
and supported by it in its spiritual activity. 

In Calvinism this idea of the Corpus Christianum is regarded as 
the union of the Government which discerns its duties — both 
from the point of view of Christian and of Natural Law — in reason 
and in the Bible, and the active independent Church, which 
administers its own law of Divine justice for the Christianizing 
of Society, and also works with the State in the spirit of a common 
obedience to the Word of God. It is a uniform system of life and 
of Society as a whole, inspired by one common ideal in things 
secular and sacred, which therefore possesses a comprehensive 
sociological fundamental theory, developed by the very same 
methods used by Catholicism and Lutheranism to achieve the 
same end . 356 

Under the influence of the whole intellectual system of religious 
thought Calvinism produces, as has already been noted above, a 
quite different idea of personality from that of Lutheranism. The 
Calvinist, alone with God and his own soul, feels within himself 
the “grace of election” ; he uses it, and the effect on his own mind 
is very different from that which fills the soul of a devout Lutheran 
— whose main sentiment is one of loving self-surrender to God 
and a loving self-giving to his neighbour — ; the Calvinist is filled 
with a deep consciousness of his own value as a person, with the 
high sense of a Divine mission to the world, of being mercifully 
privileged among thousands, and in possession of an immeasur- 
able responsibility. This idea of personality, however, which 
arises out of the idea of predestination must not be confused 
865 See p. 899. 856 See p. 899. 



618 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

with modern individualistic and democratic ideas. Predestination 
means that the minority, consisting of the best and the holiest 
souls, is called to bear rule over the majority of mankind, who 
are sinners. It includes the idea that the existing conditions of 
life and authority — so far as they do not go against the Word of 
God — are Divine ordinances, to which man must humbly and 
willingly submit. Within these limits, however, Calvinism gives 
a value to the personality of the elect soul which is thoroughly in 
harmony with the idea of Kant, while in this respect Luther tends 
to remain within the range of ideas controlled by mysticism. 

Along with this strong emphasis upon personality, however, 
the idea of fellowship is also defined in a peculiar way, a pheno- 
menon which is most characteristic of Calvinism and which has 
already been noted. Fellowship does not arise, as in the Lutheran 
idea, merely directly out of the conditions of physical life, out of 
the existing institutions of the Lex Naturae , out of the invisible 
effects of the visible doctrine and use of the sacraments ; it arises 
far more out of the predestinating Will of God itself. Fellowship 
is not a method of working out the happiness of justification, in 
which, however, the freed soul, certain of its God, never spends 
itself wholly, but it is the purpose of justification and of sanctifica- 
tion, into which all the energy of religious renewal ought to flow. 
In spite of the isolation of the particular elect soul in the process 
of the working out of election, the same fact of predestination 
places the soul once more, in principle, in the fellowship which 
uplifts, supports, tests, and educates its members . 367 

This fellowship, like that of Israel, is always defined as a 
national community. God makes His Covenant with each natipn 
and requires loyalty in return for loyalty ; he educates the nation 
by punishments and visitations, and gives His Word in order 
that man should know His Will. Particular nations and churches, 
however, are closely united among themselves, and have a very 
strong mutual influence upon each other; all are for each and each 
for all. The idea of international religious unity belongs to the 
fundamental essence of Calvinism. A union of Christian nations, 
in which each nation, in its own sphere of influence, realizes the 
ideal of the Theocratic State; that is the Will of God, if its Scrip- 
tural significance is rightly understood . 358 

887 See p. 900. 

888 On all these points see Choisy and Kuyper. The international character of 
Calvinism was illustrated recently at the Geneva Jubilee, and is also displayed 
in the active translation activity, by which everything of importance which 
appears is translated into English for the benefit of the English-speaking 
peoples. Kuyper’s book itself is a monument of this international spirit. 



PROTESTANTISM 619 

Thus this fundamental theory possesses neither the somewhat 
vegetative character of the idea of the “organism”, (since it is 
directed towards the conscious and clearly determined aim of the 
individual), nor does it possess the Quietistic features of a pure 
Patriarchalism ; rather, it combines a strong sense of authority 
with the idea of the equal dominion of the law over all. Nor is 
it the conception of Society from the standpoint of the free and 
voluntary association, for it is produced by the guiding power of 
Providence in the natural sphere, and by the power of predestina- 
tion in the supernatural sphere. The creative Divine Will binds 
together and unites all in one positive aim, to which all are com- 
mitted, and from which all trace of arbitrary individual choice 
has been removed. On the other hand, this idea of fellowship 
is not conceived as the direction and unification of Society by 
means of a tangible supernatural priestly government, since it 
arises solely out of the common possession of the Spirit, and out 
of that harmony with Divine and Natural Law which this effects. 
Difficulties and complications are solved by the Bible, coupled 
with the deliberate decision of conscience in the sight of God. 
This fellowship is a common union in an objective Divine relation 
of interest and purpose; to this end the particular individual 
must dedicate his highest and freest personal energies, in which, 
however, all are most closely united to each other through some- 
thing which transcends all individualism. 

Thus this conception of fellowship is an entirely new form of 
the Christian sociological idea, in spite of the fact that its forms of 
expression remind us in innumerable instances of the conceptions 
of # Lutheranism, Catholicism, and the Primitive Church. Down 
to the present day the peculiar nature of this structure stamps the 
life of the Calvinistic peoples with a unique emphasis on the 
cultivation of independent personality, which leads to a power of 
initiative and a sense of responsibility for action, combined also 
with a very strong sense of unity for common, positive ends and 
values, which are invulnerable on account of their religious 
character. This explains the fact that all the Calvinistic peoples 
are characterized by individualism and by democracy, combined 
with a strong bias towards authority and a sense of the unchange- 
able nature of law. It is this combination which makes a conserva- 
tive democracy possible, whereas in Lutheran and Catholic 
countries, as a matter of course, democracy is forced into an 
aggressive and revolutionary attitude . 359 

869 Kuyper's whole book is steeped in these descriptions of the fundamental 
theory contrasted with that of the European democracy of France. Hence he 
draws the conclusion that the two distinct forms of democracy of America and 



620 THE SOCIAL TEACHIWft t>F THE' CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Closely united with this new form of sociological fundamental 
theory is the balance between the ideas of equality and of in- 
equality which is peculiar to Calvinism, and the aspirations which 
it evokes, both in democratic and radical, as well as in aristo- 
cratic and conservative, movements. This question has always 
constituted one of the main problems connected with the Christian 
conception of Society ; it was always further complicated by the 
fact that the Stoic doctrine, fused with the Christian social doctrines 
from time immemorial, had always maintained that in the Primi- 
tive State all men were equal, on the basis of the equal possession 
of reason and the power of exercising it, and from that hypothesis 
often enough equalitarian inferences for the present day had 
been deduced. Similar ideas have also appeared within the 
Christian doctrine of Society itself, especially among the sects, 
and their influence has confused the issue, down to the present 
day. In the midst of these complications Calvinism adopted a 
decided position, based on the statement that equality and 
inequality are nothing in themselves, and that their only value 
consists in the varying relations of men to one another. In the 
presence of God all men are equal, for in His sight all men are 
sinners, and all are equally bound to obey Him. On the other 
hand, in relation to each other they are unequal, for the Divine 
Ruler of the world has ordained that some should serve, and some 
should rule, as part of the essence of human life, and not as a 
result of the Fall. The essence of the Divine Nature is not reason, 
and that righteousness which satisfies all the demands of reason, 
from which one can postulate the equality of all men. It is rather 
that of the sovereign Will of the Ruler who elects one, and rejects 
another, according to His eternal and inscrutable purpose, which 
may not be measured by any order of reason which can be applied 
to all alike. 

Thus the whole social ideal of Calvinism is controlled by the 
sense that human beings are unequal by Divine appointment, 
and that the only equality which exists is that of incapacity to do 
any good in one’s own strength, and the obligation to render 
unconditional obedience to the Divine Will. The result is that the 
main features of this social ideal are essentially conservative and 
authoritative. The irrationality of God, of the order of the world, 
and of election is most strongly emphasized, existing institu- 
tions and governments are fully recognized . 360 

of France are the two great world Powers of the future, whereas in his opinion 
Germany seems foredoomed to weakness owing to its belief in pantheism. 

8 «° See p. 901. 



PROTESTANTISM 621 

On the other hand, however, equality before God is not 
conceived as a mere consolation, a higher point of view which 
lifts the individual spiritually above the misery of earth, but 
otherwise leaves everything just as it was before. On the con- 
trary, this idea of equality, combined with the living spirit of 
Church fellowship and of Calvinistic individualism, had a strong 
practical influence upon actual conditions of life. The moral 
tribunal has no respect of persons; its judgment applies even to 
those in the highest position of all ; it reminds all continually of 
their equality before God, and of their obligations to the Holy 
Community. The ministers avoided with scrupulous care any 
display of their position of authority, and in their weekly meetings 
they appointed a different chairman each time ; discussions with 
the laity about the truths of Scripture were instituted, in order 
to abolish the distinction between the clergy and the laity. The 
greatest possible emphasis was laid upon the idea that true 
Christian dignity regards questions of rank and position as matters 
of entire indifference, while on the other hand, every position of 
privilege is regarded as an obligation to the whole community. 
From the purely logical point of view there undoubtedly exists 
an unsolved contradiction in this emphasis first on one element 
and then on the other. Yet the main sociological problem of the 
relation of the individual to the community, as soon as it becomes 
a conscious problem in the stages of a higher intellectual develop- 
ment, always remains antinomian. Calvinism has balanced the 
two aspects of this antinomy in a very important and powerful 
manner. In so doing, along with the organic and patriarchal 
fundamental theory of the mediaeval idea of Society, Calvinism 
has become the second great Christian definite social ideal of 
European Society, which in its turn has also experienced a similar 
deep and broad process of expansion. All other social theories 
were, and are, too Utopian and too idealistic to be able to master 
the harsh phenomenon of the struggle for existence, and the com- 
plications introduced by self-interest. Indeed, the great importance 
of the Calvinistic social theory does not consist merely in the fact 
that it is one great type of Christian social doctrine ; its significance 
is due to the fact that it is one of the great types of sociological 
thought in general. In inner significance and historical power 
the types of the French optimistic equalitarian democracy, of 
State Socialism, of proletarian Communist Socialism, and of the 
mere theory of power, are, in comparison with Calvinism, far 
behind . 861 

861 See p. 902. 



622 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

In spite of its patriarchal spirit of authority, by means of this 
balance between fellowship and individualism, authority and 
freedom, compulsion and initiative, sobriety and enthusiasm, 
aristocracy and democracy, Calvinism still had a positive influence 
upon social ideals, not only within the sphere of the Church, but 
within the whole sphere of Christian Society in general. To the 
individual it gave the possibility of an extensive co-operation, and 
a claim upon the whole, as far as this was possible within existing 
limits. On the other hand, those who possessed social privileges 
were laid under such heavy obligations to the community, and 
their position of privilege was held to involve such self-sacrifice 
for the good of the whole, which subordinates should meet with 
reverence and trust, that all inequalities were swallowed up in a 
system in which the powers of all were engaged in a mutual effort 
for the good of the whole community. Calvinism was then, and 
still is to-day, a united body, with a common feeling and a sense 
of mutual responsibility among the Church members which, by 
means of labour and criticism in common, continually subordinates 
the common life afresh to ethical standards, and moulds it in 
harmony with ethical principles. Here then — for the first time in 
the history of the Christian ethic — there came into existence a 
Christian Church whose social influence, as far as it was possible 
at that period, was completely comprehensive. As we have 
already seen, Calvinism was “Christian Socialism 55 in the sense 
that it moulded in a corporate way the whole of life in the State 
and in Society, in the Family, and in the economic sphere, in public 
and in private, in accordance with Christian standards. It took 
care that every individual member should receive his appointed 
share of the natural and spiritual possessions of the community, 
while at the same time it sought to make the whole of Society, 
down to the smallest detail, a real expression of the royal dominion 
of Christ. 

From the preceding pages we see clearly why it was that only 
now did it become possible to make an experiment in social 
transformation in harmony with Christian ideals which was 
initiated by the Church-type, founded on real principles, and 
thorough in its effects and scope. Until that time, in the attempt 
to realize the ideals of Primitive Christianity in a thoroughly 
Christian organization of Society, the sect alone had led the way. 
But as a sect it was immediately placed beyond the legal pale 
of general civil society. Calvinism had, however, incorporated 
into its idea of the Church so much of the sect-ideal that it was 
obliged to make the bold attempt (i) of constituting its national 



PROTESTANTISM 623 

church as a church of professing believers, and (2) of constituting 
its unity of Church and State as a Christian society in the strict 
sense of the personal Christian faith and character of each indi- 
vidual member. On the other hand, however, Calvinism did so 
far remain a “Church” that it never questioned the ideal of a 
unity which included Society and the State, natural life and 
worship, and the separation of a holy separate community from 
the ordinary life of humanity always remained a crime. In order, 
however, to be able to attain both these ideals, in the last resort 
it found it necessary to modify and transform the real ideals of 
the Gospel in order to make them agree with its attachment to 
the popular morality of the Old Testament. It was by the adapta- 
tion of those Gospel ideals to the Old Testament and to the natural 
ethic that Calvinism so far adjusted itself to the practical condi- 
tions of life that it became possible to carry them out in practice. 
Even so, the demands that were left were highly pitched enough. 
In the severe earnestness of the religious excitement of the time, 
and under the pressure of great conflict for a hundred years, 
Calvinism actually succeeded in carrying out its ideal. 

At the same time, as we have already indicated, this “Christian 
Socialism” was quite different from its modern counterpart of 
any kind. It retained the institution of the sanitary police (which 
was part of the life of a mediaeval town), and the system of regula- 
tions and supervision created by the Guild- spirit, though without 
their monopolistic rigidity. But whereas in these previous develop- 
ments a Christian Socialism had already been formed, which had, 
however, remained under the control of the secular and civil 
authorities, the Church co-operating with the Government now 
took these matters systematically in hand. This ecclesiastical 
Socialism gave way certainly to the pressure of modern political 
and social developments. When, however, the technical and social 
effects of these developments revealed their dubious tendency, 
once again it was Calvinism which came forward with a new 
“Christian Socialism”, adjusted to modern conditions, yet still 
bearing traces of the Puritan spirit . 362 

Thus here also, in the last resort, the peculiar essence of 
Calvinism consists in the combination of the main ideas of Church 
and Sect in the sense of a fellowship, based upon religion, 
which, in spite of all that, is still new and original. It is this 
also which determines the form of its sociological fundamental 
theory. From this point of view we can understand how Calvinism 
is able to combine the most alert and active individualism with a 

##a See p. 903. 



624 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

solidarity which admits all social differences and relates them to 
each other, its intensification of the sense of personality and at 
the same time its inclusion (in the scheme of things) of the 
collective activity of politics and economics, its emphasis 
upon the equality of all men in the sight of God, and of the 
inequality of earthly vocations which involves the need for mutual 
service, its revolutionary habit of measuring all Society by an 
ideal standard, and its conservative sense for the need of law and 
order, for authority for actual historical situations. 

So much for the religious and ethical special characteristics of 
Primitive Calvinism ; it is actually a new spirit. Upon the whole, 
everywhere it maintained this spirit, all through that century of 
vast conflicts, by which, above all, it saved Protestantism from 
the policy of the Counter-Reformation. Yet in it all there is 
nothing, consciously and theoretically, that goes beyond the 
general intellectual level of the sixteenth century, beyond the 
ancient Catholic, Lutheran, Baptist, or Humanist ideas which 
prevailed at that time. All that its contemporaries perceived as 
its distinctive feature was its anti-Catholic radicalism. Lutherans 
in particular were only conscious of differences in doctrine and in 
worship. Calvin tried to treat these differences as though they 
were merely external and terminological, and he strove to main- 
tain the unity of Protestantism as a whole. It was the Lutherans 
alone who broke the unity, separating from Calvinism as though 
it were a heresy worse than that of Nestorius or Muhammad. 
The thinkers of that period concentrated their attention almost 
entirely upon dogma, and they scarcely perceived that the real 
heart of the difference lay in the sphere of ethics and of social 
doctrine. In actual fact this difference only expressed itself 
tangibly in the peculiar energy which Calvinism displayed in 
international diplomacy and the organization of churches ; 
everywhere it was busily at work, using every apparently open 
door in order to gain an entrance to foreign Courts, or to penetrate 
into the life of foreign peoples. Calvin’s corespondence reveals a 
theological diplomacy and a strategy which embraced the 
Continent. Where substantial success had been gained, Calvin 
required a complete break with the rites and ceremonies of the 
Established Church, and a public confession of faith, which was 
just as important as an entirely new structure and the organization 
of a community free from “devilish errors”. In this policy Calvin 
parted company entirely with Lutheranism, which was every- 
where ready to make concessions to the ancient Church, wherever 
the pure preaching of justification by faith was permitted, com- 



PROTESTANTISM 


625 

mitting all the rest to the miraculous power of the Holy Spirit. 
This energy, therefore, is the direct secret of the success with 
which Calvin outdistanced both Lutheranism and the Anabaptist 
movement. The programme of the new Church, which spread 
from Geneva outwards, and stamped a new character upon the 
nations which accepted it, may be summarized thus: a radical 
break with tradition ; a new Church organization on the principles 
of Calvinistic church-order, and the international relationship 
of the new churches which support each other in things material 
and spiritual. 

In all this there is no appreciable advance towards modern 
civilization. When, however, a rapprochement of this kind continu- 
ally pushes its way to the front as an actual fact, and when, 
finally, it appears that it has been caused by the development of 
Calvinism — even though in a very one-sided direction — without 
any departure from Calvinistic principle, it is evident that this 
rapprochement cannot have arisen out of the religious and ethical 
fundamental ideas themselves, but that it must be due to an 
adjustment of these ideas to actual conditions, which at first, 
scarcely visible, still contained within itself the possibility of future 
transformations. At the same time, from the very outset this 
adaptation must have been based inwardly upon the spirit of 
Calvinism. This particular religious and ethical feature must 
have been already present in germ in an indissoluble inward 
connection with the existing political and social conditions of 
civilization, whose results then came to light in the development 
of Calvinism, and made possible to it a capacity of adaptation 
to the modern bourgeois-capitalistic civilization which was lack- 
ing in Catholicism and in Lutheranism, or at any rate which did 
not appear to this extent. Only thus can we understand the 
comparatively direct development of Calvinism, which led, 
however, to a result so different from primitive Calvinism. 

Primitive Calvinism and Geneva 

In reality this is what took place. Since from the very beginning 
the Genevan situation helped to determine Calvin’s political, 
social, and economic ideal, it led to that adaptation to conditions 
which only revealed its full significance at a much later period. 
Therefore we must now inquire to what extent Calvinism itself 
was influenced by the general cultural situation in Geneva . 368 

The first effect of the Genevan situation can be stated very 

883 The same formulation of the problem in March 1 Coligny, /, /, p. 266. Here 
I am only trying to go somewhat further than Marcks. 

VOL. II. M 



6a6 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

simply: here alone there were actual conditions within which 
it was possible to realize Calvin’s ideal of a holy community . 364 
The ideal which was occupying Calvin’s mind was also influencing 
wide circles of the Reformation movement in Germany . 366 It 
was only in the States ruled by sovereign princes that there was 
no prospect of realizing this ideal, since it threatened their royal 
power. In the great and independent city-republics it came into 
conflict just as sharply with the traditional power of the great 
families, which was again becoming dominant after the shattering 
events of the Reformation. Even in Zurich, Zwingli was obliged 
to hand over his ideal to the secular authority in the State. In 
Strassburg, Lutheranism and the oligarchy destroyed the modest 
attempts begun by Bucer. Geneva’s neighbour, the powerful 
State of Berne, did not merely provide the clearest example of 
this kind of the exploitation of the Reformation in the interests of 
the oligarchy — it was also particularly hostile to Calvin ; all along 
it made life difficult for him, and it opposed the introduction of 
the independent Calvinist Church into the State, fearing that its 
own Church government might be endangered by this bad 
example. The fate, however, with which Berne threatened its 
neighbours hung over all the small dependent communities in 
Germany which desired to organize “Puritan Lay Christianity” 
in an independent congregational church. The danger of infection 
with these ideas was resolutely combated by the territorial lords 
or the neighbouring princes; finally, those who upheld these 
ideals saw no other course to pursue than to drift into the Baptist 
movement . 386 

In Geneva alone, on the contrary — which had won its political 
freedom and its constitution in the struggle against its bishop 
and against Savoy, and whose freedom was indissolubly bound 
up with the maintenance of the Reformation — where a young 
Government, without 367 traditions, was facing a very complicated 

884 Cf. also von Bezjold: K. d. G., II, V, /, p. 81 ; also Marchs' Coligny . 

865 On this point sec Barge: Karlstadt. This must make us cautious about 
accepting the view that Calvinism represents the specifically French and Latin 
aspect of the Reformation ; see also Hundeshagen, I, p. 2g3 ; Richer , p. 59 ; and 
Marchs' Coligny, I, 1 , p. 287 ; the right restrictions of this statement in Marchs, 
pp. 28g and 2g6. On Zwingli’s reform in this respect, see Kreuzer: Zwinglis Lehre 
von der Obrigheit, igog (Kirchenrechtl. Abdh . hg. v. Stutz, JVr. 57). 

868 Cf. Rothenburg's History of the Reformation in Barge, II, 2gg~3f3\ secessions 
to the Anabaptists, II, 432 Jf. 

887 Cf. the Jubilee inscription composed by Beza in 1 584, in which “the Restora- 
tion of the religion and the ancient liberties of Geneva* * are summarized ; 
see Choisy: L'itat chritien, p. 233 . 



PROTESTANTISM 


627 

political situation, was it possible to establish a community of 
that kind, which by the very fact of its own stability also gave 
coherence, support, and strength to the State, through the genius 
of its leader also providing a firm support for the political leaders. 
Even in Geneva, however, the old families inclined towards a 
State Church on the Bernese pattern, and Calvin only overcame 
their opposition after heated struggles ; in the end, however, he 
was successful. He was then able to establish a Church which 
obeyed the magistrates in all external questions, and exercised 
an independent system of discipline ; its stability was secured by 
the permanent presidency of Calvin himself ; the Church was the 
backbone of the young and immature State. Only thus was Calvin 
able to create a holy community which directed its own affairs in 
freedom according to the Word of God, protected by its pastors 
as its tribunes, and kept pure through the exercise of discipline, 
in agreement with the authorities. The general significance of this 
phenomenon consists precisely in this: we have here the union 
of a national Church and a voluntary Church, of the Church 
as the organ of salvation and the sect-ideal, a moulding of the 
common life on Christian-Socialistic lines which is impossible 
without the organized rule of Christian thought over Society; 
that, however, means (since in the end these ideals can only be 
represented purely and with full knowledge by the ministers) 
that Society cannot be influenced in this way unless the Church 
is supreme over Society. Every effort may be made to remove all 
traces of a hierarchy; the greatest possible emphasis may be laid 
upon the independence of the secular authority within its own 
sphere ; the free co-operation of each individual may be enlisted 
to the fullest extent; all this was done in Geneva: still, it is 
perfectly plain that unless the Church is supreme — unless she 
controls the State and social life in general — the whole thing is 
impossible. This is why this first thorough and extensive social 
evolution of Christianity was also the most theocratic. In his 
teaching on the independence and secular character of the State 
Calvin used exactly the same language as Luther ; since, however, 
at the same time he created a strong independent Church (based 
on the assumption of the Corpus Christianum common to all three 
confessions) through which he desired to effect a Christian and 
ethical transformation of the whole of Society and civilization, 
in practice he made the State subordinate to the Church. 

But although the actual situation in Geneva thus made it 
possible to establish Calvinist Christianity, yet on the other hand, 
in its strong admission of the independence and validity of all 



628 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 


secular institutions based on reason, this close relationship between 
Society and the Church also had a strong reflex influence upon 
the ethic and the social ideals of the Church of Calvin. 

Democratic Tendency of Primitive Calvinism 

The first sign of this influence can be traced in a certain demo- 
cratic constitutional tendency which the Genevan experiment pro- 
duced. It is, of course, possible to point out that Calvin’s personal 
point of view was as undemocratic and authoritarian as possible ; 
that, further, in spite of the fact that the whole community shared 
in the life of the Church, Calvin’s Church Constitution, with its 
basis in the Divine Church order and with its special connection 
with the aristocratic constitution of the city, was still in no sense 
a congregational democracy, 868 and, finally, that the Genevan 
Constitution itself, under the influence of Calvin, and in line with 
the spirit of the period, developed more in the direction of an 
oligarchy than of a democracy. 369 That is all quite true. Neverthe- 
less, in the last resort, the final effect of this interpenetration of 
a city-republic with a national Church was a strong impulse in 
the direction of democracy, towards the principle of the sovereignty 
of the people. The reason for that is that the whole aim of the 
Government was to secure the reasonable welfare of the individual 
which is required by the Law of Nature, and in this sense the 
State was to be conformable to reason. 

A far greater influence in the direction of democracy was, 
however, exercised by the fact that the final and decisive method 
of influencing the political authority in this sense was the appeal 
to public opinion, and to the electors, through the sermon. Jn 
all cases of difficulty the Cri au Peuple was the ultima ratio of Calvin 
and of his successors. Calvin worked against the dominant families, 
and influenced the elections, by stirring up the masses by his 
preaching, and by the use of denunciation and the censure of 
ungodly or unreasonable laws. The famous section in Calvin’s 
Institutes in praise of the republican constitution, the ardour of 
subjects for its preservation, and the duty of the authorities to 
respect it, appears first in those editions which were published 
after 1543, as a later interpolation in the text, which had other- 
wise remained unaltered since 1536. 370 During the first century 
of Calvinism, then, this right to the Cri au Peuple was also a con- 

868 See p. 904. 

389 The increasing oligarchy in Geneva in Marcks ’ Coligny , /, /, p. sgg, which 
emphasizes Calvin’s share in this development; see, further, Choisy: Vitat 
chritien , p. 148. 370 See p. 905. 



PROTESTANTISM 


629 

tinual subject of controversy between the magistrates and the 
ministers, as can be seen from the records of both bodies. Through- 
out this controversy the ministers always insisted on their con- 
scientious view, which they emphasized very strongly, namely, 
that they had no right to be “dumb dogs”, but that they were 
the tribunes of the people. By their outspoken criticisms they 
repeatedly intimidated the Council, which repeatedly requested 
that difficulties of this kind might be discussed in private before 
they were ventilated from the pulpit. It was only towards the 
end of the century that the Council succeeded in limiting the 
freedom of the ministers . 371 In actual fact, however, the policy 
of the Consistory really amounted to an appeal to the people 
as the actual sovereign authority. This becomes still more evident 
w'hen we remember that in all these matters the main questions 
were concerned with the interest of the people, with righteous 
legislation, with the administration of relief funds, with situations 
of economic and political distress, with bad customs and the like. 
In spite of the respect for authority inculcated by Calvinism, and 
the duty of obedience which was laid upon the private citizen, 
this was its real motto : By the people and for the people. 

It is, therefore, not at all strange that Calvin’s most loyal 
disciple and follower, Beza, in face of the Massacre of St. 
Bartholomew, and the irremediable godlessness of the French 
Government, finally altogether discarded the theory of the duty 
of subjects to be obedient, and that for such cases of need he 
frankly proclaimed the sovereignty of the people as the ultimate 
court of appeal. That is the meaning of his little tractate de jure 
mggistratuum, the authorship of which has only recently been 
attributed to him with certainty. His view of the question was 
still no rationalistic artificial law of the State, with State treaties 
and the like, but only the fundamental simple idea, that Divine 
and Natural Law make the people the ultimate source of law 
when all other appeals break down ; also that violent revolution is 
permitted, if no other means are left; that the authorities are 
bound by the positive laws which in any way contain the Natural 
Law, and that if these are lacking they are still bound to observe 
the Natural Law, which is tacitly assumed, and, in a case of 
tyrannical injury, it is permissible to warn the authorities by the 
courts which are called to that duty, and if their own conscience 
does not function they may be compelled to obey the law. This 
implies the sovereignty of the people, the right of revolution, 
and the binding nature of a constitution. All this, however, is 

871 See p. 905. 



630 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

imbedded in a mass of qualifying statements and modifications, 
which combine with this democratic individualistic spirit both 
the early Christian doctrine of authority and submission to 
authority, and the doctrine of Divine Right and the Divine 
appointment of the traditional authority. Beza points out that 
all these rights and duties do not directly concern the private 
individual, but only those whose legal standing in some way 
involves them in these questions : e.g. professional groups, lower 
magistrates, elective bodies, which have been appointed and 
commissioned to represent the interests of the people. Further, 
the point at issue is not an abstract question of moulding Society 
according to reason, but one of either improving or replacing 
a bad Government, whereupon then the old historic, and there- 
fore Divine, rights again come into force ; finally, all this is only 
permitted against a Government which has really deteriorated 
into tyranny, that is, against an executive power which per- 
manently disregards Natural and Divine Law, and which in 
principle disobeys both the First and Second Tables of the 
Decalogue. Beza’s theory is still a compromise between the 
doctrines of the Divine nature of authority which supports, and 
carries forward, the process of history under the guidance of God, 
and of the Christian duty of passive obedience enjoined by the Bible, 
with Calvinistic individualism and its rational ideal of Society, 
which is practically realized in the execution of one’s real duty 
for the glory of God, and whose inner meaning is summed up 
in the phrase, “We must obey God rather than man”. Even with 
Calvin it had been a compromise. Beza simply emphasized 
the individualistic, rational, and democratic element still more 
strongly. Beza himself suggests what it was which made this 
development of the theory possible by his appeal to the welfare 
of the people as the aim of the State, and by his claim for the 
right of appeal to the people against the Government, which 
logically involved the right of actual armed resistance as well. 
The rational idea of Natural Law in Calvinism, which was 
included in the Calvinistic ethic and combined with Christian 
individualism, here reveals its significance and its logical results . 872 

Beza and the “Monarchomachi” 

Beza used to expound these theories to an international body 
of students, but the Council decreed that his book must be pub- 
lished anonymously. It had, however, a positive and personal 
connection with a whole series of similar famous publications 

871 See p. 906. 



PROTESTANTISM 


631 

by theologians, jurists, and politicians. Hotmann read the 
manuscript, and it seems probable that both men planned the 
Franco-Gallia and Beza’s treatise at the same time. These two 
men, together with Henri Estienne and Gentillet, discussed the 
theory and the literary plan of campaign . 373 This is the literature 
of the so-called Calvinistic Monarchomachi or “opponents of 
monarchy”, to which belong also the founder of the independent 
Calvinistic ethic, Lambert Danaus, and men like Duplessis- 
Mornay, the author of the Vindicae contra tyrannos , an energetic 
supporter of the Centre Party in Calvinistic theology, diplomacy, 
and Church organization. It was at Beza’s suggestion, too, that 
the first report of the Massacre of St. Bartholomew was reissued, 
under the title of De furoribus Gallicis , although its actual author 
was the pastor Ricant; the orthodox theologian Jurieu also 
defended these theological, ethical, and political theories. 

In the whole of this literature, the ideas which Beza had 
developed, which represented the doctrine of the school of 
Geneva, reappear, with various adjustments and expansions, 
undoubtedly practically determined by the irreconcilable op- 
position to the French Crown, and by the fact of the Huguenot 
and Netherlands Revolt; but these ideas were still only a con- 
ceptually theoretical deduction from Calvinistic fundamental 
principles, and they were therefore characteristic in their range 
of ideas and possibilities. In all the literature of this kind the 
sovereignty of the people, the social contract, the right of 
revolution, the legal obligations of rulers, stand out very clearly; 
just as clearly, however, there appear also the genuinely Cal- 
vinistic limitations of all radical statements about Natural Law 
b^ the idea of historic, and therefore of Divine, right, and by the 
assumption that in principle humanity is unequal. 

The idea of a social contract, in particular, which is here 
introduced, is very far removed from its later purely rationalistic 
realization, which it experienced in the classical modern Natural 
Law of the Enlightenment, set free from theology. At no point 
does it deal with the question of the formation of Society itself 
on the basis of a social contract. Society rather is regarded in 
the light of the Aristotelian-organic theory; it is the formation 
of Society through Nature and reason with the common subor- 
dination of the differently placed members through the law 
which expresses reason. It is always first of all a question of the 
contract of sovereignty, which, it is assumed, is contained by 
Natural Law in every kind of sovereignty, and which has no 

873 Cartier , pp. 204 ff. 



632 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

need at all of any positive legal formulation, although such a 
formulation is mostly, in point of fact, present, and only needs 
to be brought forward again out of the old popular and class 
laws. 

At the same time this social contract according to Natural 
Law is interpreted essentially in the light of the Old Testament 
Scriptures, in which it is regarded as a covenant between God 
on the one hand and the ruler and people on the other; it is 
thus something quite different from the primitive social contract 
of classical Natural Law. The ideas of Natural Law and of 
a covenant are applied in a thoroughly theological manner, 
since they represent an original archetypal ingredient contained 
in the Bible and in every governmental relationship, whose aim 
is not so much that of making possible a rational construction 
of the State as that of the exercise of a moral and religious 
control of the dominant historic powers. Nowhere is there any 
question of a radical new structure of the State which would 
be indifferent towards the Divine right of that which had grown 
up through history. Therefore no kind of definite State organiza- 
tion is deduced from this, but, as in the case of Calvinism, it 
is left to the play of circumstances. The Calvinistic idea of the 
mutual obligations of the people and the ruling power, and of 
the significance of the elective corporations of the subordinate 
authorities, were only further developed, certainly in a sense 
which corresponds more to the Thomist and Humanist conception 
of Natural Law than to the strongly Lutheran authoritarianism 
of Calvin . 374 

John Knox * 

John Knox and the Scottish School went farther than Beza and 
the Huguenots in their departure from the original Calvinist politi- 
cal programme, but even they did not accept the purely rational- 
istic modern ideas of Natural Law. In his pre-Calvinist period 
John Knox had been influenced by John Major, who — although 
he remained a Catholic — advocated the Catholic doctrine (with 
which we are already familiar) of the sovereignty of the people 
with a strong democratic emphasis. This teaching seems to have 
left a deep and enduring impression upon Knox. It seems prob- 
able that this accounts for his harsh remarks abopt the murder 
of tyrants during this period. While he was in Geneva, Knox, 
under Calvin’s influence, accepted and assimilated the Genevan 
principles without any reservations. He then instructed the 

874 See p. 908. 



PROTESTANTISM 633 

Scottish and English nobles in their duty towards the cause of 
reform. He told them that, as magistrate inferieurs they were both 
entitled, and indeed bound, to support the cause of religious 
reformation, and to aid the Government in this question ; so far 
as resistance was concerned, he added, they were only justified 
in that attitude for the sake of the Gospel and of evangelical 
reform ; he deprecated the use of violence, however, and in all 
secular matters he enjoined strict obedience. When, however, 
Knox found that this policy rendered it impossible to attain the 
necessary means of power, and when he saw the danger that 
both in England and in Scotland the Queens would marry 
foreign Catholic sovereigns, which would lead to a systematic 
and entire suppression of the Gospel, he was forced into a 
position of resolute opposition to the hereditary monarchy, whose 
right of inheritance could lead to such madness, and which 
ensured no kind of protection at all against godless and unjust 
tyrants. He then demanded that monarchs should be chosen and 
controlled in exactly the same way as judges, and declared that 
the magistrate infirieurs possessed both the right and the duty of 
leading armed resistance against the “Tyrant”, up to the point 
of capital punishment. Finally, indeed, he summoned private 
persons, through voluntary associations and on their own initia- 
tive, into the work of religious reformation and the formation 
of churches, implying also that if necessary they ought to take 
an aggressive share in the exercise of political power. 

Doctrine of Popular Sovereignty 
This is the doctrine of the sovereignty of the people, based 
oil reason and on Scripture, the theory of the right and duty 
of violent resistance to godless rulers, even to the point of capital 
punishment if necessary, for the doctrine of the Covenant, and 
of the right to urge the people to revolt, and to fight for the 
sake of the Gospel. This doctrine was advocated by many sup- 
porters of the Calvinist ethic; in Scotland it was upheld mainly 
by Buchanan, who at the same time reveals a very strong 
Humanist tendency. It was the doctrine of the Scottish and 
English Presbyterians under the Stuarts, the doctrine of the 
Generals in Cromwell’s Army, who, in the prevailing confusion, 
regarded thenjselves as the only legitimate authority which was 
left. This is the doctrine which cost Charles I his head. But, for all 
that, its spirit is not republican, nor in harmony with the Natural 
Law of reason; nor is it Scriptural and conservative, and in 
harmony with the conception of Natural Law. The aim of this 



634 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

doctrine is only to control the Government in power in accordance 
with the principles of the rights of the people and the good of 
the Christian Church; so far as possible it is legitimist, and it 
is loyal to the most legitimist powers which still remain, after 
the actual legitimate authority has broken down. It is not con- 
cerned with building up the State rationally from the standpoint 
of the rights of the individual ; it only desires to control the powers 
that be according to the principles of the natural constitution 
of every State — that is, according to the Bible and the Natural 
moral Law. 

In this sense both the English and the Scottish Presbyterians 
were Legitimists. Cromwell himself was no theoretical republican, 
but a man who believed in legitimate authority, who allowed his 
hand to be forced by events, till they drove him into the situation 
in which his political genius for government could develop, and 
then he had to obey his own laws. 

The meaning of the whole theory has always been that which 
Knox expressed in his famous interview with Mary Stuart. She 
accused him of striving for power, of being an enemy of royalty 
and an instigator of rebellion. Knox replied : “God forbid that 
I should grasp at the exercise of power or set subjects free to do 
exactly as they like. My one aim is that Prince and people alike 
should obey God .” 375 

Althusius 

The first step towards a rational construction of the State, and of 
the whole of Society, from the point of view of popular sovereignty, 
was taken by Althusius, who appealed to the example of the 
Netherlands, just as the opponents of monarchy had evolved their 
theory after their hopes in the French Monarchy had been 
shattered. Althusius was a strict Calvinist ; he began his career 
as a master at the Calvinist Academy at Herborn; he then 
became Chief Magistrate of the Imperial city of Emden, on the 
frontier of the new Dutch republic; later he was called to 
Franeker, and then to Leyden, as a recognized leader in the 
Calvinistic doctrine of the State. Quite deliberately Althusius 
wished to make politics independent of ethics, theology, philo- 
sophy, and jurisprudence ; he desired to gather up the scattered 
materials which were then in existence in order to construct a 
new and independent discipline, utilizing the Natural Law and 
the Decalogue merely as bases upon which the actual political 
theory could then be built up. At the same time he held firmly 

875 See p. 909. 



PROTESTANTISM 635 

to the idea of a Christian society, and to the idea of close agree- 
ment between Church and State ; to this extent, therefore, he was 
still in line with the general thought of Calvinism. The net result 
of his teaching, however, was to dissolve the compromise which 
until then had existed between the historic idea of Divine Right 
and the rights of individuals. This was due to the following 
reasons : Althusius based his doctrine upon the theory of the 
original freedom and equality of mankind in the state of Nature, 
which in its turn produced Society in all its forms as a vast 
series of associations, rising with increasing degrees of complexity, 
through the corporation, the parish, the province, to a climax 
in the State. This theory was based on the idea of a social con- 
tract, whether explicit or implicit, and this distinguished it from 
the territorial sovereignty which alone had been taken into 
consideration up to that time ; sovereignty is vested in the whole 
body of the people ; both the “ephors” and the “chief magistrate” 
(or the magistrates and the King) only possess their authority 
as the delegates of the people. The main trend of his thought 
was influenced by the Humanistic ideas of Stoicism, by the theory 
of pure Natural Law. In this theory Althusius has discarded the 
view, current for so long, that the State must be ruled by its 
supreme ruler in harmony with the principles of Divine and 
Natural Law, through intermediate courts which take into account 
the rights of the people and the interests of religion ; rather he 
constructs his theory of Society from the point of view of the 
freedom and equality of individuals, together with those limi- 
tations required by the conditions which govern an ordered 
Society designed to serve the end of the Christian meaning of 
life . 376 


Grotius 

Hugo Grotius, however — the thinker through whom the Law 
of Nature and the contract theory first gained their importance 
in world history — explicitly severed the connection between these 
theories and Calvinism, strove to replace the Calvinist State 
Church system by a policy of toleration based on rationalistic 
and political motives, explicitly rejected the anti-monarchic 
doctrine as the starting-point of his political theory, and on the 
theological side became an adherent of that Humanistic Rational- 
ism which from the days of Erasmus had never entirely lost its 
influence, and which reappeared in the Arminian theology. 
Starting from the idea of the equality and freedom of the Primi- 

876 See p. 910. 



636 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

tivc State, he taught that the State was founded in contract, 
whose purpose was the purely rational aim of the common good ; 
into this theory he incorporates a theory of international law 
(in The Law of War and Peace), which totally excludes all thought 
of Wars of Religion at all. In spite of the fact that Grotius him- 
self was a devout Christian, these theories were formulated from 
an entirely secular point of view. The further history of this 
doctrine, therefore, does not belong to the history of Calvinism, 
but to that of the rational idea of Natural Law, whose democratic 
or anti-democratic development, from this time forward, had 
only a very loose connection with Christian thought. Grotius’s 
point of view was aristocratic, not democratic. In his case, 
however, that had nothing to do with religious motives; it was 
due to purely rational and political considerations; it is well 
known that Grotius, as a supporter of John of Olden-Barneveldt, 
was on the side of the merchant aristocracy. The contrast between 
Calvin’s phrase, “ Stat (in the Being of God) pro ratione voluntas ”, 
and the doctrine of Grotius, that the Law of Reason would still 
be valid even if — per impossibile — there were no God, throws a 
lurid light upon the great gulf which separates these two worlds. 
In taking this stand, Grotius’s position, like that of Leibniz, was 
closer to the Catholic theory of Natural Law than to the Cal- 
vinist, or even to the Lutheran theories. In reality this is a new 
world. When Society is constructed on a rational basis, and 
individualism is based upon the equality and freedom of the 
reason of individuals, then the spirit of Calvinism has disappeared, 
and we are faced with the fact that the rationalistic ideas of 
Stoicism have been set free from their fusion with Christian 
thought, and that this has given rise to a specifically modern 
individualistic habit of mind. In granting the religious conscience 
exemption from the duties of the contract with the State, so far 
as these were retained, as in the Anglo-Saxon world, it preserved 
some traces of Calvinism, although Spinoza also made a similar 
exception on purely philosophic grounds. But in the Natural Law 
of French Democracy, and, above all, in Rousseau’s theory, every 
trace of the Calvinist spirit has disappeared . 377 

Locke 

John Locke, the second great founder of the modern theory 
of Natural Law, can only be connected with Calvinism and its 
conception of the Christian Natural Law with certain reserva- 
tions. Locke had been educated, it is true, in a Calvinist atmo- 

911 See p. 910. 



PROTESTANTISM 


637 

sphere by his father, who was a Puritan soldier. His whole nature 
had a tendency towards a Calvinistic sobriety, industry, and 
utilitarian objectivity, and the whole temper of his mind was 
always characterized by a piety which was as fine and clear as 
it was warm and earnest. Early in life, however, he had formu- 
lated an essentially independent conception of Puritanism, and 
his later theories of the Church and of toleration belong to the 
sect-type and not to Calvinism. On the other hand, equally 
early in life, he conceived theology in a latitudinarian sense, 
and later on, under the influence of the Arminians and the 
Socinians, he developed these ideas in his own peculiar, very able, 
and original way, which was, however, entirely non-Calvinistic. 
The latter then combined with the former, so that his advocacy of 
freedom of worship also meant freedom for philosophical and 
theological interests, and security for freedom of thought outside 
the churches. Moreover, his liberal constitutional theory of the 
State is obviously connected with the theory of the Christian 
Natural Law of the Calvinistic, scholastic kind. He acknowledged 
his indebtedness to Hooker, whose Ecclesiastical Polity , in its first 
part, is an epitome of rational Christian Natural Law; in the 
second part, however, in honour of Elizabethan Anglicanism, 
it is twisted into a theory of the monarchy as the expression 
of the will of the people, supported by the obedience of the 
Church ; this is a great contrast to the majority of the Anglican 
exponents of political science, whose views found their clearest 
expression in the absolutism of Filmer’s Patriarcha , which was 
similar to the Lutheran doctrine of authority. But although 
Lqcke’s theory of Natural Law bears a great deal of resemblance 
to the Calvinistic theory, particularly in the following points: 
in the theory of the mutua obligation in the idea that the contract 
of sovereignty is tacitly contained in all State organizations, in 
the theory of the purely earthly and utilitarian character of the 
State, and of the right of the people to control and depose their 
rulers, his theory of Natural Law is fundamentally differently 
conceived. He blends the various ingredients which composed 
the previous theories of Natural Law in an entirely fresh way; 
he starts neither from Stoic rationalism nor from Scriptural 
revelation, but from a utilitarian empiricism, from which, how- 
ever, he often reverts towards the older ideas. His Natural Law 
results psychologically from the idea of the equality and freedom 
of all mankind in the Primitive State ; in his conception the state 
of Nature was one in which peace and reason prevailed ; men 
possessed equal natural rights to life, liberty, and property, and, 



638 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

in order to maintain these rights, the individuals, by means of 
a social contract, formed a body politic. This body had the power 
to protect these natural rights of man; and out of this social 
contract there arose the forms of government which individuals 
found necessary for their welfare. This Natural Law is under 
Divine guidance, it is true, and is Divinely reiterated in the 
Decalogue, and is thus in agreement with Revelation; but that 
which it produces is solely for the good of individuals, and not 
for the glory of God. 

The ecclesiastical communities stand completely alongside of the 
State, and are free associations which in all political and moral 
questions must adjust themselves to the order of the State; they 
are free only in worship and theology. Locke feared nothing so 
much as priestly domination, whether it be Catholic, Anglican, 
or Presbyterian in form. When friction arises (and this can never 
be entirely avoided) between Church and State in ethical ques- 
tions, Locke certainly recommends passive obedience, quite in 
the manner of Calvin ; in the case of permanent injustice on the 
part of the ruler of a State he would permit revolt, and the 
resistance of those who are most justified to do so, to the extent, 
finally, of revolution, since — and to him this is part of the moral 
order — we must obey God rather than man. 

Further, Locke regarded the ruling authorities which have 
emerged from the process of history as — indirectly — appointed 
by God, and he was a firm supporter of the positive law of that 
period, which to him in England* seemed to be a particularly 
happy incorporation of Constitutional Natural Law, and which 
also implicitly contains this Natural Law as its own presup- 
position, and its own standard. But these loud echoes of the 
Calvinistic Christian Natural Law do not drown the underlying 
tones, which are quite different: the complete removal of the 
idea of the glory of God as the religious end of the State, the 
idea of the sole sovereignty of God, of the theoretical inequality 
of individuals, and their obedient adjustment to things as they 
are. Here in Locke’s theory the dominating idea is rather one 
of the most versatile individualistic rationalism, purely utilitarian 
and secular in character, which can be abstracted as it stands 
from the religious setting of Locke’s theory ; at a later date this 
often actually took place. This rationalism rests upon such an 
independent basis, both in philosophy and in public law, and 
corresponds so closely to the secular idea of progress, and to the 
political necessities of the day, that its inclusion in the religious 
framework no longer had much inward significance. It stands 



PROTESTANTISM 


639 

alongside this framework, not within it, just as the religious 
associations exist alongside of the State. That, however, is the 
spirit of the Enlightenment and not the spirit of Calvinism. 

Thus in the Revolution of 1688 the establishment of the 
constitutional Kingdom of William III expressed far less of the 
Calvinistic idea of the mutua obligatio than the execution of 
Charles I had been an expression of the Calvinistic doctrine that 
the magistrats infirieurs have the right to mete out punishment 
to a tyrant. Still, there were plenty of people ready to justify 
the second Revolution on religious grounds of that kind. But the 
Revolution itself was essentially far more secular than the revolt 
against Charles I. 875 

Hobbes 

The third main founder of the modern conception of Natural 
Law, Thomas Hobbes, was much farther from Calvinism than 
Hugo Grotius and Locke. It is true that he also used the con- 
ceptual material of the Christian Natural Law, and even main- 
tained that in an ideal instance Divine and Natural Law and 
Order might actually coincide, not in fancy, but in fact. Only, 
Hobbes did not merely conceive the Natural Law of Society 
in an anti-idealistic manner, as based on pure egoism alone, 
but, above all, he regarded the essence of the social process 
which arises out of this egoism as the establishment of an autho- 
rity which, according to its conception, must be directly sovereign, 
and therefore must include power over religion and the Church. 
It is the induction of a purely absolutist theory from rationalistic 
premises, which in many respects reminds us of some of the 
Lutheran propositions. 

PuFENDORF 

Thus Pufendorf, who was a Lutheran, combined in a peculiar 
way the doctrine of Grotius with that of Hobbes, and also held that 
the authority of the Church is delegated to the Government. In 
a doctrine of this kind there is no trace of the spirit of Calvinism. 
Lutherans and Anglicans alone understood how to gather grapes 

378 Cf. the Letters on Toleration of 1683, and the Two Treatises of Government of 
1690 ; also Leztus: Der Toleranzbegriff, etc., and the very instructive work of 
Bastide , which describes the whole period, J. L .: Ses Theories pol itiques et leur 
influence en Angleterre, igo6 ; the views which are here expressed on matters and 
theories ecclesiastical are, however, often very misleading, see especially 
chapters v and'vi. — There is an analysis of Hooker in Lang: Ref u. Naturrecht , 
PP' 28-33 > bis originality, however, is here highly overestimated. 



640 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

from the thorns of Hobbism ; but it was the Enlightenment which 
reaped the chief harvest . 379 

It would, therefore, be an error to attribute modern French 
democracy, or even American democracy, directly to the influence 
of Calvinism. Not even its theories of Natural Law were essentially 
Calvinistic in origin. Rather, in their essence, they arose out of 
purely economic movements, and their theories grew up out of 
the common central stock on which both Christian and Humanist 
Natural Law was nourished, the culture of the Ancient World. 
So much, however, is true: to a remarkable extent Calvinism, 
more than Catholicism, and far more than Lutheranism, had 
prepared the way for the gradual emancipation of those theories 
from their connection with Christian thought, even though the 
Baptist movement was more radically effective in this direction, 
as we shall see when we come to the English Revolution. It would 
be truer to say that both these movements (the Calvinistic 
and Baptist movements) have prepared the way for modern 
democracy, and given it a spiritual backbone, rather than that 
they actually created it. Even this preparatory process developed 
against the actual intention of Calvinism. But even though this 
needs to be strongly emphasized, on the other hand it is evident 
that Calvinism, by means of the constitutional and critical 
Natural Law principle which it adopted in the Genevan situation, 
certainly had a facility for adapting itself to democracy, and that, 
finally, in its religious ideas, not only was there no hindrance 
at all, but they helped to create an affinity with it. However little 
the American lack of respect for authority accords with Calvin’s 
spirit, and, moreover, however alien to it Rousseau’s social and 
political rationalism may be, Calvinism can still combine with 
both inwardly, if the sovereignty of the religious sphere of life 
is preserved. 

Thus Calvinism has become that form of Christianity which 
has an inward affinity with the modern democratic movement, 
and can enter into contact with it without injuring its religious 
ideas. At the same time, by the very fact of its fundamentally 
religious and metaphysical individualism, by its retention of the 
idea of the essential inequality in human life, and by its con- 
servative feeling for law and order, it has escaped the most 

878 Cf. Lezius and above, 537; for the whole subject, see my article Moralisten, 
Englische in PRE*, and my article Das Stoisch-christliche Naturrecht und das modem t 
profane Naturrecht in H£, igu , also in Verhandlungen des ersten deutschen Soziolo - 
gentages , 1911, in which the instructive speeches made in the discussions are 
also to be found. 



PROTESTANTISM 


641 

dangerous results of democracy : mere majority rule and abstract 
equality. To what extent it may have itself contributed to this 
process of democratization it is very difficult to say in particular ; 
some developments which have strengthened it in this direction 
will be dealt with later on. It cannot, however, be denied that 
to-day Calvinism is inwardly united with democracy, and that 
its characteristic world outlook is based upon it. At the same 
time it has also everywhere come to terms with the sects, which, 
from the outset established more upon a democratic and in- 
dividualistic basis, to-day, along with Calvinism, represent the 
idea of an essential inward connection between democracy and 
Christianity. This last point will be treated more fully in the 
last section. In all that, however, Calvinism still remains the 
supreme spiritual force . 380 

Economic Ethic of Calvinism 

The second important point is the economic ethic of Calvinism. 
Its beginnings were insignificant, but it developed into a factor 
of the greatest historical importance, both in the development 
of the modern economic spirit and in that of Calvinism itself . 381 

From the outset, in its main features the economic ethic 
of Calvinism was also related to the corresponding aspects of 
Lutheranism. The Calvinistic ethic shared the Lutheran view 
about work, to which it assigned a high value, regarding it as 
the practical exercise of a calling appointed by God, and there- 
fore as Divine worship ; it also regarded it as a method of self- 
discipline and of diverting evil desires. Both Calvin and Luther 
advocated labour as a universal duty, and abolished monasticism 
ancl mendicancy. The Calvinistic economic ethic also agreed 
with the Lutheran ethic in its “anti-Mammon” spirit, its urgent 
desire for modesty and moderation, its observance of distinctions 
in rank, its campaign against luxury, which in this respect was 
prosecuted with unexampled severity by laws against luxury, and 
which was supported ecclesiastically by the moral tribunal. 
Calvin also believed that poverty fostered the Christian virtues 
more effectively than wealth, and he launched out into violent 
denunciations of the great commercial cities like Venice and 
Antwerp . 382 In spite of all this, however, Calvin influenced the 

810 This is all brilliantly worked out in the manifesto by Kuyper , which is often 
quoted. The restraining elements due to the religious tradition which English 
Liberalism contained stand out very clearly in Held: Z we 1 Bucher, etc. — For its 
influence upon Anglicanism, and its analogy with the sects, which to-day seek 
refuge within its camp, cf. Kuyper, pp. 8-10; Karl Hartmann is here also very 
instructive, see especially pp. 27-30 and 32. 381 See p. 91 1 . 383 See p. 91 1 . 

VOL. II. N 



64* THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

“Reformed” economic ethic from the very beginning in such a 
way that, as in the political sphere, it developed an utterly 
different spirit from that which animated the Lutheran ethic, 
both in its primitive and in its present form. This took place, 
however, without any special and conscious intention on Calvin’s 
part. To a very large extent indeed, the direction in which this 
ethic evolved was determined by the conditions which governed 
the practical situation in Geneva. 

This was the decisive turning-point: Calvin was convinced 
that this “anti-Mammon” Christian spirit could express itself 
and maintain its existence within the sphere of a society which 
was based essentially upon a money economy, upon trade and 
industry. Unlike Lutheranism in similar circumstances, ^Calvin 
did not hark back to the agrarian patriarchal form of life as the 
ideal with its closely knit self-contained family life, based as far 
as possible on primitive methods of production, but he recog- 
nized industrial production based on a money economy as the 
natural foundation and form of professional work alongside of 
agrarian labour. Calvin himself had a great deal to do with 
questions of industrial production, and he quite approved of the 
fact that greater profits were made in trade than in agriculture, 
since they were simply the reward of carefulness and industry. 
It is, of course, true that he urged the abolition of certain kinds 
of business which were questionable from the Christian point 
of view, such as the manufacture of playing-cards, but in 
general he was in favour of movement and progress. It was at 
Calvin’s instigation that, with the aid of a State loan, the manu- 
facture of cloth and velvet was introduced into Geneva a& a 
home industry, in order to give work to the poor and unemployed. 
Later on, when this industry had to be given up on account of 
the competition of Lyons, the manufacture of watches was in- 
troduced with the same aim. He had no desire merely to uphold 
existing customs and methods of gaining a livelihood. He never 
denied the necessity for the mobility of an economic system based 
on industry and trade. All this, however, was due to the Genevan 
situation and the Genevan atmosphere, which even affected his 
correspondence; his letters, indeed, deal constantly with the 
interests of finance, trade, and industry (from the point of view 
of the manual labourer ). 888 

** 8 Cf. the following quotation from the letter, De Usuris , CR XXXVIII, p. 247 : 
“Quid si igitur ex negociatione plus lucri percipi possit quam ex fundi cujusvis 
proventu? — Unde vero mercatoris lucrum? Ex ipsius, inquies, diligentia et 
industrial* 



PROTESTANTISM 643 

As a jurist and a townsman, from the beginning he may have 
felt differently about these things than Luther who was a monk, 
but from the sources it is plain that, in any case, in Geneva he 
could not think or feel otherwise, if he were to have a practical 
influence, and that he accepted this necessity without scruple or 
difficulty . 884 The reason why Calvin was able to accept this 
situation as he did was probably due to the peculiar character 
of his practical active ethic, which embraced the whole sphere 
of public life, and which set in the forefront those elements of 
behaviour which were practically possible to achieve, while the 
radical commandments about love and suffering were relegated 
to the background. If Luther had lived in Geneva under the 
same conditions we can hardly imagine that he would have 
thought and felt otherwise than in Wittenberg. If Geneva had 
been a specially large and active commercial town 385 it is of 
course probable that even Calvin would have felt it much more 
difficult to submit to the claims of Capitalism. In Geneva, how- 
ever, which was surrounded by hostile and rival neighbours, and 
whose territory was very small, the conditions were narrow and 
provincial. But it was precisely in this form that Calvin found 
Capitalism acceptable, as a calling which suited the existing 
conditions in the city, and which was capable of being combined 
with loyalty, seriousness, honesty, thrift, and consideration for 
one’s neighbour. It was just because the economic conditions at 
Geneva were so bourgeois, and on such a small scale, that Capi- 
talism was able to steal into the Calvinistic ethic, while it was 
rejected by the Catholic and the Lutheran ethic. 

hat is officially expressed, properly speaking, in the important 
fact that Calvin and the Calvinistic ethic rejected the canonical 
veto on usury and the scholastic theory of money, and on the 
contrary supported a doctrine of money, credit, and usury which 
were nearer to the modern economic idea, with limitations, 
certainly, with which we shall have to deal presently. In this 
Calvin abandoned the purely consumer’s standpoint of the pre- 
vious Christian ethic, and recognized the productive power of 
money and of credit. Calvin’s co-operation with the economic 
administration of the State, and his conception of the importance 
of a social life which was well ordered from the economic point 
of view, for the holy community, show that he felt an inner con- 
nection between economic progress and moral elevation. Calvin’s 
successors at Geneva went forward in the path which he had 
traced. Beza and the VenirabU Compagnie devoted much detailed 
#8< See p. 912. 886 On this point cf. Holl: Calvinreden , pp. 61 ff. 



644 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

care and thought to questions of economic prosperity and effi- 
ciency. They also watched to see that wealth was rightly distri- 
buted, and that proper relief was given to the poor, and work 
to the unemployed. In questions of this kind the Government of 
the State continually turned to them for their opinions and advice. 
They took an interest in taxation and in State loans, and in the 
rate of interest, which was always fixed with their approval. 
They gave their judgment in favour of the erection of a State 
Bank, both in order to bring to the State the gain of exchange 
of business and to create cheap credit for the trades which were 
needing assistance . 386 

Calvinism and Capitalism 

Thus this economic practice of Geneva became the starting- 
point from which Capitalism was incorporated into the Calvinistic 
ethic all over the world, though with caution and under certain 
limitations. Conditions among the French Huguenots, in the 
Netherlands, and in England, each with their own characteristics, 
also helped to adjust modern business life to the religious point 
of view. One very important aspect of the situation is the fact 
that the Calvinists in France and England, and at the outset 
also in the Netherlands, and, above all, during their period of 
exile on the Lower Rhine, as minorities were forced out of public 
life and official positions in the State; they were thus obliged, 
in the main, to go into business life. Apart from this, however, 
the Calvinists displayed a strong tendency in this direction, even in 
circumstances which were not particularly favourable to business 
life; their industrious habits, their detachment from the world, 
and their rational and utilitarian spirit certainly strengthened 
this tendency . 387 

The economic situation in Geneva, however, contained the 
germ of logical developments which went beyond the intention 
of Calvin and the Genevese. Once Capitalism had been accepted, 
even with many precautions, given the right milieu, everywhere 
it led to results which increased its power ; while the specifically 
Calvinistic habits of piety and industry justified its existence and 
helped to increase its strength, which gave it in the Calvinistic 
communities a special character and a peculiar intensity . 388 The 
exhortation to continual industry in labour, combined with the 
limitation of consumption and of luxury, produced a tendency 
to pile up capital, which for its part — in the necessity of its 

888 Numerous examples in Choisy : Vitat chritien ; banks established, pp. 36 ff* 
and 187 ff. 887 See p. 912. 888 See p. 915. 



PROTESTANTISM 


645 

further utilization in work and not in enjoyment — necessitated 
an ever-increasing turnover. The duty of labour, coupled with 
the ban on luxury, worked out “economically as the impulse to 
save”, and the impulse to save had the effect of building up 
capital. To what extent these developments took place every- 
where is a separate question. Upon the whole, however, this 
result belonged to the very nature of the case, and it is the general 
opinion that this is what actually took place among the most 
important Calvinistic peoples . 389 

This, however, is not the main point at issue. The contribution 
of Calvinism to the formation of the Capitalist system itself is 
not the most important aspect of the question. This only becomes 
clear when, with Weber and Sombart, we inquire into the 
ethical “spirit” and the world outlook, or the “economic temper” 
which gave the system its firm hold over the minds of men, and 
which, in spite of its opposition to natural human instincts, has 
been able to strike root in human minds as a firm conviction. 
Economic traditionalism, interrupted by unscrupulous indivi- 
duals who are simply out for gain, is much more in line with 
ordinary human instincts than the concrete and abstract dominion 
of labour and profit, as ends in themselves, the continual increase 
of work produced by every fresh profit from labour . 3893 It is here 
that we perceive the importance (together with the related, yet 
different, effects of Judaism) which the peculiar Calvinistic type 
of the inward ethical attitude has gained towards the performance 
of labour in business life, and its religious estimate of the earning 
of money. The Protestant ethic of the “calling”, with its Cal- 
viqistic assimilation of the Capitalist system, with its severity and 
its control of the labour rendered as a sign of the assurance of 
election, made service in one’s “calling”, the systematic exercise 
of one’s energies, into a service both necessary in itself and 
appointed by God, in which profit is regarded as the sign of 
the Divine approval . 390 This conception of the “calling” and 
of labour, with its taboo on idleness of every kind, with its 
utilization of every chance of gain, and its confidence in the 
blessing of God, now, however, to a great extent approached 
the commercial professions and the business of making money. 
It laid the foundation of a world of specialized labour, which 
taught men to work for work’s sake, and in so doing it produced 
our present-day bourgeois way of life, the fundamental psycho- 
logical principles which gave it birth, which, however, it was 

889 Cf. Weber: Antikritisches , XXX, rgiff.; Schlusswort, XXXI, 594 ff- 

8888 See p.916. 880 See p.916. 



646 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OP THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

not bound to perpetuate once this way of life had become the 
constitution of the modern world. 

Thus there arose a current— definite, particularly powerful, 
and influential— of the bourgeois capitalistic spirit, which was 
pre-eminently typical of the bourgeois way of life in general. 
This was the predominance of labour and of the “calling”, of 
industry for its own sake, a process of objectifying work and the 
results of work, which was only possible where work was exalted by 
means of an ascetic vocational ethic of that kind, into the sphere 
of that which is necessary in itself by means of the underlying reli- 
gious conception. Calvinism, which in its early days included a 
good many groups of the aristocracy, was at first indifferent to 
social questions, but in the course of the political development in 
various countries it became bourgeois ; this social transformation, 
however, was entirely in line with certain elements in its spirit. 891 

It is obvious that such a conception of Capitalism would easily 
glide into a purely secular conception, once the religious motives 
had weakened and the religious atmosphere had begun to 
evaporate. From the time of Adam Smith, indeed, the classical 
economic theory has constructed the foundations of economics 
in precisely the opposite sense, in pure hedonism. Here, however, 
the opposition to the religious ethic was not due to its Utili- 
tarianism. In secular matters, and especially in economics, 
Utilitarianism was already the exclusive economic principle. 

In this respect English economic science only continued the 
fundamental religious convictions. The modern and anti-Calvinist 
elements only appear in radical individualism, in the intro- 
duction of the idea of equality, and in the abolition of respect 
for authority, class privilege, and the welfare of the whole. Just 
as in the case of the formation of the political theories, therefore, 
the groups of theorists divide into two sections : those who are 
rather conservative and those who are radically individualistic. 
Adam Smith himself, like Locke, was still torn in both directions. It 
was only the arrival of Bentham and his school which finally broke 
the thread which united the new economic ethic with the old. 391a 

3,1 On this point, and on the relation between mediaeval Capitalism and the 
Catholic ethic, as also on the other kinds of Capitalism which are neither 
ascetic nor bourgeois in tendency, see Weber , XXX , pp. 193-197* 

3,la Cf. Held, pp. 144-342 ; p . 249 on Bentham : “However little the doctrine 
was new in itself, its one-sided application in England by Bentham was some- 
thing new: it signified Rationalism pure and simple, and a complete break 
with the Puritan traditions of the English democracy.” Here also it is of French 
origin as Held emphasizes. For the conservative ethical elements in Smith, 
see Held, pp. 154-175. 



PROTESTANTISM 


647 

The Manchester School, with its doctrinaire optimism, the 
brutal glorification of competition as the survival of the fittest 
in the struggle for existence, and finally the thoughtlessness with 
which to-day capitalistic civilization accepts as its destiny its 
feverish labour, its crises, its specialization, and its vocational 
humanism — all this means a completely altered world. All this, 
however, belongs to the history of economics, and not to that 
of Calvinism. In connection with the sects there will be a good 
deal more to say on this subject later on. 

The significant point which is important even to-day for our 
subject is this : that in these Christian circles, and in them alone, 
was it possible to combine modern economic activity with 
Christian thought, and, indeed, that down to the present day it 
is possible to do this with a clear conscience. In this connection 
we only need to recall the circumlocutions with which Catholicism 
tries to make this modern form of economic life tolerable, and 
how, at bottom, it continually attempts to restrain it, or the 
revulsion with which early Lutheranism and contemporary 
German Conservatism officially regard Capitalism. Seen in this 
light, the significance of this new Calvinistic form of Christianity 
for the whole modern development, and especially for the position 
of Protestantism within it, becomes plain. It is the only form of 
Christian social doctrine which accepts the basis of the modern 
economic situation without reserve. The reason for this does not 
lie in any supposed “greater insight” into the essence of the 
economic processes, but in the fact that here the super-idealistic 
and Pietistic hindrances in the fundamental ethical idea have 
fallen away, which would have otherwise hindered or restrained 
this development; because, on the contrary, the Calvinistic 
ethic contains energies which directly further this economic 
development . 392 

Whether a Christian ethic of this kind, contrasted with that 
of Catholicism and of Lutheranism, is entirely an advantage, 
whether it is not tinged rather strongly with the spirit of “busi- 
ness” and the avidity of a materialistic outlook on life, is another 
question. The main point is that it is peculiar to the leading 
modern nations, or at least to majority groups amongst them, 
and that it here effects an adjustment to the modern economic 
world which has not been achieved by the Christian piety of 
other nations. 

The Christian element in this Calvinistic justification of Capi- 
talism would, however, be greatly misunderstood if one did not 

392 See p. 917. 



648 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

at the same time remember the limits with which the real 
Christian idea of love here also surrounds the ethic of industry, 
and which have continued to exert a beneficent influence right 
down to the present day, wherever, in all capitalistic labour, the 
main Calvinistic ideas have remained vitally alive. Labour is 
asceticism, an asceticism which is absolutely necessary. Profit is 
the sign of the blessing of God on the faithful exercise of one’s 
calling. But labour and profit were never intended for purely 
personal interest. The capitalist is always a steward of the gifts 
of God, whose duty it is to increase his capital and utilize it for 
the good of Society as a whole, retaining for himself only that 
amount which is necessary to provide for his own needs. All 
surplus wealth should be used for works of public utility, and 
especially for purposes of ecclesiastical philanthropy. Thus the 
Genevese assessed themselves to the furthest possible limit for 
special cases of need, and gave regularly in support of the local 
poor as well as for the numerous refugees. The charitable activity 
of the Church which was exercised by the board of deacons was 
part of the requirement of the Church-order instituted by God, 
was organized with great energy, and, with the aid of voluntary 
gifts which were often amazingly large, it was able to cope with 
the demands made upon it. This is the origin of the practice 
known among us through the example of American millionaires 
— in which even men who have become quite indifferent to 
religion will give a large portion of their profits for public pur- 
poses. The actual theory and practice of money and interest has 
also been determined by this spirit of philanthropy. 

Only “productive credit 55 for business purposes is allowed, not 
“usury credit 55 , which is simply used for living on interest. From 
poor men, or people who have been otherwise harassed by mis- 
fortune, no interest is to be taken; loans also were not to be 
refused for lack of securities. Arrangements of that kind are only 
to be carried out with reference to the good of the community 
as a whole. The debtor ought to gain just as much from the 
money as the creditor. The law of cheapness ought to prevail 
everywhere, in accordance with the principle of the Gospel and 
of the Natural Law, that “whatsoever ye would that they should 
do unto you, do ye also unto them 55 . Finally, the rate of interest 
ought not to exceed a maximum, which is to be legally fixed 
according to the needs of the situation. This was the theory. In 
Geneva practical life was regulated in accordance with these 
principles. The fight against usury and the exploitation of the 
poor fill the protocols of the Council and of the Consistory, and 



PROTESTANTISM 


649 

these Christian-Social elements of Calvinistic doctrine have also 
left their mark upon ethics. Thus we can understand how it is 
that within Calvinism, in the face of the modern development 
of Capitalism, there has always been, and still is, a tendency to 
merge into a form of Christian Socialism. We have already seen 
that a Socialism of this kind was contained, from the very outset, 
in the Genevan ideal of the Holy Community. It was continued 
in the “communities under the Cross”, where the religious idea 
developed freely. How far it helped to determine the State 
legislation of Calvinistic countries has still to be discovered. 

The great English system of legislation which deals with the 
poor, with workmen and with wages — in the guild-professional 
sense and, above all, with respect to education for work — bore 
traces of its spirit. In opposition to the “Manchester” conception 
of the State and of economics, Carlyle deliberately asserted the 
old Puritan ideas. The Christian Socialism of the English people 
at the present day is essentially of Calvinistic origin, and the 
activity of the American churches is often of a Christian Socialist 
kind directed against the abuses of Capitalism. In Switzerland, 
in the Netherlands, in England, and in America there are to-day 
Socialist clergy, whereas within the sphere of Lutheranism such 
a phenomenon is regarded as an offence against the sacred 
foundation of the Divine order, as taking part in purely secular 
matters, as a reprehensible revolutionary spirit, and a human 
intervention in the order of Providence ; among us social heresies 
are more dangerous and more objectionable than doctrinal here- 
sies. The meaning of that is, however, that Calvinism is in closer 
agreement with modern tendencies of social life than Lutheran- 
isrn, or than Catholicism, which, at least in the Latin lands of 
its origin, likewise holds these heresies at arm’s length. This also 
is the basis of that intense self-consciousness of Calvinism, the 
sense that it is the only form of Christianity adapted to modern 
life, because, on the one hand, it is able to justify modern forms 
of economic production before the tribunal of conscience, and 
because, on the other hand, by means of Christian Socialism, it 
strives to rectify the abuses of the system when they occur. It is 
very conscious of representing “modern Christianity” — not be- 
cause it is in touch with modern theological thought (for its 
theological tendency inclines to conservatism, and it is only its 
overwhelmingly practical character which leads to dogmatism 
being relegated to a secondary position), but because it is in 
harmony with the political and economic way of life, and under- 
stands how to further and yet to define its problems, whereas 



650 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

it considers that Lutheranism is philosophically diseased, un- 
practical, and remote from the problems of ordinary life . 898 

Calvinism and International Policy 

Of less importance for later times, but all the more important 
during the first century of its existence, was a third tendency, 
by which Calvinism was influenced by the Genevan situation, 
and then by later political and ecclesiastical developments. This 
was the tendency to form a religious system of politics and of 
international mutual support — that is, the policy of armed inter- 
vention. Since the independence of Geneva was intrinsically 
bound up with the fortunes of the Reformation, it could only 
be permanently maintained by federation with the Protestant 
Powers, the Reformed Cantons, and with their German co- 
religionists, for its independence was menaced perpetually by 
France, Savoy, and Berne . 894 Further, Calvin was often only able 
to maintain his position in Geneva itself with the support of the 
foreign churches, whose opinion and agreement he often solicited, 
and which aided him in difficult and complicated situations. 

To that we must add the missionary impulse, and the urge 
towards universalism which has already been described, which 
certainly at first based its confidence solely upon the Word and 
the power of Truth. In practice, however, it soon found that 
diplomatic and secular methods were absolutely necessary ; more- 
over, in the school of Genevan politics these measures had forced 
themselves upon the attention of the leaders as necessary for the 
primary aim of self-preservation. In foreign policy also these 
methods became necessary, and had to be recommended to other 
churches. The diplomatic correspondence of Calvin, the activity 
of Beza as a political agent, the Huguenot, Netherland, and 
Palatinate negotiations, are all well-known expressions of this 
necessity. In theory this practical necessity was reflected in the 
doctrine of the union of all Protestant churches and their duty 
of mutual support, which of course implies the same obligations 
for the States and commonwealths which were united with 
them . 395 Certainly at first the only immediate result was the 
necessity for financial, personal, and theological support, and for 
diplomatic assistance . 396 But immediately the further question 

#M See p.918. 994 See p.919. 

991 Cf. Brief e, 131; which deals with the question of international mutual 
support; similarly 7, 157. On Calvin’s international spirit, see Richer, p . 184. 
m Calvin’s letters give very many illustrations of this point ; it is his ideal to 
strengthen a position of power through diplomacy, but apart from bloodshed, 
as he says with reference to Condi: Brief e, II, 334. 



PROTESTANTISM 


651 

arose : to what extent may and should this help take a military 
form? I.e. how far are Wars of Religion both permitted and 
enjoined as the ultimate method of decision? The important 
decision in favour of Wars of Religion — so fundamentally different 
from the Lutheran position — was not in harmony with Calvin’s 
mind and spirit. His views on war in general were exactly the 
same as those of Luther . 897 War, he held, is a matter which con- 
cerns the State, which is permitted to use it for the secular pur- 
poses of defence, provided that it is waged with no confidence 
in the arm of the flesh and with trust in God, in all humility 
and Christian austerity of morals. The interests of religion, on 
the other hand, must be promoted without the power of the 
sword, purely in dependence upon Providence, through suffering 
and endurance ; they are not to be mingled with secular methods 
of exercising power. The constant recourse to diplomacy, how- 
ever, was already, in effect, a use of secular methods, and it was 
in the very nature of the case that on occasion this diplomacy 
had to take the ultimate step of armed intervention. Just as 
Calvin’s teaching on the duty of subjects to obey the Government 
was broken down by his other tenet: that the lower magistrates 
were entitled, on occasion, to exercise the “right of resistance”, 
and take up the reins of government, so also his teaching about 
peaceful intervention became ultimately, on occasion, one which 
admitted the right of armed intervention. Of course, a legal reason 
had always to be found for this step, just as for the “right of 
resistance”. This was discovered as soon as the ruling power had 
become a “tyrant”, and the lower magistrates had taken his 
place; they were then also empowered to form alliances with 
foreign Powers. Thus the doctrine of the expansion and main- 
tenance of the dominion of Christ by purely spiritual means 
became merged with the recognition of the right of armed inter- 
vention and of Wars of Religion, so long as, in so doing, the legal 
order was preserved . 398 This led to the right and the duty of 
military support in general; thus that which had been forced 
upon Calvinism in actual case of need was then justified in theory. 
In accordance with this Beza thoroughly investigated the whole 
subject of “Wars of Religion” and of armed intervention, as well 
as of the “right of resistance”, and he based his affirmative reply 
upon the Bible, upon History, and upon Dogma. From that time 
forward both questions were closely connected in the literature 
of the earlier opponents of monarchy . 399 
It is well known that this view attained immense practical 

397 See p. 919. gee p. 920. 899 See p. 920. 



652 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

importance, and that the example of Calvinism finally also 
affected the Lutherans in the Thirty Years War, who, on the 
occasion of the War of Schmalkalden, had indeed already dis- 
cussed the same problem. When the period of the Wars of Religion 
was over, in which Cromwell had given a last example of Protestant 
policy, this doctrine then became meaningless, but as a relic of 
those times there has still remained, right down to the present 
day, a strong sense of the close connection of all Calvinists with 
each other, an international Calvinism, with which the very 
individualistic Lutheranism of the present day, in spite of its 
Lutheran Conferences, cannot in any way compare. 

International Calvinism, after it had given up the theory which 
justified “Wars of Religion”, and the gradual severance of its 
connection with the State — while it became more and more 
democratic and capitalistic — went over to the pacifist position in 
this problem of war, which is so difficult for the Christian ethic. 
A war, like the Boer War, for example, may possibly be justified 
for reasons of national self-preservation, but Christian nations 
in general ought not to bring other nations to such a pass that 
they feel obliged to wage a war of that kind. 

The humanitarian and ethical movement against war, which 
aims at substituting a system of covenants and courts of arbi- 
tration in place of war, is pre-eminently at home among Cal- 
vinists and the sects ; they take the whole question very seriously, 
and struggle hard against the Imperialistic tendencies, which are 
indeed closely connected with the process of economic develop- 
ment of the nations to which they belong . 400 

Social Philosophy of Calvinism 

Summing up the results of these inquiries, we then begin to 
understand the social doctrines which are peculiar to Calvinism, 
and their development beyond their early position, which at the 
beginning seemed so much like that of Luther. These social 
doctrines are a product of the particular religious and ethical 
peculiarities of Calvinism, which revealed a marked individuality 
in the doctrine of Predestination, in the voluntary principle, in 
the tendency towards organization, in activity, and in the idea 
of a “holy community”, and also in its ethic, which aimed at 
achieving that which was possible and practical. On the other 
hand, however, they are a product of the republican tendency 
in politics, the capitalist tendency in economics, the diplomatic 
and militarist tendencies in international affairs; all these ten- 

400 See p. 921. 



PROTESTANTISM 


653 

dencies at first radiated from Geneva in a very limited way; 
then, however, they united with similar elements within the 
Calvinistic religion and ethic, and in this union they became 
stronger and stronger; until in connection with the political, 
social, and ecclesiastical history of particular countries, they 
received that particular character of the religious morality of 
the middle classes (or bourgeois world) which is so different from 
the early Calvinism of Geneva and of France. The results of this 
development were gathered up by the natural-philosophical and 
theological ethic, which, quite unlike Lutheranism, was highly 
developed in Calvinism, and which made steady progress from 
Galvin to Jurieu and Lampe . 401 The social doctrines of Calvinism 
have already been described sufficiently fully in the preceding 
pages. The fundamental sociological theory of Calvinism, its 
doctrine of the State and of economics, have emerged clearly 
from this analysis, and there is no need to sum them up again. 
The only point in which a summary of this kind would be useful 
is the conception of the Church. In Calvinism the Church is 
both national and free, a holy community, and an objective 
institution, a voluntary and a compulsory organization, since it 
is based upon the assumption that all the elect, if they are 
sufficiently well taught, will open their minds to the Truth, 
while it is required that all the non-elect must be suppressed, 
to the glory of God and for the protection of the elect, and must 
be prevented from expressing both their unbelief and their non- 
morality in public. Thus this is the union of the sect and the 
Church ideal, minus a Royal Head of the Church and patronage. 
The Church consists of the whole body of the elect, but that 
cloes not mean that its main idea is democratic, for the con- 
gregation is only allowed to give its silent consent to the decisions 
of the Church leaders, and the right to protest is only permitted 
in extreme cases. The Church government is in the hands of 
the official office-bearers, who are placed in office according to 
the Divine Church-order: i.e. the ministers; the courts of dis- 
cipline, the teachers and deacons, who are systematically ap- 
pointed apart from the tumult of the popular vote, and who do 
not represent the Church but the Word of God. The classical 
constitution and the system of synods made this Genevan idea 
suited to the conditions among great nations, but it did not alter 
its spirit. 

In questions of faith and morals the Bible constitutes the final 
court of appeal. Throughout it is assumed that its meaning is 

401 Sec p. 921, 



654 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

plain and clear; when uncertainty arises the meaning may be 
settled by reference to some of the most highly respected con- 
gregations, whose opinion would give added weight to any 
decision. This Church showed its independent position in the 
following ways : by its independent exercise of moral judgment ; 
by a widespread, system of supervision and denunciation of 
individuals ; by its authority to exclude members from the sacra- 
ments, which meant a civil boycott as well; and by its respect 
for, and its occasional influence upon, the municipal legislation. 
In addition, however, the Genevan Church also counted upon 
the voluntary support and co-operation of the civil authorities, 
who also took the Bible as their standard. In practice, however, 
there was continual friction between the Church and the civil 
authority on the question of excommunication. Thus in spite of 
the supposed unity of the Corpus Christianum Calvinism found it 
impossible to avoid friction with the State. There was conflict 
everywhere, not only in Geneva. In England and in the Nether- 
lands this friction led to serious conflict and vast catastrophes, 
the effects of which we still have to consider . 402 

The Calvinist doctrine of Society has already been described 
sufficiently in the preceding pages. In Geneva it bore a quite 
overwhelmingly bourgeois-industrial and financial character. We 
have yet to discover how it worked out in the rural regions in- 
fluenced by Calvinism, where the peasants were under the con- 
trol of the landed nobility. In any case, the general idea of Society 
was overwhelmingly bourgeois, and became so more and more. 
Calvinism was even accused of hatred of the aristocracy. This 
is enough to account for the class and guild organizations 
of the day, although unlike Lutheranism the question of 
stability is practically ignored; indeed, the frequent changes 
of work, and the vicissitudes of fortune in the refugee com- 
munities in general, made stability impossible. Characteristically 
there is no trace of the crude Lutheran doctrine of the three 
classes. 

Wherever class distinctions do appear, as in the legislation 
against luxury, we see that the social organization was varied; 
social distinctions, however, depend entirely upon a man’s pos- 
sessions. Possibly certain plutocratic characteristics which are 
still visible in the life of Holland and America may be connected 
with this fact. Above all, however, the idea of equality in the 
sight of God is emphasized far more strongly here than in 
Lutheranism, and in Church-life, especially in the exercise of 

401 Sec p. 921. 



PROTESTANTISM 655 

discipline, it was carried out far more explicitly. In Geneva 
violent conflicts raged round this question. We all remember 
how John Knox explained to Mary Stuart how all men, even 
kings, are equal before the Law of God. The Board of Discipline 
did not hesitate to deal with the Huguenot nobility. In spite 
of the retention of external differences, and of the strict loyalty 
which tjiis involved, this idea of the equality of all men in the 
sight of God undoubtedly caused a ferment of democratic ideas. 
Kuyper has rightly pointed this out in his manifesto of modern 
Calvinism ; this tendency was, however, modified by the charac- 
teristically patriarchal elements within Calvinism. From the very 
beginning it was a social ideal which combined democratic and 
aristocratic elements, which also exercised a restraining influence 
upon each other. This social ideal attained an exalted spirit of 
independence from earthly authority, by the way it subordinated 
all classes of Society to the sovereignty of God ; at the same time, 
however, it gained unity and stability through the conception 
of law, and through the definition of its sole aim as the glory 
of God. This fact explains the passionate and often successful 
attacks made by united Calvinistic minorities upon a whole 
nation, such as those which appear again and again in French, 
Dutch, and English history . 403 

So far as the ethic of sex and of the Family is concerned, 
Calvinism has the same principles as Lutheranism. Possibly, 
however, we may say that the personality of woman is granted 
a higher degree of independence, and that the purpose of mar- 
riage is conceived in a more rational way ; the scholastic dualistic 
id^a of its relative value, and its necessity for the restraint of 
concupiscence, has given place to the rational idea that the 
Family is a means of building up Society. Here also we have 
a glimpse of the difference between Lutheran and Calvinistic 
asceticism. Under the influence of its doctrine of Original Sin 
Lutheranism abandons concupiscence entirely to sin, but permits 
the element of sinful impulse to exist within the restrictions of 
marriage, whereas Calvinism lays less emphasis on that element, 
urging rather that marriage should be strictly regulated by the 
rational view of its service to the common good, while the natural 
instincts and passions are to be controlled by objective con- 
siderations and the attempt to direct them into other channels. 
This is merely a difference of emphasis, but it is important, and 
it throws light on the inmost distinctions 404 between the two 
systems. 

408 See p. 922. 


404 See p. 922. 



656 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 


Influence of later Calvinism 
In the main, in this section we have been concerned almost 
exclusively with primitive Calvinism, and only some of the 
characteristics which have affected its modern development have 
been mentioned. This, however, does not provide an adequate 
explanation of Calvinism as it is to-day, nor of those great de- 
velopments of the seventeenth century, which produced move- 
ments which have profoundly affected the life of the present day. 
Two important phenomena, both of which were the direct pro- 
duct of Calvinism, have not yet been mentioned : the rise of the 
Free Churches, and the rise of Puritanism within the Church, or 
Pietism. 

(I) Rise of the Free Churches 
Through the development of the Free Churches, Calvinism 
forged a bond of union with democracy, which was totally 
different from the ethic of the State which has already been 
described. This earlier ethic of the State was only concerned 
with establishing a constitution or a system of control over against 
a State which was doing injury either to the glory of God or to 
the welfare of nations; otherwise its ideas were as conservative 
and legitimist as possible. The essential meaning of the Free 
Church system, on the contrary, is the destruction of the mediaeval 
and early Protestant idea of a social order welded together by 
one uniform State Church, and of one infallible authority with 
a uniform control of the whole of civilization. From the very 
\ outset, therefore, its attitude towards the fundamental social id$as 
of the previous era was revolutionary. As a system, therefore, it 
represented a subjective and relative form of religion, which 
indeed only meant the renunciation of that earthly authority 
which possesses and promotes the extension of absolute Truth; 
for this very reason, however, it felt obliged to permit the dif- 
ferent religious communions to exist alongside of one another, 
since they appear to have some right to exist until the final 
separation at the Return of Christ. This meant that the question 
of Church membership now became a matter of individual choice, 
and that, at least outwardly, the form of Church-order becomes 
that of a voluntary association, even although theologically the 
community which thus comes into being may still continue 
to be considered as an objective, ecclesiastical institution. Thus 
the conception of the Church was moving towards individualistic 
democratic ideas, and it is obvious that an ecclesiastical ideal 



PROTESTANTISM 


657 

of this kind would have a close affinity with political democracy; 
on the other hand, also, a democracy which regards the State 
as a unity of individuals can more easily co-operate with a 
Church-conception of this kind than with the idea of a State 
Church, which at bottom in some way always dominates the 
State with its absolutist ideas. In course of time, therefore, the 
Free Church system, or the separation of Church and State, 
became the religious and political principle of democracy, while, 
on the other hand, the Free Churches produced democratic 
impulses. It is clear that this represents a new development of 
Calvinism, and one which goes far beyond all its previous ex- 
perience; above all, the Free Churches approximate more and 
more to the sect-type, even when the idea of the Church is 
preserved, with all its dogmatic and ethical consequences. 

Finally, whereas the result of the development of the Free 
Churches was a somewhat formal analogy with the sect-type, 
the second development forms a very obvious analogy with the 
sect-type, both in form and content. Pietism has no direct 
concern with Church constitutions and democratic tendencies 
or results; its one desire is to create a “pure” Church. Pietism 
intensified the fundamental asceticism of Calvinism, and in so 
doing it broke with the world and with secular culture, having 
no use for anything which goes beyond all that is directly utili- 
tarian and necessary. This certainly was a reactionary tendency, 
compared with the much freer and finer attitude of Calvin him- 
self, and also the earlier Calvinistic idea of civilization, which 
was distinguished precisely by its urbane refinement and human- 
istic culture ; naturally this idea did not cease to exist, but it was 
forced into the background by the more active and more Puri- 
tanical form of Calvinism. Pietism, therefore, developed some 
affinities with the Ethos of the sect, although the very distinct 
differences between it and the genuine Baptist Ethos still remained, 
although they had been distinctly modified. 

Both these movements, however — the Free Church system and 
Pietistic Puritanism — were not by any means identical with each 
other. The Free Church movement can be understood in the 
sense of a dogmatic and ethical Calvinism of the most correct 
kind, and can, if it will, decidedly assert or increase the freer 
attitude towards the world. Pietism, on the other hand, does not 
need to urge the necessity to break up the uniformity of the State 
Church system, since it hopes, either, that it will succeed in 
bringing the whole of Society under the yoke of Church discipline 
and of the Puritan ideal, or that it will be able to form smaller 

vol. n. o 



658 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

grdups within the Church, which would virtually create a dis- 
tinction between a religious community in the wider, more 
pedagogic, and relative sense, and one which would be conceived 
in the narrower, more Perfectionist, and absolute sense. At times, 
however, both tendencies merge into one another. The motif of 
the Free Church, in addition to its emphatic rejection of com- 
pulsion in religious matters, can be also that of the “holy com- 
munity”, and the Pietist system of creating small groups within 
the Church can also lead to the development of a Free Church ; 
instances of this kind actually happened, especially in the early 
days. 

The question now arises, To what extent are both these develop- 
ments to be attributed to the logical development of Calvinism, 
and to what extent has this result been affected by external 
influences of a foreign kind? Both these changes took place pre- 
eminently in the great conflicts in England, and in the Nether- 
lands, between the State and the supremacy of the Church, 
between the ideal of holiness and that of the Renaissance and 
of national customs. Was this the logical result of Calvinism, or 
was this situation created by influences of a special character? 

First of all, we may say that both these developments, in spite 
of great changes, can still be explained in the light of the Genevan 
basis; it must be admitted, of course, that they were not the 
direct result of the Genevan situation; on the contrary, they 
arose out of a quite different setting. They took place in fact 
in conditions in which the situation was no longer controlled by 
the life of a small State, but by the problems which arise where 
masses of people are concerned, which increasingly necessitated 
strong compulsion in religious matters. Geneva was a small State, 
and this made it possible for this comparatively limited number 
of people to be permeated with the ideals of Christian holiness. 
For a long time also its civil government was weak, and therefore 
it submitted to the control of the Church. In both respects this 
situation was unique, and unattainable under other conditions. 
In other places too, however, where Calvinism was organized 
on similar lines, it was always at first the religion of an aggressive 
minority. Within a smaller setting it was possible to set up the 
ideal of the “holy community” as a national Church, and a 
Christian civilization which covered the whole of Society, while 
the opposition of this minority to the civil authority meant in 
practice that the problem of a State Church did not exist. But 
as soon as it became a question of influencing the life of actual 
sovereign States with the Calvinistic ideal of the State and of 



PROTESTANTISM 


659 

Society, or as soon as the Calvinistic churches were placed 
within a general system of secular mass civilization, the problem 
then arose : How was the civil authority to adjust itself to the 
predominating ecclesiastical and theological interests? This led 
to the further question: How could a “holy community” com- 
posed of sterling Christians, whose faith was a matter of profound 
personal conviction, and whose lives were controlled by an 
exalted and austere ideal, be at the same time a Church which 
would provide a spiritual home for the masses of the population? 
The pressure exercised by Calvinism provoked the resistance of 
the political authority which demanded “Erastianism”, i.e. the 
control of the Church by the State, and the resistance of the 
civil authorities which had no desire to adapt themselves to 
the hard and one-sided rigorism which Calvinism required from 
its adherents. 

The fact of this resistance, however, produced a great change 
in Calvinism itself, by forcing it into a new position. Calvinism 
had to face this question: Is this ideal of a “holy community”, 
and of making God’s glory dominant in the whole life of the 
world, actually practicable? Long before, the Anabaptists had 
denied this possibility, but Calvin had asserted that it was pos- 
sible (in resolute confidence that the non-elect were in the 
minority, and that, at least outwardly, they could and must be 
made to submit to the Christian Church). And now the question 
had reappeared. And with this, too, it became quite evident that 
the Calvinist ideal possessed a certain affinity with the Baptist 
ideal, although at first no one had been aware of the fact. Like 
th^ Baptists the Calvinists now began to question the validity 
of the whole State Church system, and to replace it by a voluntary 
Church which the State cannot touch. like the Baptists the 
Calvinists undertook to separate themselves from the world by 
a Puritanical strictness of life. It was only an approximation to 
the Baptist ideal, however ; there was no real unity between the 
two. Even as a Free Church Calvinism still remained as far as 
possible a national Church, nor, in practice, has Puritanism ever 
disputed on principle the existence of secular offices, power, war, 
law, and the oath. There is, however, a certain resemblance 
between the Calvinistic Free Church and the Baptist ideal, and 
it is clear how deeply this is due to the problem raised by Cal- 
vinism in general of the really active “holy community” which 
represents the sovereignty of God . 406 

Further, it is clear that, in any case, Puritanism and Pietism 
408 See p. 922, 



660 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

were able to proceed more directly out of the fundamental ideas 
of the Calvinistic Church than the Free Church movement, 
although the latter is the more enduring and important principle 
in world-history. The Free Church movement has been described 
as a “subsidiary ecclesiastical ideal” of Calvinism, produced 
when the “primary” ideal proves insufficient or unsuccessful. On 
the other hand, however, some thinkers look upon it as an aspect 
of the Calvinistic idea of the Church connected with Natural 
Law, which only thus finds its logical expression. Modern Cal- 
vinists like Kuyper do not hesitate to ascribe the existence of 
the Free Churches directly to the influence of Calvin’s most 
essential ideas ; his idea of a State Church, with its compulsory 
Christian civilization, they regard as a mediaeval idea, involving 
mediaeval limitations, which it is easy to discard. Others trace 
its origin to influences derived from the Baptist idea of the Church, 
in which, indeed, adult Baptism is only a symptom, but not the 
heart of the matter. The question of the origin of this development 
is thus a very real problem . 406 

When we remember that in primitive Calvinism there was not 
the slightest tendency towards the formation of these “Free 
Church” ideals, but that, on the contrary, it considered it the 
greatest crime to tolerate the existence of several churches along- 
side of each other, and a withdrawal of the State from the sphere 
of its Christian duty; when too we realize that primitive Cal- 
vinism believed that the absolute and unbroken nature of the 
idea of truth requires both the unity of civilization and the sole 
dominion of the Truth, coupled with intolerance towards un- 
truth; when, further, we consider that the Calvinistic idea of 
the Church from the very outset was certainly not democratic, 
but that it carefully avoided the logical consequence of demo- 
cratic ideas, and that, although the doctrine of Predestination 
did permit an immense individualism of personality, it permitted 
no “enthusiastic” emphasis on “direct” religious experience, with 
very great variety of expression, but, rather, that by connecting 
it with the means of grace in the Church, the Word, and the 
Sacrament it extended its solemn sense of awe to all these means 
of grace : we then feel that it is impossible to come to such con- 
clusions. 

To that we must add these further considerations : whenever, 
in any particular instance, Calvinism was forced to take its place 
alongside of other denominations, it always regarded this situation 
as something which was only compulsory and temporary, and 

404 See p. 924. 



PROTESTANTISM 661 

that where, in the beginning, it was forced into the position of 
a Free Church, or a secret society, it regarded this explicitly 
as a serious lack, that in England and North America, under 
Presbyterian influence, as soon as it had the power to choose, 
it gave up its principles of toleration and returned to the prin- 
ciple of Theocracy ; that at the Synod of Charenton it directly 
and solemnly condemned Independency and Congregationalism 
in the French Church. The early Puritan communities in Eng- 
land also, which at first had been Separatist, under more favour- 
able circumstances became the great Presbyterian party, which 
desired to replace the Anglican State Church by a Presbyterian 
State Church. Even the communities on the Lower Rhine re- 
garded their Free Church form of existence as merely provisional, 
and aspired to become a State Church, after the pattern of that 
which the Calvinists had attained in Holland. Even the idea of 
a Church covenant is not Calvinistic in origin, for the Scottish 
Covenants were not Church institutions but associations for the 
protection of the Church . 407 

The Brownists 

In reality, the historical starting-point of the Free Churches, 
as a normal principle, does not lie in those Free Churches which 
were the fruit of necessity, but in Congregationalism. The origin 
of Congregationalism was similar to that of Puritanism, but it 
was not identical with it. Robert Browne, the Father of Con- 
gregationalism, was at first a member of the strict Puritan body; 
then, however, he developed Separatist principles which were 
expressed in the idea of complete separation between Church 
and State, in basing the life of the Church solely upon the 
inward power of the Spirit, in a Scriptural austerity of worship, 
in the demand for “converted” preachers, in the ideal of the 
purity of the body of communicants, in the principle of self- 
government in individual churches, and finally in the idea of a 
covenant and the voluntary character of the Church. 

In this ideal the only Puritan and Calvinist feature is the 
emphasis upon the holy community. All the other characteristics 
are Baptist, and in part akin to those of the spiritual reformers ; 
the idea of the Church Covenant especially is decidedly Baptist. 
It does not affect the argument that Browne himself, his spirit 
broken by suffering, made his peace with the Established Church, 
with mental reservations; further, his mental reservations were 
of a “spiritual’ * nature, for Browne believed that the spirit was 

407 See p. 924. 



tt» THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

all that mattered, and that externals were insignificant. The 
retention of Infant Baptism also, and the recognition of the 
validity of Anglican Baptism, certainly shows that these “Holi- 
ness” groups were not concerned with the question of Adult 
Baptism at all. They were based upon a covenant with God and 
with each other, and their constitution was simply that of purer 
and more closely knit groups within the universal Church; they 
did not intend to be new forms of Church organization. This 
comes out clearly in the controversy with the General Baptists, 
who, in common with Robinson’s Leyden Church, had arisen out 
of a Brownist community at Gainsborough, but who, under the 
influence of the Dutch Mennonites, had adopted the principle 
of Adult Baptism. In doctrine, too, the Brownists remained com- 
pletely orthodox in a Calvinistic sense . 408 

The Barrowists 

Henry Barrowe, the second “Father” of Congregationalism, 
held opinions which were very similar to those of Robert Browne. 
Barrowe was a gentleman and a layman who had been converted 
to Puritanism; in his opinion a Separatist position was the only 
logical inference to be drawn from Puritanism and the ideal of 
a holy community. For this reason he opposed the Puritans of 
the Cartwright school (whom he stigmatized as “illogical”) just 
as bitterly as the High Church Party, which on its side thought 
it was entitled to reproach Puritanism with the very existence 
of the Brownists and the Barrowists, which, it was careful to point 
out, had really been caused by the behaviour of the Puritans. 
Along with many of his followers Barrowe died the death oi; a 
martyr, a sacrifice to the cruel spirit of Elizabethan conformity, 
which saw in these Separatist movements the principles of anarchy 
at work, threatening the very existence of Church and State, and 
of Society as a whole. 

Barrowe evolved his ideal from the Bible and the Calvinistic 
idea of holiness ; to some extent also he was indirectly influenced 
by Brownism, and actually to a far greater extent by the Baptist 
movement, though this he himself would not admit. Also, just 
as in the case of Browne, he had been deeply influenced by books 
dealing with interior religion, although he did not go so far as 
to set the Inner Word above the Bible, as it was alleged was done 
by some of those who laid most emphasis upon the “religion of 
the Spirit”. His recognition of the function of lay preachers and 
of spiritual gifts, which may have been deduced directly from 

408 See p. 925. 



PROTESTANTISM 


663 

the Bible, points in the same direction. His ideal of the Church 
may be summarized thus : it is a “pure” Church, separate from 
the State; each congregation is completely independent, con- 
stituted upon the basis of a Church covenant; the sacraments 
are merely the sign and seal of this covenant ; its officials— pastors, 
elders, deacons — are called independently, in a purely democratic 
way, yet without equality; it exercises Church discipline and 
excommunication independently, supports itself and its officials 
by the voluntary gifts of the faithful, and in all particulars it 
upholds the ideal of early Christian love and holiness among all 
its members. Synods of the whole Church will only act in an 
advisory capacity; the individual congregation is to be entirely 
independent; the Holy Spirit will preserve the spirit of unity. 
In doctrine his point of view is strictly Calvinistic and Predcs- 
tinarian. The only ecclesiastical function left to the State is the 
expulsion of those who profess false doctrines; the building up 
of the Church is to be left to its own efforts and to the Spirit, 
in harmony with the principles of Scriptural Church-order. 
Marriages and funerals are civil functions. The authority of the 
State is to be treated with conservative respect, yet at the same 
time excommunication can be exercised even against princes 
without injury to their high civil position. Infant Baptism is 
retained, and the baptism of false churches is also recognized, 
since election and the influence of the Word are not bound by 
the limits of the purely visible Church. 

In spite of certain resemblances with the Baptist ideal of the 
Church as a voluntary association and with the Baptist ideal of 
holiness, there is in this last point a relic of the Calvinistic national 
diurch ideal, in the light of which these “purely independent 
communities ’ 5 appear merely as particular Perfectionist groups. 
Thus in spite of much controversy the thread which con- 
nects this movement with Puritanism has not been entirely 
severed . 409 

At this point two lines of possible development lay before 
Congregationalism: on the one hand, a merely subjective de- 
velopment in the direction of freedom of conscience, and the 
formation of more spiritual exclusive groups, without any definite 
ecclesiastical constitutional ideals, or, on the other, the organiza- 
tion of independent individual congregations into a Church, based 
on a covenant, in which each congregation is based upon the 
voluntary principle. The English Independency of Cromwell’s 
Army developed in the first direction. The Congregationalism 

40t See p. 926. 



664 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

which has maintained its existence down to the present day 
followed the second line of development. But, whichever line it 
took, Congregationalism stood midway between the Calvinistic 
church-type and the sect-type ; to some extent this was involved 
in the fact that Calvinism itself had many affinities with the sect- 
type; in reality, however, Congregationalism only arose under 
Anabaptist influence; above all, as we shall see later, it was 
influenced by a type of spirituality which differed greatly from 
Anabaptist ideals. The close connection between this movement 
and the sect-type appears not only in the fact that the General 
Baptists went over to the Anabaptists, but also in the fact of the 
development of the Particular Baptists, which followed an entirely 
independent course. These Particular Baptists likewise had split 
off from originally Independent communities, and adopted Adult 
Baptism as a result of the Free Church principle; otherwise, 
however, they remained strict Calvinists, and had no further 
connection with the Baptists. Frequently bodies of Congrega- 
tionalists went over to the Baptists en bloc ; indeed, there were 
some congregations which were composed of both elements. There 
were also Baptist congregations which organized themselves on 
the basis of a Church covenant, an explicit agreement of the 
Church members with each other and with God, which each 
member had to sign and solemnly swear to observe. That is an 
entirely Baptist idea. On the other hand, however, Congrega- 
tionalism was closely akin to the Calvinistic church-type. It is 
shown in the different ways in which this fundamental Church 
covenant is expressed; sometimes it is only implicit, and some- 
times it is explicit. When it is only implicit it is supposed to be 
contained in the covenant of Infant Baptism and in the existence 
of the Calvinistic national Church ; it then only means the idea 
of a Church which is under strict obligations to be a “holy 
community”, and leaves to it its significance as a method of 
popular education. When it is explicit it means the constitution 
of a separate body upon a basis of voluntary membership and 
strict consistency, which does away with the idea of a national 
Church. Thus we can understand why it was that many people 
went over from Congregationalism to Pietism and Presbyterian- 
ism and vice versa, while others found it possible to hold these 
views and yet to remain in the Established Church. 

In all this, however, the fundamental element is still non- 
ecclesiastical and akin to the sect-type; only it has not severed 
its connection with Calvinist theology, and it does not, therefore, 
need to be constituted by a baptismal rite of its own. This explains, 



PROTESTANTISM 665 

above all, the inconsistencies in the Congregationalist Church- 
life of New England . 410 

“Pilgrim” Communities 

Let us now follow first of all the line of development which 
led to the so-called Congregationalist Church principle. To it 
belonged the Refugee or “Pilgrim” communities, which arose 
out of the early beginnings (which have just been described), and 
which emigrated first to Holland, and then to New England, in 
order to preserve their nationality, and in the interest of their 
mission to found a “purely democratic church”. 

The English Government modified their persecuting laws to 
this extent that they allowed the Separatists to emigrate — with 
this proviso, however, that if they returned they would forfeit 
all their property and be executed. While Browne had founded 
a congregation in Middelburg, which soon went to pieces, 
Barrowe’s followers then formed a similar Church in Amsterdam. 
Under these circumstances the social position of this Church was 
a difficult one. Farmers and scholars alike had to become manual 
labourers, or to go into business. Meanwhile the anarchy pro- 
phesied by Whitgift soon began to rear its head in the congre- 
gation. The main democratic element, the majority principle, 
lay-preaching or “prophesying”, brought all kinds of strife, hair- 
splitting arguments, and rivalries in its train. There was a great 
deal of argument about the constitution : should it be aristocratic 
and Presbyterian, or ought it to be more democratic? The state- 
ment that the Church is governed not by man but by the Spirit 
of Christ is only another illustration of the influence of a pre- 
eminently “spiritual” type of thought upon the whole ; in practice, 
however, this idea had no influence at all. Robinson led a section 
of the congregation away from all this confusion to Leyden ; he 
solved the problem by making a distinction between the Church 
government exercised by the elders, and the authority of the 
Church exercised by the congregation, which really amounted 
to this: that less important matters were settled by the elders, 
and important questions by the majority of the Church members. 
At the same time Robinson approved of the idea of a “Church 
fellowship”, an advisory council representing the congregations 
which in themselves were independent. 

Pilgrim Fathers 

The Pilgrim Fathers then carried these principles with them 
to New England. There they succeeded in infusing their spirit 

410 See p. 927. 



666 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

into the numerous groups of Presbyterian settlers which arrived 
later on. Not yet did that mean, however, freedom to organize 
churches of all kinds. In New England, Calvinistic Congrega- 
tionalists alone were recognized, and even the most important 
political rights were bound up with Church membership. The 
actual communicant body consisted only of those who were 
considered “genuinely converted”, and who had signed the 
Church Covenant. The children, however, were all baptized, 
and were regarded as an outer circle within the Church, which, 
without belonging to the central group of communicants, was 
still regarded as Christian; these “adherents” also had to pay 
Church taxes. They were only required to sign what their enemies 
called a “half-way covenant”, however, which laid on them 
merely the obligation to act in a generally Christian way. Thus, 
in the colonies of New England, Congregationalism became the 
State religion, and the local churches were brought into closer 
relation with each other. This formed the starting-point of 
American Congregationalism, which under the influence of the 
Methodist Revival lost one section of its members to the Pres- 
byterians and another section to the Unitarians, but which still 
forms a large and influential community, whose constitutional 
principles have come to be shared by a whole series of other 
denominations, like the Baptists, the Seventh Day Adventists, 
and the Unitarians . 411 

Independency 

The other process of development which has already been 
mentioned, the Independency of the Cromwellian period, is an 
entirely different phenomenon. It did not unite with the English 
Congregationalists, who likewise had their origin in Leyden, and 
who started with the Church of Jacobs, composed of Congrega- 
tionalists who had returned to London, who later on, together 
with the Presbyterians and the Baptists, combined to form English 
Dissent. 

In Parliament, in the Westminster Assembly, and among the 
clergy, this form of English Congregationalism was only repre- 
sented by a very small minority, and it was here prepared to 
allow the continuance of the Established Church, merely stipu- 
lating that the individual congregation should be independent, 
have the right to excommunicate when required, and to elect 
its own officers; it was prepared to admit a certain amount of 
State control. The real support of the movement, however, came, 

411 See p. 927. 



PROTESTANTISM 667 

not from these “Dissenting Brethren”, but from Cromwell’s Army. 
It is, however, quite evident that this movement was neither 
Brownism nor Barrowism, and that, owing to the course of 
political history, it was also a good deal influenced from abroad. 
Rather, in relation to the Established Church, it was a confused 
and theoretical impulse towards inward illumination and ex- 
perience, coupled with the demand for the right of lay-preaching, 
which was exercised both by officers and by soldiers, a demand 
for converted pastors, and for freedom to constitute churches 
around a preacher who has been freely called by the Church. 
It was a much more idealistic “spiritual” movement than either 
Brownism or Barrowism; in many ways it resembled Luther’s 
earlier teaching, and also Schwenckfeld’s smaller groups, which 
were formed on the model of the Early Church. 

These Independents claimed toleration towards themselves, 
out of respect for tender consciences and for the witness of the 
Spirit within individual souls, but they were then obliged to 
grant it also to the “other sects”, on account of which the In- 
dependents seemed to the Presbyterians like “Anabaptists and 
Antinomians” ; they soon found, however, that unlimited tolera- 
tion itself produced difficulties. The Independents even accepted 
pastors appointed by the Parliamentary Commission, provided 
that they were “genuinely converted”. On the question of lay- 
preaching they went farther than Browne, claiming it as a right, 
and in this they verged on fanaticism. At the same time the 
whole ecclesiastical situation and the theory of the Church were 
still most obscure. 

In so far as Cromwell allowed himself to be influenced by 
Harrison, the real patron of the sects in the Army and later of 
the Fifth Monarchy Men, it is possible that he was actually 
influenced by Baptist ideas. He always adhered, however, to the 
idea of a union of toleration for all Protestants, and of Christian 
unity and government of the nation without discarding the 
technical organization of the Established Church. It was only 
when the majority in the Barebones Parliament abolished the 
system of tithes, which would have meant that parishes and 
universities would have lost their means of support, and would 
have been obliged to resort to the voluntary principle, that an 
attempt was made to reorganize on a new basis. This attempt it 
was, however, which caused Cromwell to dissolve this Assembly, 
which was a convention of notables rather than a Parliament. 
His own Church policy then took the line of appointing a Par- 
liamentary Commission of Inquiry, composed as far as possible 



668 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

of excellent people of different groups and tendencies, including 
Presbyterians and Anglicans ; these men were called the “Tryers”. 
Catholics alone were excluded on political grounds, and later, 
after an attempt at rebellion, the Anglicans were also excluded. 
Alongside of them, of course, the Separatist groups of the Baptists, 
Congregationalists, and the Quakers were tolerated. Thus in 
reality Independency was the religion of the State, since nearly 
all the official positions were occupied by its followers, for the 
most part earnest men of a Pietistic kind. The desire and choice 
of individual congregations could thus be taken into consideration. 
The whole procedure, and the toleration which was combined 
with it, was characterized by a strong emphasis upon “spiritual 
religion”; as we shall see later on, Cromwell’s chaplains were 
enlightened men of this type. Nevertheless, Cromwell’s leading 
ideas were Calvinistic. He also desired to see a Christian 
State. He only extended the borders of Christian experience: 
the conviction of sin, assurance, and a theology of grace ; these 
are the marks of Christian experience. He also exercised moral 
supervision over the people; only this was done not through 
ecclesiastical courts of discipline, but through the State General 
Majors. 

Cromwell 

Cromwell was also a firm believer in a theocracy. He classed 
his own proceedings, and those of the Army, with the measures 
taken by the magistrate injirieurs when the legitimate government 
had failed. He regarded his own position as sanctified by Provi- 
dence and the course of history, and therefore as his by Divine 
Right. His religious convictions remain Calvinistic and Pre- 
destinarian. Thus in principle both Cromwell and the Indepen- 
dency of his Army were quite different from the Baptist movement, 
in spite of various resemblances between the two. 

His teaching about the Salus publica and the sovereignty of the 
people is the Calvinistic doctrine of the duty of the nation to 
establish a government according to the Will of God, and he 
discerns the Will of God in the course of events. In questions 
concerning property, law, and government he is therefore con- 
servative in principle; more and more clearly his own position 
is differentiated from that of the democratic, communistic, and 
Chiliast radicals. From the very outset his Independency had 
differed from theirs ; it had far less affinity with the Baptist move- 
ment than had Brownism, but, unlike the latter, it had a greater 
tendency towards “inwardness”; the latter tendency, however, 



PROTESTANTISM 669 

was modified by the Calvinistic idea of the State as an institution 
which exists to serve and glorify God. 

From this standpoint, as Lord Protector, Cromwell also ac- 
cepted the universal Calvinistic policy of the union and protection 
of Protestants. This was a Protestant international policy, the 
last great expression of a denominational Protestant world policy, 
after the manner of Bucer, Zwingli, Calvin, and the Landgrave 
of Hesse. All the same, the Independency of Cromwell was only 
an interim phase. The final revolution of 1688 fell back upon 
ideas which were vital before Cromwell, and Independency 
dispersed its remaining faithful adherents among the various Dis- 
senting bodies : the Quakers, the Baptists, the Congregationalists, 
and the Presbyterians. 412 

At first Congregationalism and Independency were phenomena 
whose range was limited, and moreover Independency was not 
permanent. But the influence of both was great. The first result, 
which was of universal importance in world history, was the 
transition from the independent theory to the Locke doctrine of 
the State, which developed into a theory which favoured free- 
dom to form churches, and to the separation between Church 
and State which was closely connected with political Liberalism. 
We have already had a hint of this in the preceding pages, and 
it now becomes plain in its historical setting. From the time of 
Locke onwards this theory has been extended and developed as 
a philosophy of the State right down to the present day. It has 
become the ecclesiastical policy of Liberalism and of democracy. 

The second still more important result is this : that in the con- 
stitution of the United States of North America, and in the 
constitutions of the North American individual States, the order- 
ing of the ecclesiastical situation was practically shaped along 
these lines, partly as a result of the actual existence of several 
churches alongside of each other in the various States, partly, 
however, also as the expression of the Congregationalist Calvinist 
idea of the majesty of the Church, and of a freedom of conscience 
which cannot be touched by the State. Although, in a general 
way, it was held that the State was Christian in character, yet 
so far as the churches were concerned it ought to have no 
authority over them, nor be under any obligations towards them, 
but it ought to leave the religious conscience alone; this is in 
sharp contrast with the attempted separation between Church 
and the State which has been taking place in Latin lands since 
the French Revolution ; in reality this movement is the struggle 

411 See p. 928. 



670 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

of a free-thinking society against the power of the churches, and, 
above all, against the Roman Catholic Church. The ecclesiastical 
policy of the present day is being determined more and more 
by those theories, and by this example of America . 413 

Calvinism and the Free Church Principle 

After this detailed examination into the question, it is impos- 
sible to attribute these results directly to Calvinism itself; they 
may rather be described as due to the influence of a modified 
Calvinism affected by Baptist and “spiritual” influences. It is, 
however, always a fact that even the genuinely Calvinistic 
Churches, in face of the mingling of peoples and religions, and 
of the increasing tendency to secularize the State, have followed 
this example . 414 This fact is, however, of decisive importance for 
the modern forms of Calvinism. Nearly everywhere Calvinistic 
Free Churches have grown up alongside of National Churches. 
In Geneva itself separation prevails to-day. The manifesto of 
Kuyper, often mentioned, which the University of Princeton has 
almost made official, teaches the Free Church system directly as 
a fundamental Calvinistic theory. Everywhere then, connected 
with that is the tendency towards the liberal or democratic con- 
stitutions which make possible to every ecclesiastical party, and 
to every church, freedom of movement, and an honourable place 
in public opinion. 

In its passage through the Free Church phase the main block 
of Calvinism became Liberal in politics, and it participates so 
closely in the tendency of the sects towards an individualistic 
and purely utilitarian conception of the State that to-day, in tjiis 
respect, there is scarcely any difference between it and them. 
Above, in another connection, the tendency of Calvinism to form 
constitutional theories of the State has already been pointed out. 
Free Church Calvinism, however, went farther than that, and 
became receptive towards the idea of democracy itself. It was 
only in this amalgamation of the Free Church system with 
democracy that it received its present-day relation to political 
individualism. Thus at the present day Calvinism (including the 
sect-movement) is diametrically opposed to the Lutheran State 
Church system, and it proudly claims to be the only form of 
Christianity which appeals to the modern mind. It has not, of 
course, produced democracy, but in its Free Church form it has 
encouraged it. Wherever natural conditions favoured democracy — 
as, for instance, in the colonies of New England — Calvinism gave 
414 See p» 930. 414 See p. 93 1 . 



PROTESTANTISM 671 

it a decided impetus, adjusted its life in accordance with demo- 
cratic principles, and inspired it with its own spirit of the in- 
dependence of the individual of all earthly authority. 414 * 

Free Church Principle 
and Religious Toleration 

Religious toleration was one logical result of the rise of Con- 
gregationalism and of the Free Church movement. Some time 
elapsed, however, before this principle was fully accepted. The 
main obstacles to be overcome were (1) the Calvinistic idea that 
each religious body was the sole possessor of the Truth, and 
(2) the theory of the Christian nature of the State. Final accep- 
tance of the principle was also delayed until pure Calvinism had 
adopted the principle of toleration. 

The ideal of the early Congregationalists was expressed in the 
following terms: freedom to form independent churches; the 
abolition of State compulsion in religious matters ; and the ex- 
clusion of all heretical forms of religion from the State. The 
Congregationalist Puritans of New England perpetuated these 
principles ; they compelled no one to join the Church ; but they 
declined to tolerate the existence of any other church, and they 
gave important civic rights to the members of the Church. Here, 
then, we see the purely negative theory at work, which forbids 
compulsion in religious matters, while at the same time no room 
is left at all for the positive existence of different religious com- 
munions alongside of one another. It was not until the eighteenth 
century that positive toleration was introduced, and then that 
was mainly due to a slackening of religious interest and to the 
growth of various secular trade interests. In England the Long 
Parliament only granted toleration to the various groups within 
Calvinistic Protestantism ; in order to secure the Christian nature 
of the State it maintained the Elizabethan legislation which made 
attendance at public worship compulsory ; the only difference was 
that individuals were now at liberty to choose the religious group 
with which they desired to worship. As occasion offered, Brownists 
and Independents then claimed that religious freedom should be 
granted also to Baptists, Socinians, Arminians, and even to Jews 
and Muhammadans. They based this demand on “spiritual” 
grounds, urging that the external form of worship was a matter 
of comparative indifference compared with the importance of 
the inward revelation. Milton was the most “advanced” repre- 
sentative of this group; he, however, modified his Puritan and 

4U * See p. 931. 



672 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

“spiritual” ideas with a strong dash of the intellectual spirit of 
the Renaissance. Cromwell declared that freedom of conscience 
was a natural right of humanity ; finally, however, on political 
grounds he was obliged to deny this right to Catholics, Anglicans, 
and radical Baptists; he had a firm belief also in the Christian 
nature of the State, and in a State Church system of at least a 
formal and administrative kind. It was only the Baptists, the 
Quakers, and Roger Williams, who maintained that from the 
spiritual point of view all religious denominations ought to 
receive equal recognition, and that the State, which is based upon 
the Law of Nature, and only administers the Second Table of 
the Decalogue, ought to be neutral towards the religious aims 
of Society; in the same way the State is here conceived in a 
purely utilitarian sense. Williams threw in his lot with the 
Baptists, but they very soon turned him out, and he then gave 
himself up to an undenominational kind of “spiritual religion”. 
As the founder of Rhode Island he persuaded the new colony 
to found its constitution upon the basis of complete religious 
toleration; Williams also held the view that the nature of the 
State was Christian. 

As an actual principle religious toleration was not accepted 
until Locke had formulated his theory of Church and State. In 
the constitution of the American States it then became a matter 
of practical politics, in which, out of respect for the majesty of 
conscience, the human rights of liberty of worship, and of the 
freedom of the individual conscience, were made the constitutional 
basis of the individual States; otherwise, however, in America 
the general Christian character of the State has been preseryed 
quite naturally in various institutions, and above all in the national 
spirit, down to the present day. 

Jellinek has shown us that this formulation of the right to 
worship according to one’s conscience, as a human right which 
ought to be guaranteed constitutionally, forced its way into juridi- 
cal formulation, together with the “rights of humanity” already 
proclaimed by the Natural Law of the Enlightenment, and that 
this formulation was then carried over into the constitutions of 
Europe. The idea of the “calling” is another illustration of the 
same process — which shows plainly that many an independent 
idea which to-day has no religious basis at all grew originally 
out of the soil of religion. This fact, and above all the proclama- 
tion of liberty of worship as an inalienable human right, can 
only be attributed to Puritanism in so far as this term includes 
Quakers and Baptists, above all as we take into account the 



PROTESTANTISM 673 

softening influence of “inward religion” with its tendency to 
assign a very relative importance to external dogmatic forms. 
The only real source of toleration is that individualistic form of 
spirituality which considers that all external religious forms are 
merely relative; the only Calvinistic element in this point of 
view is the feeling that the State has no right to interfere with 
religion. 

Further, we ought not to forget that in addition to these 
religious forces there were many other external reasons, especially 
“enlightened” rationalistic ideas, which helped to shape these 
constitutional principles. The principle of religious toleration 
only penetrated into actual Calvinism with the growth of the 
Pietistic Separatist churches, coupled with the growth of many 
forms of religious belief and worship within one nation. At the 
present time it interprets the early Calvinistic idea of the sove- 
reignty of religion and of the Church in the sense of freedom 
from the State, and therefore as the principle of liberty of worship. 
At the same time its main trend is evangelical and orthodox. 

So far as genuine Calvinism is concerned toleration is still a 
purely political question, which aims at making the Church 
independent of the State ; it does not deal with questions within 
the Church itself. Genuine Calvinism regards the existence of 
several churches alongside of one another as a provisional arrange- 
ment which constitutes a problem incapable of being solved by 
human minds. Only at the Last Day will this problem be solved 
in the interest of the pure Truth. The process of sifting truth 
from error will be carried out by the Judgment of God, not by 
the effort of man, nor by the decision of the State. These argu- 
mdhts are still based upon the assumption that the State, and 
Society in general — with their moral foundation of Natural Law 
and the conscience of rulers — are Christian in character. In this 
respect as well, however, Neo-Calvinism considers that it is the 
supporter of modern progress ; above all, it differs from primitive 
Calvinism in the development of the Free Church system and 
in religious toleration . 416 

Neo-Calvinism 

In so doing, however, Neo-Calvinism has adjusted the relative 
Natural Law of the fallen State, which, originally, was strongly 
conservative, even though in comparison with Lutheranism it 
was far more rationalistic, to the modern classical rationalistic 
Natural Law of Liberalism. This latter conception is, of course, 

415 See p. 933. 

p 


vol. n. 



674 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

not a product of Calvinism. On its theoretical side it was created 
by Humanistically inclined jurists, who drew their inspiration 
from a Stoicism which was freed from Christian influences, and 
from the Roman Law, and also by modern psychological philoso- 
phers, with their habit of deducing everything from experience . 416 
Since, however, this conception has also been strongly influenced 
by the Calvinistic and Scholastic conception of the Christian Law 
of Nature, which some of it has actually assimilated, it is not 
difficult to understand how it was that Calvinism of the Free 
Church type, which was democratic and Liberal in its practical 
political experience, adopted these ideas. The union of Church 
and State in primitive Calvinism was based upon the duty of 
the Christian government towards God, and also upon the con- 
viction that the institutions of relative Natural Law are entirely 
unable to satisfy the needs of human society without the help 
of the Church as the organ of the Grace of God. When, however, 
Church and State were separated and the secular institutions 
were set upon their own feet, i.e. upon the basis of Natural Law 
alone, it was then inevitable that this basis of Natural Law should 
throw off the shackles of the ancient, merely relative, Christian 
Natural Law, and with that the need of being completed by the 
Church. More and more the idea gained ground of an auto- 
nomous rational Natural Law, which conceived and taught men 
to realize the purely utilitarian ends of the secular institutions 
by the light of pure reason alone, without the co-operation of 
the authority of revelation. Or, to express the same thing in 
theological terms : the Law of Nature expressed in the Second 
Table of the Decalogue can be realized without also realizing the 
First Table, which, in the fallen State, no longer belongs to Wie 
Law of Nature. This was the kind of argument which had already 
been employed by Milton, Roger Williams, and Bayle. Thus men 
felt they could quietly accept the modern secular Natural Law, 
and indeed all the more, since increasingly, in true English style, 
it was constructed on essentially empirical and utilitarian lines. 
But, as in the case of the Calvinists of New England in the 
eighteenth century, men also found it possible to adapt them- 
selves to the French conception of Natural Law, with its rationa- 
listic and idealistic temper, which was based on the theory of 
the autonomy and equality of the individual reason. Thus we 
can understand how it is that Neo-Calvinism has been profoundly 
influenced by the conception of the Law of Nature, whilst histori- 
cally and theologically it justified this point of view by stressing 

416 See p. 936. 



PROTESTANTISM 675 

Calvin’s tendencies in the direction of a rationalistic Natural Law, 
which have already been described in the foregoing pages. The 
theocratic spirit has entirely disappeared. 416a 

Neo-Calvinism extends the principle of the formation of all 
fellowship by means of association to every relationship in life, 
and everywhere it manifests a tendency to form societies for 
ecclesiastical and religious ends, as well as for civic and cultural 
purposes. Instead of the endowments, institutions, and corpora- 
tions of hereditary entailed property belonging to class and guild 
associations, there arises the principle of the free formation of 
“societies”, since, indeed, at bottom both the Church and the 
State are themselves “societies”. Upon the basis of the uniformity 
between the laws of Scripture and of Nature, Neo-Calvinism lays 
stress upon the co-operation of Christianity and Humanity in a 
sense quite foreign to the older Calvinism. From that standpoint 
it then proceeds to develop a pacifist international spirit and 
pacifist propaganda, champions the rights of humanity, en- 
courages the anti-slavery movement, and allies itself with philan- 
thropic and humanitarian movements. The Feminist movement 
also found some support here, long before other denominations 
dared to broach the subject. The earnest Christian sections of 
American and English Protestantism — which, in England, under 
the influence of the Evangelicals, includes also a large part of 
the State Church — represent the humane, freedom-loving, and 
cosmopolitan ethic of Liberalism . 417 

Thus even Cromwell believed that it was possible to combine 
the salus publica of the Natural Law with the Christian idea of 
salvation, and with this idea of the Christian State he combined 
a relatively modern and liberal and utilitarian system of politics. 
In this respect, however, the most interesting example is that of 
Gladstone, the great modern representative of Christian politics. 
He was an Anglican, it is true, but he inclined more and more 
^towards Nonconformity. Politically and ethically, his ideals were 
those of the Nonconformists. Thus for ethical reasons he supported 
Liberalism, extended the franchise, and declared his conviction 
that in the settlement of problems of foreign policy the method 
of arbitration was both possible and desirable. His policy was 
decidedly Christian, and in the secular sphere he was just as 
decided that the basis was that of Natural Law. If we compare 
with that the idea of a Christian State represented by Julius Stahl 
and Bismarck, the great difference between the continental 
Lutheran and the Anglo-Saxon world of thought, determined 
tt6a Sec p. 937. " 7 See p. 937. 



676 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

or influenced by Calvinism, stands out in clear relief. That, 
however, these differences are not due to the Anglo-Saxon tem- 
perament is shown by the fact that the Dutch ex-Minister Kuyper 
represents a similar Liberal-Natural-Law conception of secular 
affairs. In all these questions Neo-Calvinism has drifted far away 
from Calvin — a fact which Kuyper tried in vain to conceal. In 
the handling of secular questions it has formally come very close 
to modern Liberalism and Utilitarianism, and the latter finds 
in it (in Neo-Calvinism) one of the great moral forces which 
it lacks upon the Continent. At the same time it still keeps a 
sufficiently clear distinction, which is usually quite explicit, 
between itself and the abstract French doctrine of democracy 
and of equalitarian Natural Law . 418 

In surveying this development as a whole it becomes evident 
that, in the development of Calvinism as a Free Church system, 
an element was released which, from the very beginning, had 
been implicit in the idea of the “holy community”, which, how- 
ever, was there combined with the idea of the unity of Christian 
Society, and with the principle of its sole guarantee in a com- 
pulsory religious unity. The separation between these two ideas 
only took place under the pressure of the English Revolution, 
and with the help of “spiritual” and Baptist influences. The 
result was that that social ideal of absolute conformity was set 
aside, and the secular social doctrines were committed to a con- 
ception of Natural Law which was entirely utilitarian, while the 
Christian standards were maintained, directly, solely in the 
churches, and only because these ideals were realized, to some 
extent, within the churches did they spread farther, and pene- 
trate Society as a spiritual and social force. To-day faith believes 
that finally these two currents will coalesce, since the God who 
is the source of the Natural Law, is the Same who creates the 
Church. Thus these nations which have been deeply influenced 
by Calvinism, in spite of the loss of outer conformity, do believe 
in an inner permanent conformity. Everything depends on how 
long both these spheres of life will be immune from the specifically 
modern type of criticism, and how long they can still consider 
that the practical demands of life are easily met by “common 
sense”. At present these nations only know the modern world 
essentially as a political, social-economic, and technical develop- 
ment, and they have been enabled to adjust their religion to this 
way of life . 419 In this respect, however, great changes have taken 
place since Darwin, Herbert Spencer, Bentham, John Stuart 
418 See p. 938. 419 See p. 940. 



PROTESTANTISM 677 

Mill, and Ruskin, and increasingly such changes will continue 
to take place. 

Influence of Later Calvinism: 

(II) Puritanism and Pietism 

This integral element of Calvinism, however, which centres 
round the idea of the holy community, found other avenues of 
expression than those of Congregationalism and the Free 
Churches, which were soon drawn into close connection with 
Unitarianism, the Enlightenment, and with intellectual develop- 
ment in general; modern Congregationalism in particular likes 
to emphasize the connection between its belief in liberty of con- 
science and the scientific love of truth . 420 This “holy community ” 
idea might also develop within the Church merely as the intensi- 
fication of the idea of sanctification and asceticism, and this 
is what actually happened in the development of Puritanism and 
Pietism. From the very outset this possibility of development 
belonged to the very nature of Calvinism. Is it not customary 
to call Bucer, who had such a decided influence over Calvin, 
“the Pietist among the Reformers”? And Calvin himself is often 
described as a “Rigorist”. Here also, however, this tendency 
needed to be released and developed in one particular direc- 
tion by definite circumstances. It emerged first of all within 
the setting of a wide general national life, which became to 
Calvinism the menace of secularization, a difficulty which could 
no longer be solved by Calvin’s ideals administered in the 
Genevan style by the exercise of discipline. This danger did not 
arise in Geneva itself, where the Huguenots were entirely ab- 
sorbed in the great political struggle, nor in Scotland, where 
religion was organized entirely on the principles of Geneva. 
Puritanism, however, had a very decided development in “Merrie 
England”, with its dominant State Church — in the Netherlands, 
which never became completely Calvinist, and where the 
powers of the court of discipline in particular were much 
restricted — in the West German provinces, which were influenced 
by the Netherlands, and in America, which had been awakened 
by Methodism; through these channels Puritanism also pene- 
trated into the life of the French and the Swiss churches in the 
nineteenth century. In Germany also, which likewise was menaced 
by the danger of secularization, and above all where Lutheranism 
was struggling for its life against a rigid and lifeless orthodoxy, 
it gave rise to a similar reform movement, to some extent stimu- 

4 *° See p. 940. 



678 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

lated by the example of Calvinistic Pietism; from that time 
forward the separation between Lutheranism and Calvinism has 
been lessened. At the present day the whole of the Church life 
of the Continent is deeply influenced by the spirit of Anglo-Saxon 
Methodist Pietism. 

Puritanism in England 

English Calvinism was founded in the reign of Edward VI ; 
it first appeared in Cambridge, where Bucer had worked , 421 and 
in London, where the foreign churches, which were under the 
leadership of John k Lasko, set an example from the very be- 
ginning 422 of spirituality and strictness of life. During the reign 
of Elizabeth, under the influence of the exiles who were then 
returning from the Continent, English Calvinism drew much 
closer to the Genevan ideal, and it was also in close contact with 
Scottish Calvinism. It then gradually divided into three main 
currents, Presbyterianism, Congregationalism, and Puritanism, 
which often merged into one another. 

Presbyterianism was very clearly defined by Cartwright. 
Aided by Scotland during the period of the Long Parliament, it 
hoped to become the State religion of England. This is genuine 
Calvinism, spread throughout a great nation by a system of synods ; 
it needs no further description here. It seems probable that in the 
main Cromwell himself belonged to the Puritan movement 423 , from 
which he was only diverted for a time by his respect for the actual 
providential guidance of the nation through events and by his 
expectant confidence in the new revelations. A man like Baxter 
is a good representative of Puritan thought and achievement at 
its best. Down to the present day, too, the whole of English 
Pietism and Continental Pietism is still fed and nourished by the 
devotional books of Bunyan, the Baptist tinker. 

The movement began by attacking the Catholic elements in 
the Anglican Church, coupled with the demand for the institution 
of a court of Church discipline, and for the formation of “pure” 
bodies of communicants. Under the Stuarts, however, it then 
became a real religious awakening, a demand for a second 
Reformation, in which reform in doctrine should be followed by 
reform in life, and which desired to realize personal spirituality 
and holiness as the true essence of Christianity. 

421 Sec Harvey: Butzer in England , igo 6 (Dissertation of Marburg), with interesting 
information about Bucer’s socio-political proposals from De regno Chrisli, 
pp. 77S5 ; here already the conflict had begun against enclosures, monopolies, 
and miscarriage of justice. 422 See p. 940. 428 See p. 941. 



PROTESTANTISM 


679 

The following elements were characteristic of this Puritan 
movement: “prophesyings” or discussions in church between the 
minister and the congregation about the sermon and passages 
of Scripture; family worship, which included catechetical in- 
struction, conducted by the father of the family, care in the 
religious instruction of the young in matters which “pertain 
unto salvation”, since it is essential that each individual should 
know for himself all the conditions of salvation, as ignorance 
leads to Hell, as Bunyan teaches very vividly in the Pilgrim's 
Progress ; extempore prayer instead of a formal liturgy; severe 
self-discipline, systematically aiming at holiness — which explains 
the number of autobiographies, spiritual diaries and journals, 
and the stress laid on the duty of meditation ; avoidance of all 
profane pleasures, and a strict voluntary separation between the 
Puritans and the unconverted “children of this world”, or of 
the state of Nature; the demand for ascetic practices, and, above 
all, for the most strenuous industry as the best method of spiritual 
and corporal discipline ; a system of casuistry and of careful self- 
examination and consultation, combined with a very thorough 
exercise of the cure of souls ; its popular character, the provision 
of elementary education, and the effort to raise the general level 
of social life anlong “the people”; extreme simplicity of life in 
matters of comfort and of dress, which, however, did not prevent 
a certain dignity and sterling excellence of deportment ; practical 
capacity, reliability, and honesty in every walk in life, which is 
displayed in a very considerable amount of activity in practical 
affairs — in politics, in social questions, and in commerce ; and, 
finally, the spirit of unity, which, by laying emphasis solely upon 
practical experience, and the need to be “living epistles, known 
and read of all men”, abolished the barriers between the Pro- 
testant denominations, and united all “believers” in the “saint- 
liness” of Pietism. 

In all this the Puritans were consciously opposed to the Re- 
naissance spirit, and the literature of the Elizabethan and Stuart 
periods. They were also entirely opposed to the policy and 
economic standards of feudal times, which were expressed in the 
enclosures and in great monopolies. Shakespeare’s hatred of these 
Pietists with their hostility to sensuous pleasures, and Butler’s 
scorn for their theological narrowness and pedantry, are well 
known. 

The following Puritan characteristics bring out the difference 
between this movement and that of primitive Calvinism: a far 
more intense individualism, which, in spite of all the means of 



68o THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

grace, sets God and the soul over against each other in solitary 
immediacy; a detailed estimate of and examination into good 
works as “signs” of election, which introduces a legalism, self- 
righteousness, and a systematic asceticism to an extent which was 
unknown in genuine Calvinism; the spirit of solitary individual 
self-control and ascetic discipline, which does not exclude pleasure 
in the gifts and revelation of God in Nature, but which still dis- 
tinguishes the elect, who use the “speech of Canaan” and whose 
manner of life is strict, from the children of “the world” and the 
“children of wrath”. In all this the influence of new motives 
is undeniable. These new motives may be thus briefly summarized : 
the individualizing effects of the dogma of predestination, the 
collapse of strict ecclesiasticism through a period of ecclesiastical 
strife, and the division of Society into the strict and the lax. 
Naturally that produced a very different situation from that 
which had obtained in Calvin’s strictly uniform Christian State. 

On the other hand, this kind of Puritanism differs from 
Lutheran Pietism in its still unshaken loyalty to the Church, 
in its lack of emphasis upon a passionate “conviction of sin” 
and of a sudden emotional “assurance” of grace, and in the 
systematic logical result of progressive sanctification. Since in 
Lutheranism justification by faith is regarded as the key which 
suddenly unlocks the door of the heavenly treasury, and the 
happiness to which this gives rise is regarded as the only clear 
proof that the soul is in a state of grace, the central body of 
Lutheran Pietism naturally concentrated on “conviction of sin” 
and the “sense of assurance”. In Calvinism, however, grace is 
something which existed before the world was, and slowly aqd 
gradually evolves in election. Thus in Puritanism conversion was 
regarded as the effect of predestination which had gradually 
evolved, and it believed in the careful control and cultivation 
of this process, and not in “feelings”, which a mere temporal 
faith can have also. Thus it was easier to combine loyalty to 
the Church with this conception, since it is precisely the means 
of grace which mediate this progress, and from the very outset 
the fact that they are “spiritually” conceived does not hinder 
the inwardness of faith. In order to compensate for the aridity 
and austerity of the asceticism of sanctification mysticism is called 
in to help. Since, however, it was here combined with the Cal- 
vinistic idea of the insertio in Christum non otiosum , this kind of 
mysticism had a more practical and active tendency than that 
of Lutheranism. Chiliastic ideas appeared now and again, but on 
the whole they were comparatively rare, and it is not certain 



PROTESTANTISM 


68 1 

to what extent they may possibly have been introduced by 
Anabaptists and fanatics. 

Thus this Calvinistic Puritan Pietism was somewhat different 
from Continental Pietism. It was the moral school of the English 
middle classes, and after the fluctuations of the great period of 
the Enlightenment in England it reappeared as early as the 
eighteenth century — this time, however, in the shape of Metho- 
dism, which was indeed in the line of the old Puritan tradition, 
though it also contained some essentially new elements. There will 
be more to say about this later on, when Methodism is described, 
since it finally joined the ranks of the Separatists. The Evangelical 
spirit which it produced, which repeatedly led the attack on the 
Enlightenment, in spite of various deviations, reveals even to-day 
the power of the Puritan Calvinistic Spirit, and has also extended 
its influence to non-Calvinistic Church-groups . 424 

At the outset the social structure of Puritanism included people 
from all ranks of Society. To the extent, however, in which it 
became a “Holiness” movement it became the religion of the 
middle classes, and since its revival through Methodism in Eng- 
land and America this has become more and more its settled 
character. The lay element became predominant, and theology 
and clericalism were regarded as secondary; finally, after the 
Revolution the court and the aristocracy broke with it altogether. 
Its way of life did not commend itself to the higher officials and 
the nobility, and it could only be forced upon the naturalism 
of the rural population (which was so difficult to break) with 
great limitations. When this whole movement was classed as 
“lessen t”, alongside of the Established Church and the official 
world, the groups which composed it were forced from the very 
beginning into the world of commerce. This bourgeois spirit of 
the middle classes was carried over to New England at the very 
beginning by the Pilgrim Fathers, and in spite of the extremely 
primitive economic conditions of existence which prevailed there 
at first they developed the bourgeois and capitalist character 
which forms the predominant element in the American people, 
and which finally triumphed over the aristocratic and slave- 
holding colonies of the Southern States. 

This is the group which supports Liberalism in politics, and 
which, from the economic point of view, out of the fundamental 
conditions of Calvinism which in general were already favourable, 
developed, with peculiar energy and with a sober realism, the 
spirit which gave to the bourgeois capitalism of these peoples the 

424 See p. 941. 



68a THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

ideal foundations for its extensive development and success among 
the masses of the people. 425 

“Precisianism” in the Netherlands 
Calvinism in the Netherlands developed along similar lines, 
but its results were different. With the continuance of the Baptist 
groups, and of the mystical movements with their emphasis 
upon “spiritual religion”, as well as with the formation of a 
strong Puritan Pietist group within the Calvinistic State Church, 
the same elements were present which in England led to the 
explosion of the great Revolution. All that was lacking was the 
opposition of a persecuting Catholicizing State Church, and an 
inner political crisis in the system of government. Here, however, 
from the very outset the bourgeois republic had a tendency to 
adopt the secular ideals of Calvinism, and here also the eccle- 
siastical ideals of Calvinism were finally realized in a compara- 
tively satisfactory manner. Thus the Puritan development in 
the Netherlands was confined to a strongly ascetic and rigorist 
movement of those who were nicknamed the “Precisians” or the 
“Stalwarts”. This movement was composed of people who were 
opposed to the Humanistic culture of the Renaissance, and to 
its accompanying phenomena of a fabulous economic develop- 
ment, which surpassed that of all the other nations of Europe 
at that time, and they formed themselves into small groups 
within the National State Church. A tendency in this direction 
had already existed within Dutch Calvinism from the time when 
the first national synod had met outside the Dutch boundaries at 
Emden in 1571, and had there first felt its solidarity as a national 
body, and had tried to formulate an ecclesiastical system for 
the whole nation. While in Holland itself it was impossible to 
make any attempts at Church organization owing to the Spanish 
tyranny, and then to the ecclesiastical chaos which was only 
regulated with difficulty by the local authorities, the exiled Cal- 
vinists tried to organize their Church system on the Huguenot 
pattern. This ecclesiastical system, which made a clear distinction 
between the wider circle of the baptized and the narrower circle 
of those who had been explicitly received into the Church through 
Confirmation, and which also had a strict system of moral dis- 
cipline, showed its evident connection with small and strict 
refugee churches. After the Union of Utrecht (1579) the exiles 
gradually began to return to Holland; they then proceeded to 
make treaties with the various State authorities of particular 

485 Sec p. 942. 



PROTESTANTISM 683 

provinces, by which they created Calvinistic State churches, 
which, however, alongside of themselves tolerated the existence 
of minorities which held other opinions ; these churches also had 
to submit to a considerable amount of State supervision, par- 
ticularly with reference to the exercise of ecclesiastical discipline. 
Everywhere, too, they were hostile to the earlier and more liberal 
Reform movement in the Netherlands, and also to the great 
cities, which were mainly concerned with commerce, and there- 
fore in their own interest were in favour of a policy of religious 
toleration. Even as early as the Synod of Emden (1571) the 
hostility between the Preciesen (i.e. the rabid Calvinists) and the 
Rekkelijken (i.e. the party of compromise) was quite evident. 

After the State churches had been formed the opposition 
became more intense. The conflict raged round the questions of 
a strict Calvinistic constitution, a strict creed, the ethical ideal of 
Rigorism. “Precisians” and “Libertines” now faced each other 
in hostile camps. In this situation the primary concern of the 
strict Calvinists was the exclusion of the Arminians, whose 
outlook was predominantly humanist and deeply influenced by 
Erasmus, and who also stood out for the ecclesiastical dignity 
of the State, and for the independence and variety of conditions 
within each individual State; the strict Calvinists also opposed 
all the groups which supported the Arminians. Their endeavours 
were crowned with success by the treaty between the Stadtholder 
(who in the person of the Prince of Orange was likewise con- 
cerned for the attainment of national unity) and the strict 
Calvinist party at the Synod of Dort in 1618. This Synod laid 
down a host of regulations, which, with the aid of the Govern- 
ment, they hoped would help to make the Netherlands strictly 
Calvinist. It was, however, realized that this goal could not be 
attained by external means alone, and indeed, within a short 
time, Arminianism and Erastianism had to be tolerated once 
more, in accordance with the position adopted by the different 
States in particular. The strict Calvinists now realized that they 
could best attain their end by personal dealing in spiritual 
matters; if this were unsuccessful, then the “Libertines” might 
have to be excommunicated by the Church courts. Taffin and 
Udemann led the way, but in the main the authorities borrowed 
their methods of dealing with these difficulties from English 
Puritanism. Wilhelm Teellinck, the father of Pietism in the 
Netherlands, began his career under the influence of impressions 
of English Puritanism which he had gained during a journey in 
England. The other leaders, and Voet in particular, made great 



684 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

use of English literature, and many English books were translated 
into Dutch. One of the leading founders of Pietism in the Nether- 
lands, Amesius, was an English refugee, and Lodensteyn also 
wished to prepare himself for his practical activity by a journey 
to England. 

Here also, therefore, the transition from Calvinism to a Pietism 
which was more individualistic, based on the “conventicle” 
pattern, pastoral, and strongly mystical, was almost unnoticeable. 
But as time went on, and its latent tendencies began to develop, 
it became very plain that a great gulf separated this kind of 
Pietism, which was entirely orthodox in theology, and also loyal 
to the National Church, from the primitive Calvinism of a united 
national community sanctified by the sovereignty of Christ. A 
widespread system of conventicles arose with a wealth of ascetic 
literature ; the watchword of the pastors of this school of thought 
was the theologia regenitoium ; the laity was permitted to take part 
in public worship in the conventicles, in which women also were 
permitted to teach. The children of grace and of election sepa- 
rated themselves from the children of the world; they observed 
the Sabbath very strictly; they practised casuistry and self- 
examination and systematic asceticism, in which they were not 
afraid of taking hints from the Jesuits and from the Catholics 
in general. Home and Foreign Missions were carried on; and 
great stress was laid on conversion and the visible signs of con- 
version. Here too, as in England, the doctrine of good works as 
the signs and tokens of the fact of election was accepted, with 
which was combined a similar strict systematic legalism and 
exercise of self-discipline. Here also the individualistic spirit was 
revealed in diaries, autobiographies, narratives of edifying death- 
beds, as well as in the practice of family worship and in the cure 
of souls. The Pietists found it almost impossible to bring the 
secularized National Church to this austere way of life, and here 
too they took refuge in the ideas of eschatology and Chiliasm. 
Especially they balanced the prevailing hard, sober, and dry 
spirit of legalism and of discipline with a spirit of mystical 
devotion akin to the early mysticism of the Netherlands, the 
mysticism of St. Bernard, and the mystical interpretation of the 
Song of Songs ; in other words, this led to the incursion of an 
emotional and contemplative individualism which was entirely 
remote from the spirit of Calvin. Here early national traditions 
again broke through. Voet explicitly described his teacher Teel- 
linck as a “Calvinistic Thomas a Kempis”. 

The only difference between this renewed asceticism and the 



PROTESTANTISM 685 

older kind was this: the Dutch Pietists explicitly claimed that 
all secular callings ought to be penetrated by this spirit, and 
they violently opposed every endeavour to exempt secular life 
from this demand. It was explicitly an asceticism within the 
ordinary life of the world. Thus the Pietists did not desire Sepa- 
ratism, but the sanctification both of the nation and of the 
Church. Unbelievers were to be excluded, and believers were 
to rule ; it ought not to be the other way round. In the true spirit 
of Calvinism the Pietist leaders kept their gaze fixed on life as 
a whole, and they continually made fresh attempts to gain the 
aid of the authorities in their endeavours after holiness. Their 
main efforts were engaged in the struggle against patronage, 
against luxury, against modern philosophy, and against the prin- 
ciple of toleration ; they were, however, not very successful among 
the upper classes. However, the period of suffering caused by 
the wars of Louis XIV became a period of great popular success, 
which also led to a modification of the legal severity into a more 
evangelical, less Old Testament spirit. The programme of the 
sanctification of the whole Church, and of the masses, on these 
lines naturally could not be actually realized. Thus, in the end, 
Separatist phenomena appeared ; and, on the other hand, radical 
individual mystics severed their connection with ecclesiastical 
orthodoxy. Mystical inwardness and the sectarian spirit, which 
had never died out in the Netherlands, carried many religious 
people away from the Church, as we shall see later on. A strong 
section of Pietist Christians, however, remained within the State 
churches all through the whole period of the Enlightenment, 
arjjd through the confusion of the Napoleonic period. 

When the Netherlands became a unified State and a Kingdom, 
and the Calvinistic State Church also had to be reorganized, then 
these Pietists broke off as the “separated Reformed Church”, 
that is, as an orthodox and Pietistic Free Church. This Church 
still plays an important part in the life of the Netherlands, and, 
under its leader .Kuyper (who has often been mentioned in this 
book), through a common policy with the Catholics, it has won 
for the time being an absolutely dominant position. In his his- 
torical, theoretical, and political writings Kuyper has made an 
intelligent and even brilliant study of this type of Neo-Calvinism, 
which is certainly better represented among Anglo-Saxons than 
on the Continent. Still in many respects this Netherlands Free 
Church may be compared with English Dissent . 428 

The social composition of this Pietist Calvinism of the Nether- 

426 See p. 943. 



686 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

lands, which in the seventeenth century generally coincided with 
strict Calvinism, and by this means dominated the main body 
of the nation, cannot be ascertained from the material which 
is at present available. It is well known that the rich merchant 
class, above all that of Amsterdam, was Arminian in temper, 
and that the politicians valued toleration as the salvation of the 
Netherlands; it was certainly to the advantage of the exiled 
English and French Calvinists, the Mennonites and the sects, as 
also of the Spanish and Portuguese Jews, that is, of groups 
which both politically and economically formed an integral part 
of the Calvinist Republic. It is also well known that the town 
population was far larger than the agricultural population, and 
that the peasantry had already begun to turn towards a capital- 
istic technical method of pursuing agriculture, and were thus not 
so very remote from bourgeois Calvinism; in spite of that the 
Pietists fought hard against rural fairs, and we may conclude that 
among the peasants there was a good deal of resistance to their 
Rigorism. We may therefore assume that here also this strict 
Calvinism was mainly bourgeois and middle class. Here, how- 
ever, it had no occasion to stand out in such pronounced 
opposition to the aristocratic way of life as English Puritanism 
and its successors, Dissent and the Evangelical Party. At this 
point it felt itself in harmony with the spirit of the Republic 
and of the bourgeois social order; it is impossible to isolate 
and distinguish any particular social doctrines as peculiar to the 
Calvinistic Pietism of the Netherlands . 427 

Pietism in the Churches of the 
Lower Rhine and of Switzerland 
The Pietism in the Reformed Churches of the Lower Rhine, 
which at first was closely connected with the Calvinism of the 
Netherlands, and which also after the formation of the Nether- 
lands State Churches was permanently influenced by it, does not 
need to be described in detail. Here the same features recur. In 
these Churches, however, Pietism was maintained more con- 
tinuously, since in these lands Calvinism never became a State 
Church, but always — first of all “under the Cross”, then tolerated 
and supported by Brandenburg, finally taken into the Rhenish- 
Westphalian Church — it had to prove its right to exist by an 
intensified practical holiness, and it never had any connection 
with National or State Churches. In this region, therefore, Pietism 
has always remained particularly strong, and is so at the present 

487 See p. 945. 



PROTESTANTISM 


687 

time, providing a favourable atmosphere for a very flourishing 
sectarian movement. This Pietist movement had no visible effect 
on politics ; as a minority religion it was shut out from all wider 
political influence, although even at the present day it is not 
regarded with favour by the Prussian authorities. Its economic 
results are well known. They have not been confined within the 
limits of a Pietist middle class, but they include the great and 
rich merchants and manufacturers ; this is quite intelligible, since 
there is here no privileged class of landowners, nor any social 
group which would be out of harmony with vital Pietist prin- 
ciples . 428 

There is just as little need to describe the Calvinistic Pietism 
of Switzerland. It owed its origin to the influence of German 
Pietism ; from the outset, therefore, it cannot be interpreted from 
the point of view of Calvinism. The religious awakenings of the 
nineteenth century in French Switzerland were also due to foreign 
influence. The Calvinistic setting has, however, had a strong in- 
fluence upon this Pietism, and has stamped upon it the charac- 
teristics of ecclesiastical Puritanism. Politically the Swiss Pietists 
belong to aristocratic conservative circles; they really form a 
republican aristocracy. Its economic and social effects which 
attract most attention are the industrialism of French Switzer- 
land, the wealth of Basle, and its great services to the common 
weal . 429 

In North America, moreover, it is impossible to isolate Cal- 
vinistic, Puritan, and sectarian influences. Each particular 
question would need to be studied in much closer detail. In this 
connection we can only emphasize the fact, which is generally 
redbgnized, that everywhere the Puritanism of the leading Eng- 
lish section in American life is regarded, even down to the present 
day, as an essential element of American political and social life, 
although, so far as I can ascertain, no one has ever yet thrown 
a clear light upon the precise connection between the two 
facts . 430 


488 See Gdbel: Gesch. des christlichen Lebens. A great part of the more important 
passages have already been utilized above ; here it is mainly clear how Calvinism 
and Pietism merge into one another. On this point cf. Ritschl: Gesch, des 
Pietismus , I; Simons: Synodalbuch und die Kirchen unter dem Kreuz- The Pietism of 
the Wuppertal, with its results in economic and ethical life, must be regarded 
as well known. 

418 See Ritschl, /; the rest is based upon general impressions; in any case 
Basle is a model of social ethics of a Pietist-Calvinistic kind. 

480 See p. 945. 



688 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 


Neo-Calvinism and the 
Rise of Ascetic Protestantism 

If we look back, from the point at which we have now arrived, 
at this subject as a whole, the difference between primitive and 
modem Calvinism becomes quite plain. Neo-Calvinism, with its 
Free Church system, and its accompanying phenomena of democ- 
racy and liberalism, as well as with the Pietistic Rigorism of 
a strong self-controlled individualism, very utilitarian in secular 
affairs, has moved very far away from the early aristocratic 
Calvinism of the period of its foundation at Geneva, when it was 
still close to Lutheranism. For that very reason, however, it 
has become a great new social and ethical principle within 
Christendom. 

The Christian ethic here bears a quite different complexion 
from its aspect in other confessions, particularly in Lutheranism. 
In Lutheranism it was precisely the inwardness of the Christian 
morality of love which demanded detachment from the external 
affairs of the order of law and of the State ; further, it encouraged 
the exclusion of competition and of the struggle for existence in 
the professional guild organization, and from that point of view 
recommended the individual to withdraw into inward happiness, 
and in external matters to submit humbly to the existing aris- 
tocratic organizations of life. Neo-Calvinism, on the other hand, 
requires the Christian-Liberal organization of the State and of 
Society, independence and freedom for the individual, equality 
of opportunity as well as in the eyes of the law, the organization 
of international peace, and the conquest of the struggle for exis- 
tence by means of self-discipline and active social help through 
associated effort. Only thus does it believe that the Christian 
ideals of freedom and brotherly love can be realized, and thus 
it appeals to the Bible as the great social text-book of humanity. 
The patriarchal conservative elements of the Christian ethic have 
receded, and the aspects of social reform and love of liberty have 
come to the front . 431 

Within Lutheranism and Calvinism, therefore, the Christian 
ethic has developed in diametrically opposite directions. In German 
Prussia, Lutheranism has become the support of the conservative, 
aristocratic, legal positivist, and compulsory orthodoxy order 
of life, and develops in its genuine adherents the Christian virtues 
of an inwardness which is detached from the world, along 
with those of submission, patience, reverence, kindly care 

481 See p. 945. 



PROTESTANTISM 689 

for others, and conservative endurance. Calvinism, on the 
contrary, has become a Christian intensification of the ideas 
of democracy and liberalism, and it produces the virtues of 
independence, love of liberty, love of humanity, and of Christian 
social reform. 

Both the chief elements of the earliest Christian ethic have been 
divided between the two confessions, and in the process each has 
been extraordinarily invigorated. Catholicism, on the other hand, 
has remained until the present day a combination of both these 
elements, and, as occasion arises, it emphasized sometimes the 
democratic aspect of Natural Law, and sometimes its aristocratic 
and patriarchal aspect, quite sure that it can prevent any conflict 
between these tendencies by means of its central ecclesiastical 
board of control, which is daily gaining more authority. Calvinism, 
however, in its fundamental tendency towards as much of a 
national Church as possible, and in its emphasis upon the in- 
equality of mankind in all relationships which are not directly 
religious, still remains inwardly aloof from the purely voluntary 
Church-system, and from the equalitarian communistic ideas of 
the strict sect, in spite of all the close connection between the 
two. The individualism which is based upon predestination is, 
and remains, different from the individualism which is supported 
by the rationalistic Baptist doctrine of freedom. 

Now, however, the last point is certainly not settled by merely 
emphasizing the difference between Calvinism and the sects, 
since it is precisely this difference which has become so much 
less important in recent times. Calvinism has formally drawn 
nearer to the sects. On the other hand, after the Baptists had 
reorganized themselves into the Mennonite sect, all the other 
sects which appeared later on were already more or less under 
the influence of Calvinism. The Free Church principle and 
Pietism have, moreover, permitted both the main groups to come 
still closer to one another. 

Only now is it possible to discern the position which Calvinism 
occupies in the world at the present day, and its social signifi- 
cance for civilization. Calvinism and the sect-group composed of 
the Baptists, Methodists, and Salvationists to-day constitute a 
religious unity which also represents a great sociological collective 
type of Christian thought. It is supported mainly by the Anglo- 
Saxon nations, but it is not confined to them, but is present in 
all Calvinist countries. It has also had a very great influence 
upon the religious and ethical thought and practice of contem- 
porary Lutheranism, especially with the aid ofTPietism, which 

vol. n. ft 



690 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

arose from the same source, even although it is characteristically 
different . 432 

This fusion is based, on the one hand, on the fact that the 
sect-idea which influenced Calvinism a good deal from the 
outset became increasingly powerful as time went on, and finally 
prevailed. The whole of this previous study proves the truth of 
this statement. The sect-idea was only checked by the fact 
that Calvinism positively accepted the world, and by its con- 
ception of itself as an objective ecclesiastical institution, in spite 
of all its Free Church tendencies. 

The theological idea of predestination which originally dis- 
tinguished Calvinism so clearly from the Baptist movement has 
to a great extent receded, without the necessary disappearance 
of the practical and ethical results which were derived from it. 
The idea of sanctification which was bound up with that dogma 
lived on independently, and led to the Free Church ideal with 
a strict system of ethics. At this point, however, the development of 
the sect came into touch with Calvinism ; this was due to the fact 
that as the sects extended and settled down under tolerant State 
conditions they became large national churches, and they then 
either gave up or largely modified their attitude of separation 
as “holy communities”, and their opposition to “the world” with 
its political and economic conditions. The modern sects in par- 
ticular, have been influenced by Calvinism from the very be- 
ginning, and they are very different from the Waldensians and 
the Baptists. Both groups agree in their emphasis upon the 
voluntary principle, and upon a systematic ascetic strictness in 
their way of life. Thus together they have developed into a force 
which in contradistinction to the softer, more easygoing, and less 
principled Lutheranism has been called “ascetic Protestantism”. 
It might also be called the “individualistic Protestantism of 
active-holiness”, if this description were not too cumbrous. From 
the point of view of historical influence this “ascetic Protes- 
tantism” is to-day the chief force in Protestantism, since it extends 
its influence far beyond the genuinely Pietistic and ascetic circles 
of “earnest” Christians. Along with mediaeval Catholicism it 
constitutes the second great main type of Christian social doctrine, 

432 This is a leading idea of Max Weber ; and also of Kuyper ; also see Knodt, 
45-46, and Holl in the Calvinreden, p. 26. Held has noticed this also. P. 303: 
“The working classes had long ago turned away from the aristocratic State 
Church, and their religious needs were met especially by the sects, in which 
the democratic spirit of Puritanism lived on in a modified form.” Finally, I 
would refer the reader once more to Weber* s views on this question. 



PROTESTANTISM 


691 

while the more subtle but weaker ideas of social doctrine in 
mysticism, in spiritual idealism, in Lutheranism, and in philo- 
sophical Neo-Protestantism are far behind it in historical influence. 

While Catholicism had both the necessary complexity and 
authority to embrace and to direct the whole of life, ascetic 
Protestantism has the necessary hardness and flexibility, the 
religious energy, and the matter-of-fact sobriety, the power to 
adapt itself to the ethical ideas of the average man combined 
with doctrinal simplicity, which likewise enable it, in its own way, 
to dominate the whole of life ; and just as Catholicism was con- 
nected with the general conditions of mediaeval life, so ascetic 
Protestantism is connected with modern developments in the 
political, economic, social, and technical spheres. 

In order to understand this fully, however, it will be necessary 
also to study the development of the sect-type within Protes- 
tantism. In so doing we shall discover that mysticism and spiritual 
idealism contain influences which have a vital effect upon the 
social doctrines of all confessions. We shall note in particular the 
significance of the transformation of the sect-type into great mass 
communities, the development of their freedom within the sphere 
of the tolerant modern State, and the adaptation of the sects 
to the bourgeois social order. Since, however, in all this there 
takes place that adjustment with Neo-Calvinism to which allusion 
has already been made, the social doctrines of Neo-Calvinism 
can only be presented in a conclusive manner in conjunction 
with the social doctrines of the sects. 


4. TttE SECT-TYPE AND MYSTICISM WITHIN PROTESTANTISM 
Introduction 

Lutheranism and Calvinism do not represent the whole of 
Protestantism. In these two great confessions the Reformers were 
able to work out their basic idea of the Church as an institution. 
It was thus that they maintained their connection with the funda- 
mental idea of the Early Church, and, above all, with mediaeval 
Catholicism and its theory of a universal Church of the people, 
dominating the whole of civilization. Other movements, how- 
ever, of a sectarian and mystical type, constantly emerged along- 
side of this mediaeval unity of Catholic civilization, and their 
ideas had a most decided influence upon the thought of Catholi- 
cism. The same phenomena appeared both within and alongside of 
Protestantism. Thus, in addition to the institutional idea of the 



692 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Church, Protestantism also developed the characteristic ideas of 
the sects and of mysticism. Since these ideas originated in the 
New Testament , 433 the emphasis laid on the New Testament by 
Protestantism naturally gave a great impetus to these tendencies. 
In Protestantism, however, the need to work out its own idea of 
the Church as an institution, and its relation to an absolute, 
objective, supreme truth of revelation, was felt to be a matter of 
paramount concern ; the sectarian and mystical movements were 
therefore thrust aside and forced to adopt an independent position. 
However, in spite of ecclesiastical antagonism, both these move- 
ments still remained in closest touch with the Protestant Churches, 
and from the middle of the seventeenth century these ideals had 
an increasing influence upon them. Reference has already been 
made to the adjustment which took place between these ideals 
and those of Calvinism. The reason for this is clear. From the 
very beginning, indeed, the Protestant Reform movement had 
been permeated by both these tendencies, and its opposition to 
Catholicism was due, to a great extent, to the co-operation of 
both these factors. 

It was through mysticism that Luther first gained that personal 
certainty of salvation in which he found that the ennobling and 
overcoming power of grace was imparted, not through mechanical 
sacraments which could not deliver from conviction of sin, but 
through an inner spiritual experience. The strictness and purity 
of Luther’s Scriptural attitude towards ethics made him place 
the personal ethic of the Sermon on the Mount, and the doctrine 
of the priesthood of all believers, in the forefront of his ethical 
teaching. This meant that he had discarded the mediaeval doctrine 
of the compromise between Nature and Supernature. He slrove 
to find a new interpretation for the forms and values of the 
natural life: thus, in his earlier period, Luther’s outlook was 
often very similar to that of the sect-type. 

Protestantism, however, did not attain its full independence, 
combined with an ever-increasing hostility towards the sectarian 
and mystical tendencies, until the following points had become 
clear : first of all, men had to learn to base their hope of salvation 
firmly and exclusively upon the objective assurance of the forgive- 
ness of sins through the Death of Christ ; this led to concentration 
of emphasis upon the inward appropriation of the forgiveness of 
sins, directly offered from without; everything else followed 
logically from this central fact of experience; on this objective 
foundation the Protestant Church was firmly established, with 

483 See p. 946* 



PROTESTANTISM 


693 

power to mediate the certainty of redemption through the Word 
and the Sacrament; the final stage of this process was reached 
when the spiritual ethic of the Sermon on the Mount spread from 
the Church outwards into the established forms of professional 
and social life. 43 4 

This separation between Church and Sect, however, did 
not prevent the sectarian and mystical movements from feeling 
themselves, to some extent at least, at home within Protestantism. 
In point of fact, within Protestantism these sectarian and mystical 
ideas have undergone a peculiar process of development, very 
different from that of the older forms; they differ completely 
from the development of the same ideas within the sphere of post- 
Tridentine Catholicism. 

At the close of the section on the Middle Ages the main charac- 
teristics of the sect-type were indicated . 436 Here, therefore, it is 
only necessary to bring out the connection between the Protestant 
sects, or the Anabaptist movement, and the mediaeval sects ; we 
also need to make clear the particular form which they now 
developed within Protestantism. 

The question of mysticism, however, needs different treatment. 
It was, of course, mentioned incidentally in connection with the 
later Middle Ages , 436 but its religious nature has not yet been 
analysed, nor the religious-sociological character with which it is 
connected. At that stage it was not necessary to go into the 
question fully, for although even then mysticism was an important 
factor for theology, for the philosophy of religion, for the history 
of civilization and for psychology, the religious and sociological 
peculiarities and results had scarcely begun to appear. 

Mysticism meant the rise of a lay religion within the Church, 
and it greatly encouraged the individualistic tendency of the 
bourgeois world. But at that time it had no influence upon the 
life of the religious community, nor had it yet any critical signifi- 
cance in connection with the idea of the Church, or with doctrine. 
Mysticism was still either under the protection of the Church, or 
it was connected with the Religious Orders. It never stood alone. 
Protestant mysticism, on the contrary, learnt to regard itself as 
the outcome of the idea of the priesthood of all believers, and 
of the personal religion of conviction, and thus it was able to 
make an independent stand. 

In studying this question our primary aim will be to make 
clear the sociological results of these phenomena. As we 
proceed it will become clear that they introduce into the history 
484 See p. 947. 484 See above, pp. 328-343- m See abovc > PP- 37 ^ 377 - 



694 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

of Christianity a principle which has to-day assumed a position 
of paramount importance. 

I. The Baptist Movement 
and the Protestant Sects 

The first question with which we have to deal is that of the 
Protestant sect, or the Anabaptist movement. At an earlier stage 
in this work we have shown that the sect-idea was deeply rooted 
in the thought and creative activity of the great Reformers. Luther 
made a distinction between the ethic of the Sermon on the 
Mount, or the ethic of the individual, and the secular or official 
ethic, or the ethic of the relative Natural Law of the fallen State. 
He defined the former as the genuine Christian ethic. In so doing, 
however, he was really only making concessions to the needs of 
the national Church, necessities which God allowed to exist, but 
which were actually due to the Fall . 437 Traces of the earlier idea 
remained, however; it was never entirely hidden, but was only 
obscured by the hollowness of orthodoxy. This is revealed by the 
fact that at the outset of his career Luther had reckoned on the 
influence of smaller groups of earnest Christians to leaven and 
influence the general compulsory religion of the Territorial Church. 
It was only the danger of subjectivism which caused these plans 
to be set aside, and in the uniform Territorial Church of the 
Visitations they were allowed to disappear . 438 

The opposition within Protestantism has never ceased to appeal 
to these statements which belong to Luther’s earlier days; they 
are echoed again and again, from the days of the early Baptists 
down to the time of the English Independents and the German 
Pietists . 439 

The sect-type has influenced Calvinism still more strongly, 
though from a different point of view. Calvin adopted the sect- 
ideal — the idea of the “holy community” — and also the sectarian 
methods by which this ideal could be realized, such as excommuni- 
cation and Church discipline, and he applied this ideal to a whole 
territorial and national Church, instead of to small groups of 
genuine Christians within the Church. The non-elect and the un- 
believers were to be disciplined for the glory of God with the same 
means which were to be used to develop and establish in the 
elect a spirit of genuine spiritual piety. Thus in Calvinism the 
sect-ideal of the holy community became the general ideal of 

487 Cf. Hamack: Dogmengeschichte, III*, p. 004 : “That which was divided between 
the cloister and the world in Catholicism the Reformers desired to unite in 
common labour.” This, however, is simply “intramundane asceticism”. 

488 See p. 947. 488 See p. 947. 



PROTESTANTISM 695 

national life and of civilization ; at a later stage the inner tension 
which this produced shattered the solidarity of Calvinism. 

It is not difficult to understand why the Protestant sect-type 440 
extended its influence far beyond the measure permitted by the 
ecclesiastical Reformation itself. An entirely natural factor in this 
development was the influence of the Bible, including that of the 
Sermon on the Mount, which could only be adapted with diffi- 
culty to the compromise which the Reformers had achieved. 
Again and again it was the direct influence of the Sermon on the 
Mount which impelled people to form strict Christian communi- 
ties, whose members wished to live according to this standard; 
they then found it impossible to remain under the wing of a 
national Church, and of a general civilized society. This pheno- 
menon is all the more intelligible because both in thought, and 
possibly also in organization, the religious life of that day was 
already permeated with these ideas, due very largely to Walden- 
sian or Bohemian influences. Thus the groups which held these 
views saw in the Reformation simply the development of their 
own programme, and in its victories the possibility of developing 
a free, anti-hierarchical, and entirely lay religious movement. 

General Characteristics of 
the Baptist Movement 

In fact, under the stimulus of the Reformation, on every hand 
there sprang into existence an enormous number of small groups 
of earnest Christians, living apart from “the world”, claiming 
complete civil and religious freedom, whose main ideal was the 
formation of religious communities composed of truly “converted” 
persons, on a basis of voluntary membership. Their outward 
symbol of membership was Adult Baptism, which implied the 
voluntary principle. They rejected Infant Baptism, with its 
implications of an all-inclusive, non-ethical basis of Church 
membership. Another characteristic external sign was the demand 
for Church discipline, and authority to excommunicate, which was 
closely related to the demand for “a pure Church”. They did not 
accept the ecclesiastical doctrine of the Sacrament. To them the 
Lord’s Supper was mainly a festival of Christian fellowship, and 
an expression of personal faith in Christ. Thus they were classed 
with the “ Sakramenlierier ”.* Their real strength, however, lay in the 

440 See p. 949. 

* Luther’s epithet for those who denied the Real Presence of Christ in the 
Sacrament of the Lord’s Supper. He applied it particularly to men like 
Zwingli, Karls tad t, Oecolampadius, Schwenkfeld, and others. — Trans- 
lator’s Note. 



696 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

emphasis which they gave to their desire to be a “holy com- 
munity”, “holy” in the sense of the Sermon on the Mount, and 
implying a voluntary community composed of mature Christians. 
In practice this “holiness” was expressed in the following ways : 
in detachment from the State, from all official positions, from 
law, force, and the oath, and from war, violence, and capital 
punishment; the quiet endurance of suffering and injustice as 
their share in the Cross of Christ, the intimate social relationship 
of the members with each other through care for the poor and 
the provision of relief funds, so that within these groups no one 
was allowed to beg or to starve ; strict control over the Church 
members through the exercise of excommunication and congre- 
gational discipline. Their form of worship was a simple service, 
purely Scriptural in character, conducted by elected preachers 
and pastors who had been ordained by the laying-on of hands, 
and prayer by the synods representing the local groups . 441 They 
also accepted the moral Law of Nature, but they opposed the 
relative conception accepted by the Church, the compromise of 
Natural Law with Original Sin. Like their mediaeval predecessors, 
they interpreted the Law of Nature as the absolute Natural Law 
of the Primitive State ; from this interpretation they sometimes 
deduced conclusions which were as revolutionary as those pro- 
claimed by the followers of Wyclif and Huss. In general, however, 
they held that it was impossible to carry out the Natural Law, and 
the Law of Christ with which they identified it, in the world, 
because the world is of the devil, and is the scene of suffering and 
endurance until the Advent of Christ, from which the faithful are 
to prepare themselves by separation from it. Thus this movement 
displays the main characteristics of the sect-type, with which our 
previous study of the question has already made us familiar. 

Origin of the Baptist Movement 
Thus we can understand why some thinkers have even suggested 
that perhaps these Baptist sects were merely a sign of the reappear- 
ance of the mediaeval, Waldensian sect, made possible by the 
Reformation. To that we must reply: (i) that we have no con- 
clusive proof of the continued existence of any sect of this kind 
as a uniform international organization, and (2) that there is no 
evidence that the Baptist leaders came from these sectarian 
circles. They were all the product of the religious movements of 
the time; some were originally Lutheran, others Zwinglian or 
Humanist, while some came from the ranks of the laity whose 

441 See p. 951. 



PROTESTANTISM 


697 

main interest was in the Bible. But in addition to the positive 
characteristics which have just been indicated— the priesthood of 
all believers, the central position of the Bible, and their emphasis 
on personal religion — these movements also contained some 
negative features — a spirit of criticism, of disappointment with 
the Reformation, as well as a more thorough emphasis upon its 
main ideas. This comes out in their emphasis upon Adult Baptism 
(or rebaptism) as the motto of the new movement ; it comes out 
still more clearly in the struggle against the moral sterility of 
the great Churches of the Reformation, with their emphasis on 
compulsion in religious matters, and in the bitter scorn which 
the Baptist leaders pour upon the friendship of the Reformation 
leaders with the world, and with royalty. These facts are familiar, 
though their deeper significance is less generally recognized. 

The situation thus created was only the outward expression of 
the inward difficulty of the Reformation Churches. They had an 
extremely high, almost Utopian ethical ideal. They had renounced 
the Catholic system of stages, and had given up the hierarchical 
authoritative direction of souls, but their great desire was to pene- 
trate the whole mass of the population equally with the miracle 
of the strict Christian ethic of love, and thus to make the life of 
the world the direct organ of the love which religion inspires. 
Lutheranism hoped to achieve this object entirely idealistically, 
purely through confidence in the miraculous power of the Word ; 
Calvinism, more practically, hoped to attain the same end by 
means of an apparatus of control, based upon Scripture, and 
founded by God. It is not surprising that this extreme idealism 
was grievously disappointed, and that this practical reform did 
not*succeed. In contrast with Catholicism the ideal was universal- 
ized, deepened, and intensified, and Catholic methods of com- 
pulsion were renounced. Thus, within the sphere of Lutheranism 
in particular, a process of practical demoralization set in, which 
was freely admitted by Luther and his companions ; down to the 
present day Catholic controversialists make great capital out of 
this fact . 442 Above all, it furnished the Baptist opposition parties 
with plenty of material for criticism. Even in Geneva Calvinism 
was unable to hold out for more than half a century at its highest 
level. The deterioration of the Calvinist ideal is clearly visible in 
that Puritanism which sank to the level of a self-righteous piety, 
regarding material prosperity as the Divine reward of orthodoxy. 

The more that practical and ethical achievement fell away from 
the ideal, however, the more the churches, in true ecclesiastical 

448 See p. 952. 



698 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

fashion, concentrated upon the objective possession of salvation, 
upon the Divine endowment which is entirely independent of a 
righteousness achieved by good works. In Protestantism this 
Divine endowment meant Scriptural doctrine, and the pre- 
dominant position of the pure message in the ministry of the 
Word. Thus the Protestant Churches fell a prey to an orthodoxy, 
which, with its limitation to “the Word”, “pure doctrine”, and 
the confession of faith, was much narrower and severer than 
Catholic orthodoxy, which, indeed, finds salvation, not only in 
correct dogmas, but in worship and in mystical devotion, that is, 
in non-dogmatic imaginative elements. This emphasis on ortho- 
doxy also led to a closer relationship with the civil authority, 
which alone could secure, at least outwardly, the supremacy of 
the true faith. This relation between the Protestant Church and 
the civil authority naturally resulted in the whittling down of the 
subtle Lutheran distinction between the real Christian ethic of love 
and the secular ethic of Natural Law, till it was almost entirely 
obliterated; this, of course, meant that morality itself became 
secularized . 443 The problem of the relation of the Christian 
ethic to war, authority, force, and law was soon no longer felt. 
On the contrary, men boasted that it was one of the advantages 
of the pure Reformed doctrine that it provided scope and a 
Divine sanction for all these things, which would not be counten- 
anced by monks or fanatics, with the natural assent of all the 
opponents of Christ. 

It was at this point that the Anabaptist movement arose. It 
attacked the new theological dogmatism, the compulsory State 
Church, and the tendency to secularization . 444 As a movement it 
throve on opposition; it laid particular emphasis upon certain 
elements which had originally formed part of the spiritual ideal 
of the Reformers, which, however, under the stress of circum- 
stances, had become merged in the idea of a national Church 
which compromises with secular civilization. The Anabaptists 
deliberately opposed the results of this compromise, and in so 
doing they also opposed the whole idea of the Church, and of an 
ecclesiastical civilization. This violent opposition, however, proves 
that in reality it had been caused by the Reformation itself. This 
is also proved by its apocalyptic-eschatological temper, an 
element which we do not find in the earlier evangelical sects. On 

443 The well-known books of Tholuck and Hundtshagen speak very plainly on 
this point. 

444 This point is brought out very plainly and vividly by the testimonies which 
have been collected by Sebastian Franck , Schwenkfeld 9 and Gottfried Arnold . 



PROTESTANTISM 699 

this point the Anabaptist movement was in agreement with 
Luther, who felt that he could only interpret such a collapse of 
the whole ecclesiastical tradition from the point of view of the 
approaching End of the World, and the coming Antichrist, who 
had been proclaimed by prophecy. 

To the Baptists, with their principle of small voluntary com- 
munities, separate from the world, this attitude seemed quite 
natural, for it was only possible to combine the idea of the world- 
wide dominion of Christ with the break-up of Christendom into 
small groups of this kind which separate themselves from the 
degenerate Church of the people, on the assumption that the 
great falling away of the masses, and the gathering up of Christen- 
dom into a small group of believers, prophesied in the Apocalypse, 
had already begun. It was only after these eschatological hopes 
had been raised that certain individual groups proceeded to try 
to erect the Heavenly Jerusalem by force. Further, in the excite- 
ment caused by this expectation, they opened the door to mystical 
and “enthusiastic” influences, which later on were forbidden by 
the pure Baptists of the Mennonite persuasion ; these influences, 
however, were also connected with the excitement created by the 
Reformation, and in many ways they united with the various 
mystical movements which branched off from it. All this was 
alien to the true Waldensian movement, which proves that in the 
Baptist movement we are dealing with a by-product of the 
Reformation, which is closely connected with the Scriptural 
purism and moral earnestness of the Reformation, but whose deep 
inward opposition to the ecclesiastical idea of the Reformers is 
also quite evident. 

It is, however, probable, and even possible, that the wide 
expansion of the Baptist movement was greatly assisted by some 
lingering traces of the influence of the Waldensians and of other 
sects; it is even possible that this fact alone provides the final 
explanation of the growth of this movement. It is quite possible 
also that here and there individual leaders may have been influ- 
enced by traditions of this kind, in ways which we cannot now 
trace . 445 The Reformation, however, and the opposition which 
it aroused, certainly provoked the rise of this movement, and 
helped to shape its course. At bottom, therefore, the whole 
movement belonged to the Reformation. It was caused by the 
Reformation; it appealed to its principles and ideals, and it 
remained in closest touch with it ; Catholicism, on the contrary, 
rejected this Anabaptist tendency entirely. 

445 See p. 953. 



700 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 


Catholic and Protestant Attitude 

TOWARDS THE SECTS 

Thus the history of the Christian Church presents us with this 
strange spectacle, in which the very varied sect-movement, which 
had formed the complement of Catholicism, was almost entirely 
vanquished in the Catholic sphere, and then went over as a whole 
into the Protestant camp. Tridentine Catholicism excluded the 
unlimited possibilities of development which mediaeval Catholi- 
cism had contained ; it became such a rigid centralized organiza- 
tion that sect and fellowship movements could no longer exist 
within its sphere. The motive which led to the formation of sects 
naturally did not disappear suddenly from within Catholicism. 
But they were diverted into the formation of new Orders and 
ecclesiastical confraternities. Thus Tridentine Catholicism of the 
Counter-Reformation experienced a new and brilliant period, 
during which many new Orders were founded; since then, 
however, the sect-impulse within the Catholic Church has died 
out. The Bible was placed under the strict control of the Church, 
and every kind of “fellowship 5 5 group was obliged to submit to 
the ecclesiastical authority . 446 This has been the official Catholic 
position ever since. The only development has been in the direc- 
tion of increased rigidity. 

The Protestant Church, however, with its strong emphasis 
upon the Bible, its lack of hierarchical centralization, and the 
possibility which it contains of continually offering fresh interpre- 
tations of the Scriptures, from that time forward provided a fruitful 
soil for the sect-movement. It is true that at first the Protestant 
Church persecuted and suppressed this movement as cruelly and 
violently as the Catholic Church had done; but the Protestant 
movement was unable to eradicate the principle completely, 
because it contained within itself the elements of this principle. 
Hence new sects arose continually out of the ashes of the perse- 
cuted movements. It is the combination of all these factors which 
explains the peculiarly complicated position of the sect-movement 
in relation to Lutheranism and Calvinism. 

In its austere ideal of detachment from the world, and its 
emphasis upon good works, the sect-type is more adapted to 
Catholicism; for monasticism bears a certain resemblance to it, 
and the monastic life itself, to some extent at least, acknowledges 
the sect-ideal. On the other hand, the sect-type, in its insistence 

448 Cf. Gothein: Staat und Gesellschaft des Zeitalters der Gegenreformation, pp. 139-145 , 
161-176 . 



PROTESTANTISM 701 

on the necessity for judging everything by the standard of the 
Bible, on personal “assurance”, and on ecclesiastical liberty, is 
really more at home within Protestantism. Finally, also the sect- 
type completely accepted the Protestant doctrine of grace and the 
idea of the “calling”. 

At bottom, however, this complicated relationship is not 
difficult to understand. Both in Catholicism and in Protestantism 
the sect-idea arose out of fundamental primitive Christianity, 
but in each case its form of expression was entirely different. 
Catholicism controlled this tendency by allowing it to express 
itself in the formation of new Religious Orders and confraternities, 
and, in the end, it stamped out every trace of an independent sect- 
movement. The Protestant attempt to destroy the sect-movement 
was, however, unsuccessful. At first it merely tolerated its exist- 
ence outside the Protestant Churches, in the form of Dissent. 
Finally, however, in the form of Pietism, it incorporated the 
sect-movement into its own life. 

Catholicism was more pliable and ready to compromise. Just 
as in its graded ethical system it accepted secular civilization, and 
at that particular point in history in the Tridentine Reform 
absorbed the Renaissance most thoroughly, so also in an equally 
adaptable manner it assimilated the sect-idea through its new 
Orders and Confraternities. On the other hand, however, so far 
as it could, it annihilated every sectarian or cultural movement 
which attempted to maintain an independent existence. 

Protestantism was simpler, narrower, and more Scriptural, 
and therefore it rejected both non-ecclesiastical culture and the 
sect-movement. But its unchangeable principle of personal 
otnviction and “assurance”, and its emphasis upon Scriptural 
purity, led it in the end to tolerate the sect-movement as an 
independent phenomenon. The relationship between the two, 
however, was so close and intimate that official Protestantism was 
deeply affected by the influence of the sect-ideal ; this, again, led 
to a wealth of development, compared with which the elastic 
Catholic synthesis seems hard and narrow. 

In the last resort, however, the sect is a phenomenon which 
differs equally from the ecclesiastical spirit of Protestantism and 
of Catholicism. It is an independent branch of Christian thought; 
it is the complement of the Church-type, and it is based upon 
certain elements in the New Testament ideal. The great national 
churches represented both the idea of grace, and that of a 
common spirit which produces individual souls, and thus they 
also assimilated into their own life the presuppositions of civiliza- 



702 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

tion in general. For them the main question was this : how could 
they gain an influence over the masses? Salvation and grace are 
as independent of the measure of subjective realization of strict 
ethical standards as they are pliable in adjusting themselves to 
the institutions of Natural Law, institutions which have become 
necessary through sin, which have a healing and disciplinary 
effect, but they certainly cannot really be called Christian. This 
adaptation to the institutions based on Natural Law turns the 
Christian ethic into a compromise which, in one way or another, 
accepts the world . 447 Thus, from the point of view of their influ- 
ence upon world history, the great national churches formed the 
main expression of Christian thought; they are great historic 
powers, under whose influence the Christian ethic has been 
carried forward and developed. They were the first great result 
of the world mission of the Primitive Church. Once they were 
firmly established, however, they provided both the material and 
the occasion for the play of forces, through which there was 
introduced the critical and hostile element of an individualistic 
form of Christian piety, severely ethical in the Primitive Christian 
sense, which did not believe in a mass religion at all. This criticism, 
however, contained a fundamental element of the genuine ethic 
of Primitive Christianity. Under its influence there arose small 
groups of earnest souls who judged the life of the world by the 
high ethical standard of the Gospel. Their sociological expression 
naturally took the form of a society of persons united by a deep 
common personal conviction, who were entirely opposed to the 
ecclesiastical system, with its inclusive character, and its claim to 
be the sole depository of grace. This development took place within 
all the Christian churches, because in them all, along with the 
Bible, and the endowment of grace, the germ of the sect-type was 
latent. This seed of the sect-type developed along different lines 
within the different churches, but the end attained was the same. 
Within Catholicism its main form of expression was detachment 
from the world, realized in practice on the higher moral level of 
monasticism ; within Protestantism it expressed itself in an indi- 
vidualistic and subjective method of interpreting the Scriptures, 
and in its emphasis upon the attainment of salvation without 
priesthood or hierarchy. There is no doubt that Protestantism has 
proved the more fruitful soil for the growth of the sect-idea. The 
whole course of Protestant development has been accompanied 
by and carried through with the aid of a powerful sect-movement. 
The extraordinary sociological consequences of this development 

447 See p. 953. 



PROTESTANTISM 7 o 3 

of the sect-type within Protestantism have already been shown 
by its influence upon Calvinism, and in this chapter this will 
become still more evident. 

Space forbids me to give a detailed presentation of the sect- 
movement at this point; all I can do is to mention the salient 
features, and to outline the general course of the movement, in 
the same way as this subject was handled in connection with the 
Middle Ages. 

Anabaptists at Zurich, 

and First Extension of the Movement 

The Anabaptist movement broke out in 1525, in Zurich, in 
radical Reform circles, to whom Zwingli’s application of the 
principles of Scripture seemed inadequate. The following were 
its main characteristics : emphasis on Believers’ Baptism, a 
voluntary church, the precepts of the Sermon on the Mount, the 
rejection of the oath, of war, law, and authority, and, finally, the 
most far-reaching mutual material help, and the equality of all 
Church members, the election of elders and preachers by the 
local congregations, and, to a large extent, the unpaid character 
of the pastoral office; these principles were in close agreement 
with the democratic tendencies of the masses. In the main, the 
whole movement sprang from the lower classes ; primarily it was 
recruited from the ranks of the manual labourers, miners, and 
similar groups. Its leaders were mostly trained pastors, whose 
main concern at first was with the literal application of the Word 
to existing conditions, and with questions of Church discipline. 
As.time went on, however, they learned how to appeal to the 
democratic instincts of the masses. 

The first demands of the peasants were moderate enough, and 
(probably quite rightly) they have been connected with their 
doctrines, in so far as they referred to the restoration of the law 
of Christ and of the apostolic Church. The later radicalism of the 
Peasants’ Revolt, however, was connected with the Hussite and 
Taborite ideas of the absolute law of God and of Nature, and not 
with the ideas of the persecuted Baptists. 448 The moderate Baptists, 
however, who suffered patiently for their convictions, constituted 

448 On this point look up the article entitled Bauernkneg by Sommerlad in Schiele s 
Lexikon . He rightly emphasizes the Natural Law in its absolute Taborite 
significance and connects the radical demands with Hussitism. Tx*e moderate 
early demands of the Twelve Articles are connected by Berens: The Digger 
Movement with the Anabaptist movement ; Stolze: Z ur Vorgeschichte des Bauer nr 
krieges, igo8, calls the Baptist Hubmeier one of the authors. 



704 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OP THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

the main body of the movement. Rioting and violence had no 
place in their programme. It was only the Moravian groups, 
under the leadership of Hut, which practised communism, 
refused to recognize any “man-made law”, and abandoned 
themselves to a Chiliasm of the Joachimite type. 

From Zurich the movement spread with great swiftness and 
intensity : everywhere it attracted to itself all who were dissatisfied 
with the Reformation, as well as a remnant formed of members of 
the earlier mediaeval evangelical groups. The whole of Central 
Europe was soon covered with a network of Anabaptist communi- 
ties, loosely connected with each other, who all practised a strictly 
Scriptural form of worship. The chief centres were in Augsburg, 
Moravia, and Strassburg, and, later on, in Friesland and the 
Netherlands. 

The whole movement was an early premature triumph of the 
sectarian principles of the Free Churches. 

This whole principle, however — apart from the Anabaptists’ 
objection to all forms of official connection with government and 
the administration of justice — was so harshly opposed to the 
still dominant mediaeval idea of a social order expressed in a 
State Church that Catholics and Protestants alike could see in it 
nothing less than the destruction of the very basis of Society itself. 
Hence the response of the official Churches to the movement was 
a horrible and sanguinary persecution. First of all, the leaders of 
the movement were taken and put to death. Some were burned 
alive ; some were slain by the sword ; others were drowned. Then 
came the turn of the masses, who were decimated with savage 
cruelty. 449 

Before 1526, while the ecclesiastical conditions in some places 
were still most unsettled, individual Baptist groups began to 
organize their own religious system on an independent basis ; with 
all the unlimited possibilities of ecclesiastical organization which 
seemed to be opening out in many directions, it looked as though 
there were a sphere and a future for the Anabaptist movement. 
For that very reason, however, the ecclesiastical authorities 
brought this provisional period to an end as quickly as possible; 
they resolutely manufactured an ecclesiastical unity from above, 
since it did not arise spontaneously from below, through the 
power of the Spirit. Only where a positive organization of this 

449 Cf. the negotiations of Philip of Hess about the policy to be adopted with 
regard to the Anabaptists in Hochkuth: £./. hist . Theol. Only the Landgrave is 
in favour of a relatively humane policy, but he cannot carry it through against 
the men of order who want to “preserve the State and Society”. 



PROTESTANTISM 705 

kind was still impossible, as, for instance, in the Netherlands 
before 1572, did the Baptist movement prolong its existence. Here 
it finally attained a permanent, though limited, possibility of life. 
Everywhere else persecution was dominant. This terrible pressure 
of persecution then drove the Baptist communities into an excited 
Revivalism and Chiliasm, and thus some fanatics in the Nether- 
lands (just as the Taborites had done at an earlier date), came to 
the conclusion that the Last Days were at hand, and that they 
were justified in attempting to set up the Heavenly Jerusalem by 
force. They based their argument upon the example of the Old 
Testament and the Apocalypse. This led to the horrors of Munster, 
which was a disaster for the whole movement, and only made their 
persecutors feel still more sure that their oppressive attitude was 
justifiable and right. 

The Mennonites 

Out of the confusion which ensued, Menno Simons gathered the 
Anabaptists into a peaceful evangelical community; he excluded 
the Taborite-Joachimite type of fanatic, and gave the leading 
position in the movement to the Zurich section, which had been 
in the majority from the outset ; at the same time he appealed to 
the example of the mediaeval evangelical sects. The following 
were to be the general lines of organization : each group was to be 
controlled by the spirit of the Sermon on the Mount, with power 
to excommunicate and discipline its members ; Church members 
were all to be considered equal; the leaders in the community 
were to be openly elected to office, otherwise remaining in civil 
life. The taking of oaths, participation in war and in the adminis- 
tration of justice, were still forbidden. Great stress was laid on 
separation from all non-Baptist Christians ; this went so far as to 
demand that a marriage should be dissolved in which the husband 
or the wife had been either excommunicated or convicted of 
unbelief. 

Conditions in the Netherlands, where each individual State 
organized its Church system independently, and on different lines, 
gave the Mennonite Baptists the right to a bare existence, although 
they had no civil rights, and had to endure much oppressive 
treatment from orthodox Calvinism. Finally, under the influence 
of the surrounding Calvinism, to an even greater extent they have 
adopted the Protestant ethic of the “calling”, and from this stand- 
point they have learned, not merely to tolerate the State, law 
and public life, but they themselves have become part of its life. 
In time of war they made their contribution to the State through 

VOL. 11. R 



706 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

the taxes, and in return they were granted full civil rights. They 
became bourgeois, prosperous, and wealthy. When, after 1650, 
the radical element reappeared, they rightly condemned these 
Baptists for compromising with the world. 450 

Even then, however, the Baptist movement was unable to create 
a uniform organization. It split up into various Free Church 
groups, large and small. The Baptists of Friesland and Waterland 
were inclined to assert the independence of the individual congre- 
gation ; they also laid a good deal of emphasis upon individual 
freedom in general. This attitude was opposed to the spirit of 
those groups which were administratively centralized, and which 
exercised a strict Church discipline. From this centre the spirit of 
independence spread through the whole Baptist movement, till at 
last it either did away altogether with the system of Church 
government by a supreme Board of Elders, or, at least, it limited 
their powers to such an extent that, in the end, they became merely 
nominal. 451 

English Baptists, and the 
Rise of the General Baptists 

The next important development of the Baptist movement took 
place in England. It had been introduced into that country about 
the year 1530 by the masses of Dutch emigrants who joined forces 
with the aftermath of the Lollard movement. At first they were of 
the Chiliastic Hofmann type, but later on they became Mennon- 
ites. Here also they were cruelly persecuted as “Separatists” and 
enemies of the social order. In spite of all these difficulties, how- 
ever, they maintained their existence until the period of the 
English Revolution, when we shall hear more about them. 

On the other hand, from England there went forth influences 
which helped to draw Pietistic Calvinism into closer contact with 
the Baptist movement. We have seen already that the same 
phenomenon occurred in connection with Congregationalism, 
but in this instance the contact was far closer. About 1602 a 
certain John Smyth founded a Congregational church at Gains- 
borough ; it was from this congregation that there arose the great 
Church of the General Baptists, which to-day has spread into 

450 See p. 953. 

451 Ten Cate , Gemeente of oudsten souverein? Doopgezinde Bijdragen , 46, 1906, pp. 141- 
151 : “Bij een karakteristiek van de innerlijke ontwikkeling der gemeenten van 
hun ortstaan c. 1650, mag deze trek van overgang der suvereiniteit uit de 
handen der oudsten in die der gemeente niet worden vergeten : De oudsten 
verloren hunne macht en te gemeende ontwikkelde zich tot een geheel 
democratische independente ins telling” (p. 5/). 



PROTESTANTISM 


707 

many parts of the world. At first the basis was Puritan and 
Calvinistic; but while Browne and Robinson developed their 
Congregationalism on very similar lines to the Independency of 
the Baptists, without accepting the specific Baptist doctrines, 
Smyth, who took his congregation to Amsterdam, and settled 
there as a Refugee Church, was drawn farther and farther into 
the Baptist way of thinking. Finally he acknowledged Believers’ 
Baptism as the logical result of Separatism and the “holy com- 
munity”. He baptized himself, and then the members of his 
church, and thus re-established the church as a Baptist congrega- 
tion. Then he openly declared his connection with the Baptists 
and the Mennonites, and joined that body. One section of his con- 
gregation, in spite of a fraternal relationship with the Mennonites, 
did not agree to the fusion of the two elements and, under the 
guidance of Helwys and Murton, its members returned to England 
in 1611. It was there that their church became the mother of 
the great Church of the General Baptists. The main features of 
this Church are these: it rejects the doctrine of predestination, 
demands separation between Church and State, establishes 
Church fellowship upon a voluntary basis, ethical and spiritual 
fitness, and upon baptism by immersion; it renounces the dog- 
matic errors of the early Baptists, permits its members to swear in 
a court of law, to take part in war, and to take official positions 
under the State for the purposes of citizenship ; it rejects com- 
munism, and desires to be a corporation which includes all 
classes without any social distinctions whatsoever. 452 Otherwise 
this Church maintained its connection with the Baptists of the 
Reformation period, although, on account of their historic origin 
and their permanent environment, they became strongly impreg- 
nated with the spirit of Calvinism. Throughout the confused 
period of the English Revolution they maintained a precarious 
existence ; since then, in England, America, and on the Continent, 
they have developed into a large body. 453 In reality all that they 
have retained of the original Baptist spirit is the Free Church 
principle of membership on a voluntary basis, and the require- 
ments of moral discipline; otherwise, however, they have gone 
far beyond Menno Simons, and have accepted the general Pro- 

482 Newman, p. 392. For “spiritualist” features in Smyth’s original programme, 
and which the original Congregationalists with whom he was closely connected 
decidedly rejected, see Barclay , 106-109 ; such features are always more likely 
to occur among the Baptists than among people who wield dogmatic authority. 
Yet he desired to be connected with the external Word as the means of th£ 
Spirit, the affirmation of the moral law of the Bible, and strict order in the 
Church, 458 See p. 953. 



708 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

testant ethic of “the calling”, together with the recognition of 
the State, of law, and of economic life. They have thus severed 
their exclusive connection with the lower classes and have gained 
adherents from the most varied ranks of Society. To-day it is more 
accurate to speak of Baptist “Free Churches” than of Baptist 
“sects”. The persecuted Baptist movement with its patience and 
hope, in ways which had already been prepared by Menno 
Simons, thus made its peace with the world, very much along the 
same lines as the Protestant churches of other confessions had 
done. The only original elements which remained were: the 
voluntary principle of Church membership, a strict morality, and 
a very thorough individualism, which — like the individualism of 
the Congregationalists and Independents (which had been pro- 
duced by Calvinism) with which it was closely related in religion, 
and also in positive historical ways — affected the whole of the 
political and social life of America, as well as that of the English 
middle classes, and united itself also with other impulses which 
were moving in this direction. 

The radical Baptist element, however, had not died out. It 
renewed its vigour at the time of the English Revolution. In an 
earlier section of this book we have seen how Congregationalists 
imitated the Baptists in their Church constitution, and how the 
Cromwellian Puritans and Independents, with their enthusiasm 
for lay-preaching and their aloofness from Church organization, 
also represented Baptist principles; all these factors then united, 
to the advantage of the Baptists and the Quakers among others. 
The chief characteristics of these Independents, however, were a 
greater emphasis upon the more spiritual and Pietist elements on 
the one hand, and, on the other hand, upon the Calvinist, Puritan, 
and theocratic elements. The peculiar feature of this Cromwellian 
Independency consisted precisely in that union of the toleration 
of a free Protestant Church organization, with a strict surveillance 
of Christian morals, combined with the right to carry on a Holy 
War for the cause of God, and with the inauguration of a Christian- 
civic commonwealth. Its connection with the Baptist movement 
lay rather in the Baptist ideals which were generally accepted by 
Calvinism, and in the explicit freedom of Church organization 
than in the characteristic Baptist radicalism of a new building 
up of the Kingdom of God upon the ruins of secular and civil 
organization. The radical Baptist spirit, however, was very much 
alive in Harrison and his followers, and it was increased by the 
newly revived Chiliasm. 

In the army, Harrison’s regiment formed the real focus for the 



PROTESTANTISM 709 

sectarians, while Cromwell’s regiments were the seat of Puritanism. 
In the Barebones Parliament, moreover, Harrison and his followers 
wanted to set aside all law and all courts of law, in order to 
prepare a people, freed from all secular ties, for the Advent of 
Christ; indeed, many of them attacked the idea of private pro- 
perty, and they wished to break up the Church organization 
altogether by abolishing its financial foundation— -the tithing 
system ; all earthly authority was to be destroyed in order to make 
room for the Heavenly King and the coming Kingdom of God. 
It is difficult to judge to what extent these ideas were accepted by 
the nation and by the army, and how far they are a real link 
with the original Baptist and Sectarian radicalism. At any rate, 
we know that the literature of the early Baptists was widely read. 
In his Holy War no less a person than Bunyan had before his 
eyes the ideal of Munster, while his Pilgrim's Pt ogress is connected 
with the story of Tobias in the Wanderings of Hendrik Niclaes . 

In the Barebones Parliament both groups came into conflict, and 
the dissolution of the Parliament of “saints” was the expression 
of the painful separation of Cromwell from his old companions. 
This radical sectarianism finally made it impossible for the work 
of Parliament to continue, although otherwise it had rendered 
signal public service by earnest political work. It split into two 
groups: a moderate majority for Cromwell, and a fanatically 
advanced minority for Harrison; it therefore resigned its com- 
mission into Cromwell’s hands. From that time forward the 
radical “saints” were the opponents of Cromwell; they threw in 
their lot with the popular democratic movements, which, in this 
general breakdown of previous conditions, now came to the fore. 
This turn of events, however, threw the republic between the 
Scylla of dictatorial authority and the Charybdis of doctrinaire 
fanaticism. Men of energy and political responsibility like General 
Monk did not hesitate about their course of action ; they decided 
to join the moderate party, under Cromwell, and, as usually 
happens, the masses followed suit. This ended the last great period 
of Baptist revolt, which, however, had only been able to reach 
this point in the wake of the Independent movement, which was 
more Puritan than Baptist in its outlook. This advanced sectarian- 
ism was the last politically important wave of Chiliasm, the last 
return of the spirit of the Hussites and of the Peasants’ Wars, the 
last attempt by Christian social reformers to prepare the way for 
the Kingdom of God in the world by means of the sword . 454 


454 See p. 953. 



7io THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 


Radical Baptists and the 

English Revolution: the “Levellers” 

In the last years of the Civil War, and above all after Cromweirs 
“apostasy”, certain groups emerged which bore Baptist character- 
istics with the addition of some peculiarities of their own. In the 
unsettled state of affairs, and in the widespread attitude of 
“spiritual” indifference to forms of worship and to organization, 
there were now no longer any groups with particular forms of 
worship; these groups had all become politico-social parties; 
they, however, display all the more plainly the politico-social 
conclusions drawn from the religious idea as such. The largest and 
most important group was that of the “Levellers”. These men 
had strong political interests, and set themselves in opposition 
to the leaders of the army, but they also based their claims on 
religious grounds. They represent that current of thought which 
believes in the radical Law of Nature, of God, and of Christ, 
which will allow no compromise with the institutions corrupted by 
sin, but which desires to realize the Christian social and political 
ideal throughout Society, from top to bottom. Their leader, 
John Lilburn, came from Puritan circles ; he had been a victim 
of the Star Chamber and an exile in Holland, and later an officer 
in the Parliamentarian army. He then fell out with the Parliament, 
inflamed the army by his agitation, and induced the soldiers to 
assent to the famous proposals to the Commons and to Parliament 
which are known as the Agreements of the People. The leading 
feature of this movement was the demand for complete separation 
between Church and State, deduced logically from the standpbint 
of a “Spiritual” Christianity, and the division of the Church into 
free, self-supporting ^congregations ; it also included the ideal of a 
radical democracy, based on the facts of Christian equality and the 
freedom of the redeemed. The demand was not for equality in 
possessions, but for full equality before the law, and for a real 
share of the whole people, so far as it is really Christian and 
religious, in the work of government; it was also felt that the 
system of law needed to be simplified, and the practice of capital 
punishment restricted. In this sense Jesus was the first “Leveller”. 
Forced back by the opposition of the generals, and finally by the 
Protectorate of Cromwell, they became a passionately hostile 
opposition partly, which did not hesitate to encourage con- 
spiracies and attempts at assassination, and even union with 
the Royalists, until finally they were forcibly suppressed. John 



PROTESTANTISM 7 n 

Lilburn himself ultimately found a refuge in the quiet haven of 
Quakerism . 455 

The “Diggers” 

The Socialists and Communists of the Revolution were much 
less influential. While the “Levellers” based their arguments for 
political freedom on religious premises, in the common interest 
of the radical middle class and of the workers, these socialist 
groups represented the interests of the rural proletariat, which 
also hoped to gain its rights and a reward for its sacrifices in the 
Civil War by means of the Kingdom of the “Saints”. The move- 
ment did not spread beyond the agricultural workers, for, at that 
period, there was scarcely an industrial proletariat worth the 
name. They called themselves the “Diggers”; they formed a 
small group organized on communistic lines, and held that it 
was their Christian duty to place common land and crown pro- 
perty under spade and ploughshare. 

Their spokesman was Gerard Winstanley, from whom there 
has come down a pamphlet dedicated to Cromwell, and entitled 
The Law of Freedom , which contains a programme of Christian 
Social Reform. Many of his other writings have also been pre- 
served. Originally Winstanley had been a purely “spiritual” 
man on the lines of Hans Denk, Sebastian Franck, and the 
Familists. But this Christian-Social ideal, which he upheld as 
the logical result of this spirituality of the Inner Light and of the 
Indwelling Eternal Christ, which is in harmony with the creative 
Divine Reason, is the ancient sect-ideal of the Absolute Natural 
Law, as it was before the Fall, the ideal of freedom, equality, and 
brofherhood, which only recognized the use of law, force, and 
dominion in so far as those things are permitted by the full 
consent of all the individual members of Society, and as they 
freely serve the common good. All historic law which goes beyond 
that, all that the Church and the monarchical and aristocratic 
principle exalt as the relative Natural Law, which has been 
instituted by the Fall, is a product of the flesh, of selfishness and 
externalism ; it has only been glossed over with complicated argu- 
ments, by the false theology of priests and professors in the 
interests of a particular class. Christ, the Inner Light, Reason, the 
absolute Natural Law : it all means the same thing. The victory 
of Christ, now, in England, means that a new era has begun; and 
this message ought to be carried over to the Continent as well. 

This Christian Natural Law is to be carried through, first of all, 

485 See p. 955. 



712 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

by the cession of the common land, and of the estates which have 
no masters, to be worked by the poor and needy as a communistic 
experiment. The family and the private household are to be re- 
tained. The whole scheme is to be realized without the use offeree. 

The “older brethren”, as they called the landowners and 
capitalists, are to remain in possession of their property and 
income ; only the land which has become free shall be entrusted to 
the “younger brethren”, i.e. to those who have no capital. The 
Spirit must then carry through the new order Himself. Winstanley 
conceived this new order as an absolutely democratic society, to be 
ruled by elected officials changing every year, from which he 
excluded money, hire, and the exploitation of labour. The 
example of the law of Israel, spiritually interpreted, was in 
his mind throughout. Finally, he placed this choice before 
Cromwell : either to set up the new order and thus to remain a 
true Christian, or merely to continue the old order under a new 
name, and in so doing to betray the indwelling Christ. 

Winstanley’s ideas form an anticipation of theories on the 
subject of property, similar to those propounded by Locke at a 
later period, and they foreshadow a reform of the land laws like 
that of Henry George to-day. At first, however, these ideas had 
no effect at all, since the next development was in the exactly 
opposite direction, and brought about the break-up of property 
held in common, and the dispossession of the free peasants in 
favour of the Enclosures. 

Shortly after Winstanley’s death, there appeared in London in 
the year 1659 two pamphlets by a Dutchman, Peter Cornelius 
Plockboy, who belonged to the moderate Baptist movement. 
Stimulated by the Moravian Baptists, and perhaps also by* the 
Labadists, he drew up a programme for a co-operative society 
on Christian principles, organized in the grand style; in this he 
hoped to force the bourgeois element to imitate him. We do not 
know whether these ideas bore any practical fruit or not. Win- 
stanley’s ideas, however, influenced the Quaker Bcllers; he in 
turn influenced Richard Owen ; thus there is a direct connection 
between Winstanley and modern Socialism. He himself, however, 
disillusioned in the same way as Lilburn, finally found a home 
among the Quakers, together with many of his followers. 456 

The Millennarians 

The closest connection with the radical Baptist movement was 
maintained by the Millennarians. This party taught that the four 

456 See p. 956. 



PROTESTANTISM 


7i3 

world-empires of the Book of Daniel, familiar to students of the 
ecclesiastical philosophy of history, covered the whole intervening 
period, down to the Protectorate of Cromwell; when it broke 
down they expected the Fifth World Empire of the full dominion 
of Christ. They looked for the Advent of Christ, and for the 
setting up of the true Kingdom of the “Saints”, without priest or 
sacrament, law or oath, king or government, for the kingdom of 
the complete Christian anarchy of love. Some waited for this 
future in quiet patience, and endured the world ; others, like the 
Taborites and Mtinsterites, became violent revolutionaries. 

The genuine religious fanatics belonged to this section. Their 
spirit dominated the Left Wing of the Barebones Parliament, and 
made it impossible for Cromwell to govern through it. They were 
a real danger to the Protectorate. A smaller group composed of 
quieter people, split off from the main body of the party. This 
section was led by a certain John Pordage, who adopted mystical 
and ascetic ideas. In his teaching, the “Kingdom of the Saints” 
was spiritualized into a Philadelphian society, very much on the 
lines of the later Quakers and the Labadists. Many, however, 
maintained an attitude of bitter hostility to Cromwell. 

The radical Baptists were closely connected with the Millen- 
narians. They were strongly represented in the Irish Army, and 
they greatly desired to choose an Anabaptist general to lead 
them; in the end Monk cleared them all out of the Army. At the 
Restoration, these Chiliasts were the only people who could not 
accept the new order, or who went over to the Pietistic groups. 
They made an attempt at resistance which was defeated with 
bloodshed. Their leader, Harrison, died in the conviction that 
he would soon come again at the right Hand of Christ, at the 
setting up of His Kingdom. From that time forward the revolu- 
tionary Baptist movement was over . 457 

The other religious groups which arose during the Revolution 
belonged to the mystical spiritual movement, and will be men- 
tioned later in that connection. The Quaker sect, however, in 
which all these religious tendencies finally merged, was a curious 
blend of sectarianism and spiritual religion. For that reason it also 
will be described later. 

In this section I only wish to emphasize the sectarian element 
which played a very distinct part in the Great Rebellion, in the 
same way as in the previous chapter I was obliged to lay stress 
on the Scottish and Huguenot element within Calvinism. All 
that went beyond the sectarian element which I have just described 
457 For the Fifth Monarchy men, see Gooch , 260-267 , 324 and Glass. 



714 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

belonged to the sphere where fanaticism was rife. These move- 
ments were characterized by mystical ideas and experiences, a 
great belief in “spiritual religion”, and, above all, by that “ad- 
vanced” interpretation of the Law of Nature which belongs to 
the aggressive Chiliasm of the Anabaptist movement. This last 
element in the extremely complicated movement belongs to the 
subject of our present inquiry. It was not the dominant factor, but 
it left abiding traces of its influence. Here, as always, the first result 
of idealistic radicalism was merely to prepare the way for reaction. 
Nevertheless the movement had a permanent influence. Indirectly, 
through its connection with Puritan Independency, and directly, 
through these radical groups, it was the influence of the Baptist 
movement which helped to loosen the connection between 
Church and State, which made the formation of Free Churches 
possible, and which helped to Christianize the ethical and social 
interests of the English people apart from dogmatic compulsion. 

All this took place in an atmosphere of Utopian fanaticism, but 
in the next generation it became a moderate political and eco- 
nomic programme. It was the last time that a political and social 
revolution was carried through in the name of Christ, but it was 
to these Christian ideas that it owed a great part of its power, 
and only through them has it been introduced, in its secularized 
form, into the modern world. Here we see very clearly the 
significance of the Christian outlook on life, expressed in the 
terms of the sect-type, not merely in the history of the Church 
and of religion, but also in the sphere of political and social 
questions . 458 

Pietism 

The sectarian energies which were released in the English 
Revolution were connected with the Pietist and Puritan form of 
English Calvinism. As we have already seen, this element was 
also one of the factors in Continental Calvinism. Although this 
movement had a quieter and less eventful history than its English 
counterpart, it too had its Left Wing, which developed here and 
there into sects of the extremist type ; the whole movement also 
spread into Lutheranism. At this point it is customary to gather 
up all these phenomena under the term “Pietism”. 

Generally speaking, Pietism simply represents the sect-ideal 
within the churches, restricted and controlled by the fundamental 
thought of the Church. It reappears continually throughout the 
history of the Church. Its characteristics do not vary: always 

458 See p. 956. 



PROTESTANTISM 


7i5 

there is the same insistence on the New Testament law of morals 
and on the idea of the Kingdom of God, and the same opposition 
to all externalism in the ecclesiastical sacramental system. In this 
sense, like the sect-ideal itself, Pietism belongs to all the churches. 
At that time (i.e. the seventeenth century), for similar reasons, 
Catholicism also had its own Pietist movement in the shape of 
Jansenism. But Catholicism can only tolerate that kind of move- 
ment if it is properly controlled by the Church as an Order or a 
Confraternity, so Jansenism was completely crushed. The corre- 
sponding movements within Calvinism we know already as 
Puritanism and “Precisianism”. 

Pietism, however, did not remain within the churches; every- 
where it took the further step which led to separation and to the 
formation of sects. In the Netherlands this sectarian development 
began with Labadism ; in England its new phase of development 
was ushered in by Methodism. The same phenomena also ap- 
peared within Lutheranism; and they came into touch with 
Calvinistic movements of the same kind; this intercourse has 
gradually become more intimate and vital, and is still a real 
force at the present day. In this later English and Continental 
Pietism, however, the whole movement does not come to a head 
in a process which influences the history of the world — the 
destruction of an old system of government and the erection of a 
new system — as was the case in the English Revolution. In that 
particular instance the religious movement was set, by the course 
of events, at the very heart of the political and social conflict; 
that explains the overwhelming force of an upheaval in which a 
Christian nation actually beheaded a king. 

Continental Pietism was not connected with any great events 
of this time. That is why it remains, especially in Germany, more 
of a party matter — almost a hole-and-corner affair — which is 
limited to theological and ecclesiastical circles, and becomes, in 
the main, tame and colourless. It is true that it displays a great 
deal of genuine, warm, and self-sacrificing piety, but it also displays 
that pettiness of religious groups which compensates for their 
detachment from the world by a still more thorough spiritual 
pride ; affecting to despise worldly influence, they strive to attain 
it by personal scheming and intrigue, and they give vent to their 
passions in all kinds of religious bickerings, thus revealing exactly 
the same characteristics as the darker side of the Baptist move- 
ment. 

In Germany, when the country had recovered from the Thirty 
Years War, there arose a reaction against the popular religion 



7x6 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

of the Territorial Churches, which had become formal in their 
officialism and rigid in their orthodoxy, while morally they were 
far too indifferent. The leader of this movement was Spener, 
who, in addition to his emphasis upon Luther’s earlier idea of 
forming small groups of “earnest Christians” within the Church 
at large, had also been deeply influenced by the Pietism of 
England and Holland. 

One of his main innovations was the introduction of the con- 
venticle system which he had seen at work in England and in 
Holland. By this method he hoped to achieve that spiritual and 
ethical reform of the Church which was needed as the complement 
of the reform in doctrine which had already been carried out so 
thoroughly. It was his intention, however, to keep this movement 
entirely within the life of the Church. But its “Perfectionist” aim 
of separating “converted” Christians, that is, of mature and 
conscious Christians, from the rest, in order to form them into 
smaller groups of real Christians, its stress on the need for “con- 
verted” preachers, its emphasis upon lay religion and upon the 
pure apostolic primitive Church, revealed a spirit which was still 
inwardly hostile to the spirit of ecclesiasticism. Spener also held 
that the greatest impulse towards reform lay in the idea of the 
coming Kingdom of God, and the approaching world trans- 
formation. 

The ethical point of view which was developed from this belief, 
of an asceticism active within the sphere of one’s calling, but 
detaching itself from the world, and a rational methodical 
discipline of self-consecration in preparation for the future life, 
stood in direct opposition to the Lutheran ethic of moral neutral- 
ity, tolerance, and the free outworking of the Spirit. In spite of 
the fact that it accepted the doctrines of the Church, the Sacra- 
ment, and the Territorial Church system, the affinity between 
Pietism and the spirit of the sects is evident. Its opponents cer- 
tainly emphasized this fact often enough, for they constantly 
compared Pietism with the Anabaptist movement, with the 
followers of Valentine Weigel, the Rosicrucians, and the Quakers. 
The driving force in this movement was clearly akin to those 
sects. The opponents of Pietism, however, would not see, or at 
least they would not admit, that their own Church system really 
contained certain affinities with the sects. Pietism was based, and 
rightly so, upon the Bible, and upon Luther’s earlier ideals, 
and it was forced into existence by the formalism of the State 
Church system. Its attitude towards the world and towards 
civilization was still only the logical inference from Luther’s 



PROTESTANTISM 717 

doctrine of Original Sin and conversion, which prevailed as soon 
as the Lutheran doctrine of Baptism, and its freer but ill-defined 
attitude towards the world, was less emphasized. Also its imitation 
of the Calvinistic conventicle, and the connection with Calvinistic 
asceticism and moral discipline, was no mere casual, foreign 
influence of Calvinism, but an appropriation of the means, already 
closely related, which had been evolved for similar reasons, and 
which were to lift the German movement out of its distress. 

In addition, all the other logically connected phenomena of this 
sectarian ascetic spirit were also introduced : the emphasis upon 
the co-operation of the laity ; the independent study of the Bible 
without ecclesiastical control of exegesis ; depreciation of the State 
Church and of the “ subsidia ” religionis ; the demand for the right 
to excommunicate and to exercise Church discipline as an 
activity of the Church, and not merely as a function of the police ; 
the impulse towards personal and experimental religion; the 
reduction of all secular culture to the elements which were 
practically useful, and the entire rejection of philosophy and 
theology; the evangelizing and educating of baptized but not 
really “converted” children; the introduction of confirmation 
in place of adult baptism ; the new Pietistic Church order of joint 
ministry, which assumed that the Church began with the gather- 
ing together of individuals in groups, but which at the same time 
maintained the silent transference of authority over these groups 
to the Government; under these circumstances, for the time 
being, practical results were impossible. In Germany there were 
no large Separatist movements, owing to the fact that, unlike the 
law^of England and the Netherlands, the law of the Empire did 
not permit them. 

Pietism remained within the Church; indeed, at the time of 
the Enlightenment it bound itself very closely with the relics of 
the old dogmatic ecclesiastical system, and from its reawakening 
at the beginning of the nineteenth century there arose the great 
renewal of orthodoxy in this century, through which, however, 
the Church life of the present day has been impregnated with a 
mass of Pietist explosive material. 

To sum up : Pietism represents the sect-ideal within the Church ; 
the mystical elements with which it was mingled will be dealt 
with in a later section of this book. The influence of the Church- 
type upon the sect-ideal is everywhere quite evident ; this appears 
not only in questions of doctrine and organization, but, above all, 
in its attitude towards social questions. Like Puritanism and the 
later Baptist movement, Pietism had no trace of the tendency of 



7 18 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

the sect towards political and social radicalism. It did not need to 
become bourgeois like the early Baptist movement ; from the very 
beginning it was bourgeois and loyal. In the spirit of Lutheranism 
it accepted the existing social order of the State; the idea of 
Christianizing the social order did not occur to it. On the contrary, 
Pietism liked to be connected with the ruling class and with the 
aristocracy; it aimed solely at Christianizing the hearts of men. 
It carried on Home Mission work, and healed social ills by a new 
kind of charity, which depended on free group initiative; no- 
where did it touch the fundamental facts of existing conditions. 

The resemblance between Pietism and the suffering and perse- 
cuted Baptist movement is slight. Pietism expressed asceticism 
and renunciation of the world in the form of the acceptance of 
existing conditions of labour, rather in the sense in which Puritan- 
ism and the later developments of the Mennonite movement had 
expressed it. In this respect Pietism comes into touch with the 
commercial ethic of the Calvinistic churches. Pietism teaches that 
secular business and interests have no intrinsic value of their 
own; the Christian man takes part in them as the “Lord’s 
steward”, simply for the purposes of civil life, and of the “Kingdom 
of God”. Pietism does not seek to reform the world; it simply 
gathers “earnest Christians” together into a party within the 
Church, and seeks to convert the heathen; this all shows how 
indifferent it is to questions of social reform. Its task is simply to 
seek the conversion of individuals, and to gather “converted” 
souls into groups for fellowship and edification. Its interest in the 
release of the third estate, that is, of the laity, is concerned purely 
with the religious and ecclesiastical sphere, and consists in giving 
the right to possess an independent personal piety, and the right 
to form conventicles. 

It is precisely at this point that a characteristic distinction 
appears between German Lutheran and Calvinistic Pietism. 
When Calvinism, which aimed from the very beginning at the 
creation of a “holy community”, came under the influence of 
Pietism, it found its supporters mainly in the lower and middle 
classes, whereas in German Pietism, on the contrary, the lower 
middle classes preferred to become Separatists, and Pietism within 
the Church simply concerned theologians and the aristocracy. 
The Lutheran Church system is, indeed, not inwardly at home in 
Pietism and its ethic, even though the Lutheran doctrines of sin 
and conversion come very close to its spirit. 

Pietism, of course, has produced some notable effects upon the 
development of civilization : under its influence life became more 



PROTESTANTISM 7ig 

personal and inward, social distinctions faded into insignificance, 
and social existence became more humane. On the other hand, 
these very influences often became perverted, owing to the 
Pietists’ tendency to be on good terms with the aristocracy, and 
to form cliques and parties. Pietism is, in fact, a revivalist form of 
Christianity, fitted to meet the needs of small groups, which seeks 
and finds its support in the Territorial Church, while it leaves the 
world and secular civilization severely alone. When it does influ- 
ence civilization at all, particularly on the political and social 
side, it does so reluctantly and almost involuntarily. Here, once 
more, we see the standpoint of the persecuted sect, which here 
comes to terms with the existing organization in Church and 
State. This is why Pietism was comparatively popular with the 
authorities when they had learned — with great difficulty — that 
it was impossible to maintain the old purity of a State religion. 
Pietism supplies the State with loyal servants, who practise sub- 
mission as part of the asceticism of their calling ; it does not seek 
to alter existing conditions; the only obligation it lays on the 
Government is that of patriarchal kindness and care for the com- 
mon weal, and it obliterates class distinctions only within the 
limits of religious intercourse ; indeed, this also did not take place 
to any appreciable extent . 459 

The Moravians 

The fact that in Pietism the sect-ideal is so closely connected 
with the Church explains why the few important Separatist 
movements which took place were not voluntary, but were the 
result of actual compulsion. This is true of the only larger Separa- 
tist ihovement, the Herrnhut Community. Like the Quakers, this 
body was not a simple expression of the sect-idea, even though it 
was connected with the Church. From the very beginning it 
contained various elements. On the one hand, it consisted of the 
Lutheran inwardness of Count Zinzendorf, a man of great per- 
sonal charm and attractiveness, who, in an age of sentimentality, 
seemed like some gallant Crusader of olden days. His aim was to 
unite the true lovers of Christ in small groups, rather after the 
earlier ideal of Luther and Spener’s system of “conventicles”. 
He never dreamed of the impossibility of uniting these supra- 
ecclesiastical Philadelphian groups with Lutheranism. On the 
other hand, the Herrnhut Community contained the sectarian 
impulse of the Moravian Brethren, who, having incidentally 
settled upon the Count’s estate, became to him a “chariot and 

4M See p. 956. 



720 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

warhorse” for gaining the victory; in the process, however, his 
conventicle idea developed into that of a sect, organized on an 
exclusive basis, founded upon the voluntary principle, and upon 
maturity in Christian experience, exercising powers of discipline 
and excommunication — a body in which laymen exercised a 
spiritual ministry. Out of the tension and conflict between these 
two tendencies, and in consequence of the rejection of the Count’s 
“conventicle” idea by the official Lutheran Church, there arose, 
finally, a new Church, which gradually settled down into an 
established existence, with inherited traditions, rather like that of 
the Society of Friends. It had no objection to Infant Baptism, 
but its chief aim was to attain the highest possible degree of 
inward piety and Christ-mysticism, by means of worship, organ- 
ization, and education. Nevertheless, it still retained important 
characteristics of the sect-ideal. The body of communicants was 
to be as pure as possible ; and discipline was directed to this end. 
The small size of the community, its system of mutual control, 
its independence of the State, its legal character as an “associa- 
tion” ( Verein ), its business undertakings which arose in order to 
secure its existence, its urgent desire to win souls freely to Christ 
through missions to the heathen, above all the endeavour after 
an active purity of the Christian ethic which was to distinguish 
its members from the “children of this world” : all this gave to 
the Church of the Brethren — partly with and partly against its 
will — a certain likeness to the sects, which it was in the habit of 
ascribing to the influence of the Bohemian Brethren, and of the 
Waldensians, and through them to the Early Church. Traces of 
an attitude to the Sermon on the Mount similar to that which 
characterized the Baptists are also apparent. Finally, their ethic 
(even though it was imparted and established by the Count in 
the spirit of a happy and childlike Lutheran piety) was com- 
paratively tolerant towards the world, and quite unsystematic; 
on the other hand, however, through its desire to present an 
active Christian piety very different from the life of the world, 
and through Calvinistic accessions to the community, it was, in 
many respects, related to Puritanism. In any case, the Moravians 
felt a closer affinity with Calvinism than with Lutheranism. The 
economic results, too, which were produced by these circum- 
stances soon appeared in the shape of an excellent and increas- 
ingly successful business life, characterized by integrity and 
frugality. This tendency was strengthened by the fact that at 
first the community was gathered from the shifting element in 
the population, and that it became limited essentially to active 



PROTESTANTISM 7 a, 

members who were engaged in trade, and also by the fact of the 
necessity of meeting their own expenses, particularly those con- 
nected with their mission work, which meant that they were, and 
are, forced to depend on the business enterprise of the whole 
community . 460 

The Methodists 

Of much greater importance was the founding of Methodism, 
which was one of the most important events in the later history 
of Christianity, and of modern spiritual development. It marked 
the renewal of orthodox Christianity in a quite individualistic 
accentuated form; it anticipated the continental revival move- 
ment of the nineteenth century, and was one of the means by 
which the English world was rendered proof against the spirit of 
the French Revolution; it presented a radical opposition to the 
whole spirit of modern science and civilization. Methodism, like 
the Moravian Church — by which, indeed, it had been stimulated, 
and for which, like the latter, it had been prepared by a Pietist 
conventicle-movement — was an attempt to leaven the life of the 
National Church with the influence of smaller groups of genuine 
and vital Christians. Externally, it was only forced to take up an 
independent position because the pulpits of the National Church 
were closed to it. Inwardly, however, this separation was in- 
evitable. For this body, like the Moravian Church, belonged 
essentially to the sect-type and not to the church-type, in spite of 
its earnest desire to remain inside the Established Church. 
Indeed, its own nature forced it to adopt a far more independent 
attitude than the Moravian Church had felt necessary from its 
own point of view. For the primary aim of Methodism was not to 
gather devout lovers of Christ into small fellowship groups, but to 
awaken the masses, which, under the influence of an “enlight- 
ened” Church and the pressure of industrial capitalism, had 
become indifferent, dull, and coarse. The movement was already 
faced by the conditions produced by the wide development of 
modern science, and by the social situation, which, on the Con- 
tinent, were only developed in the nineteenth century. The 
Methodist Revival laid renewed and extreme emphasis upon the 
doctrine of Original Sin, and it taught that the way to salvation 
consisted in a direct sense of “assurance”, based on justification 
through the Blood of Christ. Its leaders proclaimed that salvation 
from hell, death, and damnation could not be attained by an inert 
confidence in baptismal grace, nor by a certain measure of decent 

460 See p. 959. 
s 


VOL. II. 



722 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

and correct behaviour, but by a radical change, the conscious 
passing from the state of condemnation to that of forgiveness and 
peace, together with the genuine ethical energies released by this 
experience. 

The results of this Revival, however, which the Methodist 
missionaries carried on amidst dangers and toils like those of the 
first apostles, and which, with the aid of great open-air services, 
they finally carried right into the life of the lower and middle 
classes, had to be secured and gathered up into a coherent whole. 
In order to achieve this end, however, organization was needed ; 
Wesley, who was an indefatigable and indomitable missionary 
like Paul, and a dominating, powerful organizer like Ignatius 
Loyola, was a master in this art. As this process of organization 
went on, the main characteristics of the sect-type, which were 
already present in embryo, began to emerge in the stress laid on 
adult conversion and on ethical Perfectionism. To the emotional 
elements of the direct “sealing of the Spirit” and of “assurance of 
salvation”, in which Methodism comes very near to the spirit 
of the Lutherans and the Moravians, there was added a spirit of 
composure and self-control in which Wesley remained true to 
Puritan Calvinism. 

The aim of Methodism was to win men and women to Christ, 
who would then be genuine Christians, full of “joy and peace in be- 
lieving”, and who, as far as they could, were aspiring to perfection ; 
the means was the gathering of such Christians into an organized 
society. At first, during the original period, the Society consisted 
of adult members who came in from the outside ; the question of 
Infant Baptism did not need to be raised, since all the members 
belonged to the Established Church which dispensed the Sacra- 
ment of Infant Baptism throughout the land. A probation period 
of six months preceded the final reception into the Society. The 
members received their Society ticket, which had to be renewed 
every quarter, and within the Society they were divided up into 
classes of about ten persons, who gathered themselves together 
weekly under a lay leader for mutual fellowship, guidance, and 
Bible study ; the renewed grant of the Society ticket, and the final 
reception of candidates, were dependent upon the leader’s report. 
The groups, again, were gathered together into districts which 
were visited systematically by an ordained pastor ; the latter had 
at the same time the duty of carrying on evangelistic meetings for 
outsiders. The districts, again, were placed under the supreme 
guidance of the General Conference of the famous Hundred, 
which was constituted at first merely by the arbitrary choice of 



PROTESTANTISM 723 

Wesley, then according to seniority and then by the addition of 
elected ministers, and finally also of elected laymen. 

We cannot enlarge any further upon the development of this 
system of Church government, whose main features have remained 
unaltered to the present day. Its general character is clear. It is 
something between an Order, established upon a foundation of 
unconditional obedience and minute mutual control, like the 
Jesuit Order (with which Methodism was compared in its early 
days), and a society of earnest Christians, proving the reality of 
their faith by their lives, founded upon entirely voluntary mem- 
bership in which the members have a permanent share, as in the 
Baptist organizations. 

The two sociological forms of the sect-type, the Religious Order 
and the voluntary association, are here combined; at the same 
time they are made elastic for the reception of increasing numbers, 
without, however, allowing the opposition to the popular piety 
of the church-type to disappear. Infant Baptism is, in reality, 
replaced by the experience of the New Birth, which is connected 
with conversion, and its recognition by admission to the Society. 
Nothing was altered in Church dogma, its supernatural character 
was only intensified, and its general meaning was summed up in 
conversion and its presuppositions, and in sanctification with its 
heavenly results. The continuance of the Church was taken for 
granted, but in spite of that its spirit was denied. This necessarily 
led to external separation, in England itself last of all. 

When this separation and independence had been achieved, 
Methodism passed through the same experience which had be- 
fallen the Baptists, the Moravians, and the Quakers. An inherited 
position was developed in which the children of members naturally 
belonged to the community ; this fact, coupled with the reception 
of increasing numbers of people, who to-day (counting all the 
different branches of Methodism) number about 30 millions, with 
the increase of the clerical element, which was unavoidable under 
these circumstances, and with the introduction of scientific 
theology and general culture, with the many influences which 
modified the original attitude of opposition to the world and to 
civilization, finally led Methodism to become less and less of a 
sect and more and more of a Church, or, rather, a number of 
churches. All that remained of the original sect-spirit was a 
certain sensitiveness about questions of organization, which is 
peculiar to all societies organized on a voluntary basis — a rivalry 
between laymen and ordained pastors, by which (in the various 
denominations) laymen attained an increasing but varying share 



724 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

in the general administration. It was this which led to most of the 
separations and reunions which have taken place. Further, just 
as in the case of the Baptists, the original restriction to certain 
classes of Society disappeared. To begin with, Methodism gained 
its victories in the middle and lower classes, among the miners 
and in the industrial towns. To the middle and lower classes it 
brought a new sense of the sacredness of personality ; it appealed 
to the popular imagination, and awakened a devotion which 
found expression in a most self-sacrificing charity. From the 
aristocratic classes and the rural population, as well as from the 
educated professional classes, it remained, on the whole, remote. 
It had brought the impulse of personality and individuality into 
the life of the masses, who were being brutalized by the industrial 
system, and with its charity it helped them in their distress. 
Otherwise, however, its ethic served to maintain the existing order 
in Church and State ; it balanced the emotional character of its 
type of conversion by emphasis upon sanctification, which was to 
be attained by a severe and rigorous course of self-discipline, and a 
far-reaching practice of asceticism in work. Its attitude towards 
the social problem was displayed in its zeal for franchise reform, 
for the liberation of the slaves, for philanthropic activity, as well 
as in its strict Sabbatarianism, its opposition to modern culture, 
science, and art. In modern Methodism this opposition to culture 
has been modified, but it has not been removed . 461 

The Labadists 

In the Netherlands also, which were influenced by a certain 
type of Puritanism, the sect-movement was present, although it 
did not spread very widely because Rigorism had already been 
allowed a fairly free course in the State churches. There a man 
like Lodensteyn pushed the idea of the purity of Church member- 
ship to such an extreme that the Sacrament of the Lord’s Supper 
could no longer be observed. Others so changed the baptismal 
formula that they did not describe the children as “Christians”, 
but merely as “destined for faith” — both strong proofs of sectarian 
inferences drawn from Puritanism. Labadie alone tried to form a 
sect, and in so doing he influenced others in the Separatist direc- 
tion. This sect was like a monastic order; but since his leading 
idea was not merely the idea of sanctification, but was chiefly 
mystical in character, we will describe this in detail later on. 
Further, this movement declined and disappeared during the first 
generation after it had been founded. In the Netherlands and the 

4M See p. 960. 



PROTESTANTISM 725 

Church of the Lower Rhine, however, it became the rallying- 
point for a marked development of the sectarian spirit . 462 

Modern Sects 

Almost all the sects which have been mentioned are still in 
existence. Many new ones of a similar type have been added — 
the Salvation Army, the Adventists, the Irvingites, the Darbyists, 
the Wurttemburg Temple, and others. Everywhere their activity 
arouses the continental Territorial Churches, and actually within 
them the so-called “Fellowship Movement” constantly produces 
fresh analogies to the origin of those sects. From the point of view 
of social doctrine they all bear the same characteristics : a society 
founded on a voluntary basis apart from the State, Perfectionism, 
asceticism expressed in hard work, a conservative-middle-class 
outlook, even where their political attitude is theoretically one 
of bourgeois Liberalism. These newer sects represent the natural 
development of the persecuted Pietist element (within the 
Church) during a period when the sect is no longer persecuted, 
and when the absolute necessity of civil and social order for the 
immensely complicated economic organism has become clear and 
obvious. With the rise of Capitalism the early ideals of the perse- 
cuted Waldensians and Baptists became impracticable. Hence- 
forth the only course to pursue was : either to oppose Capitalism 
altogether and to propose something entirely new, or, however 
hostile certain groups might be to the world and to civilization 
in general, to adjust themselves to the existing order of Society, 
merely modifying or getting rid of the unchristian phenomena 
which accompany it . 463 

It is this sense of contrast which has reawakened in the modern 
world the old ideas of world-renewal which characterized the 
aggressive sects. These ideas have again come into prominence 
through the Bible, particularly in the Sermon on the Mount, 
and the idea of the Kingdom of God. There has been no recur- 
rence of Hussite Wars, it is true, nor of armies of “saints” ; and at 
the present day the aim of Christian Socialism is no longer 
primarily to attempt a direct transformation of world conditions 
4#2 On this point, see Gobel, II, Ritschl, I, and Heppe. 

4«8 p or modern history of the sects, see “ Kirchen und Sekten der Gegenwai t ” , 
published by Kalbe *, 1907', further, the collection entitled Kerke en Secte , Baarn, 
Hollandia Druckerij . For the so-called “Gemeinschaftsbewegung” , see the article by 
Benser in Schiele’s Lexikon. For the connection with the general life of the people, 
see Tischhauser: Gesch. d.ev. Kirche in derersten Hdlfte des 19. Jahrh.,1900 . These are 
things which the modern educated German knows nothing about, but which 
play an important part in real life. 



726 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

by means of an organized society inspired by a common religious 
aim, and strengthened by united worship. To-day men know or 
feel instinctively far too clearly how complicated are the problems 
of our common life and our common civilization involved in these 
great questions, to attempt anything of this kind. With the rise 
of the great sovereign States which dominate the life of the citizens 
down to the smallest detail, and with the revelation of the nature of 
the Capitalist system, the ideal has naturally changed its emphasis. 

The ideal of the Christian Revolution has become at once more 
spiritual and more complicated. Society in general is now sum- 
moned to a change of heart and disposition under the influence of 
the Gospel, which, with the co-operation of all social-technical 
experts, shall then, and not till then, create a change in the 
general situation which shall harmonize with the ideas of Christian 
personality and of the Kingdom of God. To-day a genuine Christ- 
ian love and sense of the value of personality seems to demand 
expression along the following lines: a break-away in principle 
from the individualistic social order which has grown up during 
the last two centuries ; the equal surrender, not merely of indi- 
viduals, but of all, for the common good ; the creation of just and 
suitable means for a sufficient material existence for all, as a 
basis for the development of spiritual values. 

Thus, in its origin, with Owen and St. Simon, Socialism con- 
tained within itself transformed Christian impulses of this kind. 
By his reference to the Quaker, Bellers, Owen restored the direct 
contact with the sect-ideal. In Germany this point of view was 
represented by Weitling. Since, however, Socialism has finally 
given up all connection with religion, and since the Marxist 
development of the “class-war” idea and its acceptance of* the 
Gospel of Naturalism, there have been no further developments 
in this direction. 

Christian Socialism 

Its place, however, has been taken by Christian Socialism which 
claims to present the demand of the Gospel for brotherhood, and 
the coming of the Kingdom of God in its undimmed clarity and 
uncompromising character, after its eyes had been opened by 
Social Democracy to these inferences drawn from the Gospel. 
Christian Socialism rejects the glorification of the prevailing 
bourgeois order as one which represents a relative Natural Law 
which owes its necessity to the fact of sin, and its character of a 
Divine appointment to the Divine permission. Taught by the 
modern science of the State and of Society, and by the experiences 



PROTESTANTISM 


727 

of everyday life, Christian Socialism sees clearly one thing which 
Calvinism (which was moving steadily in the direction of Christian 
Socialism) did not see : that the possibility of a spiritual and ethical 
development depends entirely upon the substructure of a healthy 
collective social constitution, and that spiritual factors are very 
closely connected with physical and economic factors. Christian 
Socialism has learned from experience that the previous exclusive 
emphasis upon “the ideological 55 aspect of the problem takes us 
nowhere. It is this which constitutes its new element. Christian 
Socialism, therefore, also rejects the Pietistic attitude of with- 
drawal from “the world 55 into a sphere of “spiritual life 55 and 
evangelistic effort, because it implies an attitude of despair 
towards the world, and an attempt to quiet the Christian con- 
science by winning a few souls, many of whom are not of the best. 
In the view of Christian Socialism, to identify the Kingdom of 
God with the Church, or to relegate it to the future life, seems to 
be a position which corresponds neither with the Bible nor with 
the demands of reality, both of which require a sphere on earth 
in which it should be possible to rise above the mere struggle for 
actual existence, and beyond the Gospel of Competition and the 
survival of the fittest. 

In this attitude, however, we perceive once more the familiar 
characteristics of the primitive Christian tendency, the character- 
istics of the aggressive sect which believes in an actual transforma- 
tion of conditions in this world. The Kingdom of God and reason, 
the Kingdom of God realized on earth , the invincible faith in the 
victory of goodness and in the possibility of overcoming every 
human institution which is based upon the mere struggle for 
existence, the Christian Revolution : this is the primitive, splendid 
ideal of the sect. It is only the Chiliast ideal translated into human 
and intelligible terms. It is the ideal of a Christianity without 
compromise, formulated in harmony with modern social views, 
an ideal which could not be conceived within primitive Christ- 
ianity with its faith in the miraculous Second Coming of Christ. 
From the Patristic period the old Christian theories of the nature 
of Society have been handed down through the centuries (with 
changes which have been already described), and these same 
theories still hold good in all communions, and until the present 
day are continually being repeated, with a naive ignorance of the 
world situation, in spite of the wholly altered practical position 
in Christian ethics. Thus Christian Socialism alone has broken 
through these theories, and forced men to think out afresh the 
social ethic of Christianity and its relation to the actual changes 



7*8 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

in the social order. It has laid bare the worm-eaten condition of 
the previous conventional Christian ethic, which, at its best, 
offered something for the ethics of the family and the individual, 
but which, on the other hand, had no message for social ethics 
save that of acceptance of all existing institutions and conditions, 
much to the satisfaction of all in authority. Christian Socialism 
has regained for the Christian ethic its Utopian and revolutionary 
character ; once more it has brought upon its heralds the reproach 
of Christ, which officials of Church and State are always ready to 
hurl at all who indulge in humanitarian sentiment or in idealistic 
dreams, at all who “wantonly deny the impossibility of over- 
coming sin”, and the absolute necessity of their methods of 
suppressing it. 

The fundamental distinctions within the movement, which 
expresses itself very differently among Catholics, Calvinists, 
Lutherans, and Free Protestants, and which, above all, has greatly 
agitated the Lutheran Church, cannot be described here. This 
point alone must be emphasized: with this movement all the 
interior problems of the Christian ethic and of that Stoic idealism 
which is so closely connected with it, have been reawakened. 
Once again we are faced with the question : how far is it at all 
possible for the faculty of thought and of the Ethos, of faith and 
of the world outlook, to oppose the natural processes of social 
development, and to overcome and shape them, both from within 
and from without? Is it possible that ideal laws of the Ethos and 
of the Divine “nature of Humanity” can overcome, or at least 
affect, the ordinary natural laws of social development? Can it be, 
after all, that that which is humanly possible forms the limit of 
that which is ideally necessary? Is there, in fact, any real hope of 
a Christianity for the majority of mankind? 

Tolstoi 

It is a remarkable fact that while Western Christendom was 
thinking in this way about a real Christian renewal of Society 
within the modern State, the old radical sect-ideal found a prophet 
in Russia, who, on the contrary, wished to break with the State 
entirely, and with the whole technical and legal system of civil- 
ization, in order to found a new humanity. It is the radical early 
Christian ideal, shorn of its apocalyptic element, which also 
refuses the aid of modem technical Rationalism. 

If in spirit men will only break with the present world-order, 
then out of the spirit of love itself a new world will arise — a world 

464 See p. 962. 



PROTESTANTISM 729 

without State, law, or compulsion, without mechanization or the 
desire for material pleasure. Tolstoi can only be completely under- 
stood from the point of view of the Russian world, and perhaps 
also from the point of view of the development of the Russian 
sect-system. His significance, however, is this: for the West he 
proclaims the old radical sect-ideal of a realization of the Sermon 
on the Mount, in the artistic form in which it is alone possible to 
attract the attention of modern cultivated people to such ques- 
tions. Tolstoi’s message is based essentially upon the Sermon on 
the Mount ; it is, however, characteristically free from all traces 
of that tension which the expectation of the imminence of the 
Coming of Christ produced in the Primitive Church ; it steers clear 
also of all the dangers involved in an ecclesiastical ethic of com- 
promise, or of a fusion with the busy activity of the Western world. 
The fact that Tolstoi founds his whole message upon a conception 
of God which is strongly coloured by Western pantheism, and 
which dims the clear spiritual motives of the Sermon on the 
Mount with a kind of modern ennui, need not detain us here. 
Tolstoi’s understanding of the Gospel may be limited, but the 
fact remains that his message — like that of the radical sect and of 
Christian Socialism — is still a reminder of the essential funda- 
mental features of the Gospel, which had been obscured by the 
doctrine of the relative Natural Law of fallen humanity, and which 
the classical Natural Law of Liberalism as well as the most modern 
kind of Socialism had forgotten, and it had therefore obliterated 
all traces of their connection with the source from which they 
sprang . 465 

At this point we must leave these questions. They belong to 
the realm of systematic ethics, not to the history of ethics and of 
social doctrine. 

II. Mysticism and Spiritual Idealism 

We must now direct our attention afresh to the second current 
which flows alongside the main stream of ecclesiastical Protestant- 
ism — to “spiritual religion” and mysticism. We have already 
noticed it frequently in its connection with the sect-movement; 
in the usual treatment of these questions this second element is 
unhesitatingly classed with the sect-movement. 

“Baptists and spiritual reformers” (“Tiiuferund Spiritualisten”) 
has become a stock phrase, as if in essentials both were the same. 
This is, however, an entirely erroneous idea. For these two move- 
ments are like separate streams, which only mingle their waters 

465 See p. 962. 



730 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

now and again, but which historically vary greatly both in their 
sources and in their development. 

The subject with which we are now concerned is Christian 
Mysticism and its significance within the sphere of Protestantism. 
This Protestant mysticism also carries forward pre-Reformation 
ideas and tendencies, like the sect, but it is far more closely con- 
nected with Luther’s original main ideas, and is therefore still 
more strongly rooted within Protestantism . 466 

It is, however, a very difficult matter to distinguish clearly 
between this type of mysticism and the sect-movement; this 
difficulty is increased by the fact that the old heresiological 
tradition ignored these differences entirely, and under its in- 
fluence modern research has only learnt very gradually to distin- 
guish between them. The difference becomes most evident when 
we consider the sociological consequences to which these move- 
ments gave rise; this indeed is the standpoint from which the 
difference between the Church and the sect is most easily dis- 
cerned . 467 If, however, we are to gain a right understanding of the 
sociological consequences of mysticism, our first task must be 
to understand the nature of the religious source whence these 
consequences proceed. In the first place, therefore, we must make 
a general analysis of the religious nature of mysticism. It is only 
at this point in our inquiry that the time has come to deal with 
this question, although mysticism itself goes back to the very 
earliest days of Christianity; the intellectual content which 
underlies Protestant mysticism in particular was formed partly 
by the mysticism of St. Bernard and Richard of St. Victor, and 
partly also by the deep, rich, and splendid German mysticism of 
the later Middle Ages. 

Mysticism : A Direct Religious Experience 

In the widest sense of the word, mysticism is simply the insist- 
ence upon a direct inward and present religious experience. It 
takes for granted the objective forms of religious life in worship, 
ritual, myth, and dogma ; and it is either a reaction against these 
objective practices, which it tries to draw back into the living 
process, or it is the supplementing of traditional forms of worship 
by means of a personal and living stimulus. Mysticism is thus 

466 See p. 962. 

467 For the difference between both the remarks concerned in Hegler , see 
information in Harnack's Dognungeschichte , ThLZ 1S98, Nr. 9, and Luthardt: 
Gesch. d. christl. Ethik II, 249/ ; also Sippell: Chr. W ign y pp. 955-957, gives 
important information in line with my definition of the conception of the sect. 



PROTESTANTISM 73l 

always something secondary, something which has been deliber- 
ately thought out, although this emotional condition which 
has been deliberately produced is characteristically connected 
with an immediacy of feeling which is the entire opposite of the 
former process. Thus it always contains a paradoxical element, 
a certain hostility to popular religion and its average forms of 
expression, an artificiality which, however, is again extinguished 
by its own thirst for direct communion with God. Hence the 
primitive religious fact itself in which experience and the expression 
of the experience are simply identical, is never mystical . 468 The 
vitality of the religious sense, however, when it is faced with 
objectified religion, easily and often develops mystical character- 
istics. It expresses itself in ecstasy and frenzy, in visions and 
hallucinations, in subjective religious experience and “inward- 
ness”, in concentration upon the purely interior and emotional 
side of religious experience. Certainly these visions are rarely 
creative in the sense of imparting fresh knowledge; they are 
almost always expansions and interpretations of the common 
faith, as was the case with the spiritual gifts of the early Christians, 
and with the innumerable visions and prophecies of mediaeval 
recluses and saints, an experience which has been repeated all 
through the centuries, down to the present day. 

Alongside of, or within, the recognized forms of worship, 
mysticism creates special and more intimate mysteries, in which 
salvation is appropriated in a peculiarly inward manner; in 
these mysteries the ancient cults of sacred meals, “feeding upon 
the god”, of sacrifice, of a new birth from the divinity into an 
immediate eating and drinking of the life of the divinity, become 
intensified and inward to the point of a real new birth and deifica- 
tion. Mysticism creates prophecies and ecstasies as well as fantastic 
allegories and a “spiritual” interpretation of the objective side 
of religion. This mystical sense, however, can also create a passion- 
ate realism of communion with the gods, which makes the 
ancient cults or the accepted rites the means of immediate sub- 
stantial union. The Hellenistic mysteries united the most coarse 
and material conceptions with “spiritual” theories which reduced 
them all to a symbol, which still, however, had a wonderful effect. 
According to Paul, the Christian Supper of the Lord was itself a 
mystical creation; and when the Eucharist became an objective 
ecclesiastical rite, Eucharistic mysticism transformed it, for the 
second time, into a mystical experience. 

Above all, eroticism here plays a leading part, since either the 
4#s See my articles upon Revelation , Faith , Faith and History , in Schiele s Lexikon • 



732 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

sexual stimulation is also used to stimulate religious enthusiasm, 
or the latter strengthens and expresses itself in sexual stimulation. 
The imagery of Love and the “Wine-shops” of Sufi poetry, and 
certain Christian interpretations of the Song of Songs, harp upon 
the same string in the spiritual life. 

On the other hand, this immediacy of feeling likes to escape 
from the finite world of sense through a spirituality which either 
treats it with indifference and ignores it, or removes it to a distance 
by means of ascetic mortifications. Mysticism is thus open to the 
incursions of a spiritual Pantheism and of a radical Dualism of 
flesh and spirit, of time and of eternity ; and, in connection with 
it, to the suggestions of an asceticism which crushes all that is 
finite, or of a Libertinism which treats everything as equally 
indifferent. 

Mysticism in the New Testament 

Thus, in all religious systems in these varied forms mysticism 
is a universal phenomenon. It reached a particularly high stage 
of development in India, Persia, Greece, Asia Minor, and Syria. 
It was only natural that it should appear within the primitive 
Christian movement, where it developed partly from within, 
out of its own life, and in part was introduced from without and 
eagerly accepted . 469 It is to this mysticism that the so-called 
“Enthusiasm” of the Primitive Christian Church, a large part of 
the “spiritual gifts”, the “speaking with tongues”, the power of 
exorcism, the whole of its spiritual activity, belongs ; this pheno- 
menon recurs again and again, in the Christian sect-movement, 
down to the present day, bringing home with great power the 
redemptive energy of the Gospel to the individual soul. Paul, in 
particular, on his mystical side represents this type of Christianity 
which existed along with his Church convictions in a permanent 
state of tension, though he himself was not aware of a conflict 
between the two tendencies. Paul took over the Christ-cult of 
the Primitive Church as a form of religion which had already 
been objectified in worship, tradition, and organization. But he 
inspired it with a deep and passionate mysticism, which also 
utilized the ancient terminology of the pagan mysteries. It is in 
this alone that his religious originality consists, contrasted with 
the view of the Primitive Church ; and it was only thus that his 
anti-Jewish universalism became practically effective. Thus the 

449 For the subject in general, see Edv. Lehmann: Mystik in Heidentum und Christen - 
turn, igoi; A. Merx: Ideen und Grundlinien einer allgemeinen Gesch. der Mystik , 1903; 
above all, Erwin Rohdes' Psyche , also James: Varieties of Religious Experience . 



PROTESTANTISM 


733 

Lord’s Supper, the centre of the new cult, became to him a 
mystical, substantial union, and Baptism became an actual 
dying and rising again with Christ. To him Christ became an 
actual sphere of life of a supersensual kind, in which the believer 
lives, feels, and thinks, and becomes a new spiritual personality, 
“a new creature”. Thus all that was merely ceremonial and 
traditional was relegated to the sphere of “the flesh” and “the 
world”, and the “Christ according to the flesh” fades out of sight. 
So the history of Israel was allegorized and spiritualized, in order 
that it could be directly applied to the Christian believer, and 
the Christian community became the spiritual Body of Christ. 
Ecstasies and visions were not wanting, spiritual gifts were 
exalted and cultivated, and incorporated into a new spiritual 
life. 

Here, in this primitive Christian pneumatic enthusiasm, and 
in the Pauline Christ-mysticism, lie the inexhaustible sources of 
Christian mysticism. In the Fourth Gospel this mysticism has 
already become calm and controlled, and adjusted to the historical 
and objective side of religion. Here, in particular, however, it 
has also produced or discovered its really characteristic formulas 
— flesh and spirit, darkness and light, allegory and “the letter”. 

Other early Christian writings contain similar elements. 
Through the New Testament, spiritual enthusiasm and Pauline 
mysticism became a permanent source of power, stimulating the 
corresponding sense of need and vivifying its formulas. This 
mysticism has expressed itself in a very vital way at all periods 
of Church history, and particularly at all periods of criticism of 
tradition, of religious decline, and of new religious developments. 

Tfie germ of the idea of the Church as an institution was already 
latent within Primitive Christianity, for it was given naturally 
with the conception of grace, of a finished salvation, and of the 
salvation of the world. Primitive Christianity also contains the 
germ of the sect-idea, which reveres the Sermon on the Mount as 
the moral law of its Master and continues His expectation of the 
coming of the Kingdom of God upon earth, and gathers the pure 
and holy into the fellowship of the Church which waits for Christ’s 
return. Primitive Christianity also contains the germs of a mysti- 
cism for which this fleeting world is but a symbol, all that belongs 
to the sense-life and to the earthly sphere a mere limitation ; for 
which every form of worship is only a means of substantial union, 
and all faith simply a direct translation from the visible to the 
invisible, into the very life of God and Christ . 470 

470 See p. 963. 



734 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Mysticism and the Philosophy of Religion 

Now, however, we must seek to distinguish mysticism in the 
narrower, technical concentrated sense in which it is used in 
the philosophy of religion from this wider mysticism with its 
immense variety. The phenomena which have just been described 
proceed directly from the emotional sphere, and for that reason 
they are comparatively instinctive and spontaneous, and can be 
combined with every kind of objective religion, and with the 
customary forms of worship, myth, and doctrine. They contain 
no kind of doctrine and theory about themselves ; at the most all 
they possess is a primitive technique of religious self-cultivation 
and the production of a certain temper. Their varied forms of 
expression — enthusiasm, orgiasm, contemplation and Gnosticism, 
allegorical and spiritualizing tendencies, the renewal or the 
bringing forth of forms of worship — are quite different from each 
other, and they develop very different results which often cancel 
each other out. Hence they do not essentially affect the existing 
sociological connection with religion, for they simply mean an 
intensification of its powers, or a particular emphasis upon some 
of its elements, or perhaps they add new forms of worship ; but 
concrete religion they do not deny. 

The whole question can, however, sometimes assume a far more 
unified aspect, and then a considerable sociological element is 
introduced into the situation. The active energies in mysticism 
of this kind can become independent in principle, contrasted with 
concrete religion; they then break away from it and set up a 
theory of their own which takes the place of the concrete religion 
and of its mythos or doctrine ; this may take place either by means 
of open denial, or through an allegorical change in interpretation. 
When this takes place, however, mysticism realizes that it is an 
independent religious principle ; it sees itself as the real universal 
heart of all religion, of which the various myth-forms are merely 
the outer garment. It regards itself as the means of restoring an 
immediate union with God ; it feels independent of all institutional 
religion, and possesses an entire inward certainty, which makes it 
indifferent towards every kind of religious fellowship. This is its 
fundamental attitude ; it does not vary whether the mystic adheres 
externally to the religious community or not. Henceforward union 
with God, deification, self-annihilation, become the real and the 
only subject of religion; 

This theme is then presented as the abstract content of mystical 
experience, and is made the general universal essence of all 



PROTESTANTISM 735 

inward and genuine religious processes, A union with God of this 
kind, however, further requires a general cosmic theory in which 
is established both the possibility and the manner of realizing 
this process of salvation. It also requires a technique of causation 
and completion of the mystical experience deduced from this 
theory. 

A theory of this kind must be able to show how it came to pass 
that, in God, a separation between God and finite spirits could 
take place, and how this separation can be overcome by the very 
fact that the finite spirits have their being within God. It shows 
how all that is finite proceeds from God and returns unto God, for 
the sense of identity persisting through the separation becomes the 
very means by which the sense of separation is removed. This 
theory defines the degrees by which the creature falls away from 
and then rises up again into God; finally, it shows clearly that 
reflection upon and understanding of this process explains the 
religious experience to itself, and thus it attains an understanding 
of its own particular central content. The purely intellectual 
process of this association of ideas, so it is said, is, where it is 
really genuine and independent thought, the religious experience 
itself, and through this intellectual process the religious experi- 
ence again interprets and clarifies its own ideas. From this there 
arise also the degrees of this experience, which are simply the 
stages of this intellectual process translated into terms of spiritual 
experience, to the point of the conscious attainment of the full 
sense of identity. 

This type of mysticism becomes an independent religious 
philosophy, which recognizes that the religious process is the 
samd universal expression and consciousness of the metaphysical 
connection between absolute and finite being, and which dis- 
covers everywhere, beneath all the concrete forms of religion, the 
same religious germ, which, however, only reaches complete and 
pure maturity under its fostering care. Thus mysticism becomes 
independent of concrete popular religion, timeless and non- 
historical, at most concealed under historical symbols, the only 
valid interpretation of the religious process, under whatever form 
it may be clothed. It becomes anti-personal and ascetic, since it 
allows personality to be absorbed in God, because it regards the 
senses and finite existence as the wall of separation between God 
Transcendent and God Immanent. This type of mysticism gives 
rise to that form of Pantheism which, however, in the philo- 
sophical sense is no Pantheism, because in it the separation of the 
finite ego from God is as important as its reunion with God. This 



736 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

therefore tends to develop into the crudest Dualism or into a 
gradual descending system of Emanations. It becomes a peculiar 
kind of intellectualism, an intellectualism which looks down with 
contempt upon the sense-bound standards of the intellect, and 
which replaces the common, carnal, and unhallowed ways of 
thought by a religious logic which is intelligible only to the 
religious mind. It can, however, also become pure voluntaryism, 
as soon as the dangers of thought for religious inwardness are felt, 
and the main stress is laid upon union of the will with God, or 
upon the decline of the will to live. Thus Brahmanistic speculative 
mysticism and Buddhistic voluntary mysticism, the Dominican 
mysticism of knowledge and the Franciscan mysticism of the will 
and of love, are all able to exist side by side. 

This technical mysticism in the narrower sense, with its own 
philosophy of religion, has also appeared in various religious 
spheres with a remarkable similarity of form : in Indian Brahman- 
ism and its repercussion in Buddhism, in the Sufism of the Parsees 
and of Persian Muslims, in the Neo-Platonism of the Greeks, in 
the varied syncretism of late antiquity which is known as Gnosti- 
cism. In the guise of Platonism, Neo-Platonism, and Gnosticism 
it presented itself to the Early Church, which seized it eagerly 
as a scientific foundation for its own religious doctrine, in the 
same way as it took Stoicism into account for its moral and social 
teaching, as a scientifically worked out analogy for its system of 
ethics. The stages of this development within Christianity are 
clearly defined. Jesus is not a mystic. He lives simply with His 
gaze fixed on God, urges practical sanctification of life, and 
proclaims the imminent realization of the ideal. 

Paul and the ‘ ‘spiritual’ * men turn inward, spiritualize, and 
revive the Christ-cult and the Christian tradition which had 
grown up in the Early Church apart from philosophy and specula- 
tion, and with a free use of the mystical language of the ancient 
mysteries. The Gnostics, and the philosophers and theologians of 
the Early Church, open their minds to the mystical philosophy 
of religion, emphasizing more or less the concrete dependence 
upon Christian history, and affirming in varying tones of em- 
phasis the practical and ethical idea of personality. 

Mysticism in the narrower and the technical sense of the word, 
the mysticism which is concerned with the philosophy of religion, 
therefore, also developed an immense importance within Christ- 
ianity. It helped the scientific theology of the early Christians to 
bring their faith in the Divine incarnation, in the hero of the 
cultus, in Christ, into line with the scientific formulas of the 



PROTESTANTISM 


doctrine of the Trinity, which was conceived at first in harmony 
with the theory of emanations, and then as the comuh^nhoi;/, 
<* J* Son »«h the Father ta. It hcl “ 

define the possession of salvation as something to be attained 
through union with God in the Christian cultus, and to give a 
religious and philosophical meaning to its sacraments. It was also 
of value for the apologetic of the early Christians, since mysticism 
represented the natural universal religious consciousness which 
comes to completion in the Incarnation of the Logos and in the 
sacraments of the Church. 

In connection with our present subject, however, all this is 
only relevant in so far as the relative acceptance of mysticism 
at that time formed the starting-point of and the justification for 
an ever fuller penetration of mysticism into Christianity itself. 
For us rather the significant effects of mysticism only emerge 
clearly where the sense of need for the inwardness and quickening 
of the religious process appropriated the technical methods of the 
soul’s ascent to God, worked out by mysticism. This ascent was 
described as a process by which the soul rose from meditation and 
self-denial through ripening knowledge and union, to the heights 
of ecstasy, and thus was able to attain and experience Christian 
union with God and with Christ. Here Dionysius the Areopagite 
forms not the only but the noblest bridge of union with the Neo- 
Platonism which had most thoroughly formulated this doctrine. 
The Alexandrian theologians and Augustine had also already 
made their contribution. The decisive point, however, was not 
reached until mediaeval piety accepted the traditional Christian 
system, with its foreign elements inherited from antiquity (so 
remote from the Germanic temperament) of cultus, doctrine, and 
hierarchy ; this it did by way of mysticism, which breathed into 
it an atmosphere of warm, personal piety. Thus St. Bernard and 
the Victorines freed the Christian faith from dogmatic rigidity 
and infused into it new warmth and vigour. Thus also the mystics 
of the Reformation period describe the gradual ascent of the soul 
from purgation, through illumination, right up to the heights of 
blissful union with God. 

Further, we must also note the doctrine of mystical union with 
God or of the Indwelling of Christ as the very heart and basis of 
all practical religious achievement, and the radiating centre of 
religious ethics. Along these lines Christian mystics have sought 
and found a substantial union with Christ, in which the Christian 
experience became the principle of all religious activity and power, 
and, on the other hand, practical power to overcome the world 



738 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

became the test of the reality of union with Christ. In this way 
the gulf between past and present, between doctrine and practice, 
was overcome, and faith became the principle of direct practical 
achievement. Thus the Christocentric piety of the Middle Ages 
restored to believers direct access to Christ; the rock of Byzantine 
dogma had been struck, and out of it there flowed rivers of living 
water. 

Luther also, sometimes revealed traces of this spirit, and it was 
through these ideas that Karlstadt, Schwenkfeld, and Osiander 
developed a mere faith in the doctrine of justification into the 
power of a life which expressed itself outwardly in direct and 
practical ways. This, too, was the tendency of the Christology 
of all the “spiritual reformers” of that day; it enabled them to 
interpret the Jesus of History and the mystically discerned Christ 
of Experience by the more general principle of the Logos incarnate 
in Christ, through whom they were brought into contact with the 
eternal living fullness of God. 

The Divine Seed 

This latter element, above all, needs to be taken into account 
as a means of establishing the mystical impulse towards an 
interior life, and of breathing fresh life and energy into objective 
religion upon a general theoretical scientific foundation. This 
basis is held to be that universal cosmic process, which is also the 
ultimate underlying truth in the Christian experience of salvation, 
of the descent of the Absolute into the finite world of sense, in 
which, however, God remains the Ground of the Soul, the Seed 
and the Spark even of the Creature, which in selfishness and sin 
asserts its right to an isolated independent existence. This is the 
great doctrine of the Divine Seed, of the Divine Spark which 
lies hidden in every mind and soul, stifled by sin and by the finite, 
yet capable of being quickened into vitality by the touch of the 
Divine Spirit working on and in our souls. This “seed” is the 
source of all religious longing for and awareness of God. Simply 
quickened by the historic revelation, this “seed” is developed into 
a complete power of overcoming the world and of return to God 
by the purely inward movement of the Spirit which is kindled 
and strengthened within the soul. Here all the emphasis falls 
upon the present, immediate, interior religious movement of 
feeling and of thought, in contrast to all external authority, all 
literalism in faith, to all theories which would make salvation 
dependent upon historical facts and upon the individual’s know- 
ledge and acceptance of these facts. Here the saving energy of 



PROTESTANTISM 


739 

God joins forces with the movement of transient religious emotion, 
and faith is certain that it is able to distinguish the motion of 
the Divine Spirit from all merely human opinion and desire, by 
the practice of self-examination and the cultivation of a selfless 
spirit. All that is ecclesiastical, historic, dogmatic, objective, and 
authoritative is changed into a mere means of stimulation, into 
that which arouses that personal experience which alone is 
valuable, and on which alone the hope of salvation is founded. 
This is a theology of the subjective consciousness of salvation, 
and no longer one which confines itself to the objective facts of 
redemption. The Spirit, or the present living consciousness of 
salvation, and the facts of history and of the cultus, have been 
placed in a new relation. All that concerns the Church, doctrine, 
and dogma seems to be simply a precipitation of a personal 
religious life of that kind, and can only be understood in its true 
sense by the gracious inward influence of the Spirit, the move- 
ment of God within the soul. The spirit of God can only recognize 
His own Presence in the Scriptures and in the Church, and only 
thus can strength and nourishment be drawn from them; left 
to themselves both the Bible and the Church are merely a dead 
letter or an empty ceremonial. This is mystical “spiritual religion” 
in the service of a direct and personal religious life, preserving 
that which is alone worthy, a life in the spirit which rises above and 
conquers the world. 

German mysticism evolved this theory as the foundation of 
practical reform, in connection with the emancipation of late 
mediaeval lay-Christianity from its ancient setting; at the same 
time* with varying consistency, it remained in touch with the 
objective institution of the Church, and, so far as lay in its power, 
it preserved the main Christian tendency by its emphasis upon 
personality. According to this theory, the finite spirit achieves 
actual reality in the world process ; in its selfish resistance towards 
the Spirit of God it commits real sin, and through the working 
of the Divine Spirit which lays hold of it in Christianity it is 
raised to the true centre of personality and united with God. It 
is true that the ultimate end of union with God in contemplation, 
or in the surrender of the will to the Divine Love, still somehow 
always involves a certain loss of selfhood in God. In this respect 
Dante himself found it difficult to preserve the distinction. There 
can, however, be no doubt that mysticism intends to maintain 
the elevation, salvation, and deification of the true and genuine 
centre of personality. The whole mystical idea itself is indeed at 
the service of a personal living piety, of an “interior life” which 



740 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

has a direct experience of salvation. This fact, together with the 
relation between the inner working of the Spirit and the stimula- 
tion, heightened power, and intensification which come from 
history (which was somehow always maintained), distinguishes 
this Christian mysticism from its ancient foundation of Neo- 
Platonism, quite apart from the fact that the Trinitarian-Christo- 
logical doctrine was retained and interpreted in this sense . 471 

The mysticism of the period of the Reformation arose out of 
this old mystical tradition, and its foundation in the New Testa- 
ment, which constantly inspired it with fresh life. It is a matter 
of common knowledge that Luther himself was greatly influenced 
by it. Calvin, however, came far less under its influence. His 
doctrine of the Eucharist, too, does not agree with it, but rather 
with anti-Catholicism, and with the tendency to place a great 
gulf between the Creator and the creature. Calvinism is related 
to the sect-type, but not to mysticism. In spite of that, however, 
mysticism penetrated into it through all the avenues which 
were then possible, just as it penetrated into the Catholicism of 
the Counter-Reformation and into Lutheran Pietism. While in 
connection with Catholicism its strength lay in its desire to 
represent itself as the complement of the exaggerated emphasis 
upon the purely objective aspect of religion, and in its power to 
unite itself with the Catholic doctrine of justification in the shape 
of an inward substantial transformation of the believer ; 472 on the 
other hand mysticism had a great attraction for Protestantism 
in its fundamental emphasis upon personal assurance of salvation, 
and, particularly in Lutheranism, in the doctrine of the present 
happiness of those whom Christ has set free. 

The spiritualized conception of the Church in Protestantism, 
and the unsettlement which prevailed while the new Church 
organizations were being formed, provided this movement with 
scope for independent development. When this section was 
excluded from the churches and needed some other support and 
fellowship it found a very uncertain support and refuge in the 
excited “Enthusiasm” of the Anabaptists and in their ascetic 
system of morality. Some mystics remained entirely solitary, and 
entrusted their knowledge only to the printed page . 47 24 Under 
these circumstances there arose a Protestant mysticism which, 
unlike Catholic mysticism, was not a compensation for ecclesi- 
astical formalism, but which was a conscious, active, and inde- 
pendent principle of religious knowledge, inward experience, 
and morality. Only upon the basis of Protestant individualism 
471 See p. 963. 478 See p. 964. 47la Cf. p. 739. 



PROTESTANTISM 


74i 

and Paulinism did specifically Christian mysticism attain an 
independent development, with new creative power, which 
exercised an ever deeper influence upon ecclesiastical Protestant- 
ism, and yet always remained inwardly separate from it. Antici- 
pating the results of the modern, speculative, and autonomous 
philosophy of religion, it pointed forward to the development 
of modern Protestantism, and, in connection with Pietism, it 
destroyed ecclesiasticism, making the ecclesiastical exclusiveness 
and institutionalism of Protestantism increasingly uncertain. 

“Spiritual Reformers” 

This form of mysticism certainly found its highest and noblest 
expression only in the most outstanding thinkers and the most 
“interior souls” among the Protestant “Spiritual Reformers”, in 
men like Sebastian Franck, Valentine Weigel, Dirck Coornheert, 
and John Saltmarsh. Detached elements of this process of thought, 
however, often appear among them all in an obscure connection 
with ecclesiastical statements, as, for instance, in Karlstadt, 
Schwenkfeld, and others. Conclusions of this kind were not un- 
common in the “Enthusiasm” which played such a prominent 
part in the early Anabaptist movement, in the beginnings of 
Quakerism and in Methodism. Individuals also came to the same 
conclusions, even though mere “Enthusiasm” which depends 
upon sudden, extraordinary, and unregulated manifestations of 
God in itself certainly has no connection with the mystic’s repose 
in the eternal unchanging Divine Spark within the human soul. 
Since, however, in all this the “enthusiastic” temperament still 
presses forward through religious excitement into the direct 
presence of the Spirit or of God, it has a strong tendency towards 
mysticism, which was often fully developed by “enthusiastic” and 
highly educated Baptists. The English Puritans passed from Piet- 
ism and Enthusiasm into mysticism and “spiritual religion” — at 
least in part — and when they did so it was with great vigour. 
Continental Pietists also came under the same influence ; in both 
instances the older “spiritual” literature was producing a belated 
effect. As we have already noticed, the Congregationalists and 
Independents were “Spiritualists” without realizing it. The 
Quakers, in particular, developed their classic theory of the 
Inner Light out of an “enthusiastic” movement, and thus found 
rest of spirit and light in perplexity. It was, however, only when 
“Enthusiasm” and the urge towards “inwardness” achieved 
results of this kind that mysticism became real spirituality; at 
the same time, in its anti-hierarchical tendency to further the 



742 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

idea of the priesthood of all believers, this spirituality reveals its 
Protestant character . 478 

Thus we see clearly the difference between this “spiritual * 5 
tendency and the sect-ideal and the Baptist movement. For the 
Baptists the decisive element is the Law of Christ, the Sermon on 
the Mount, and the absolute Law of Nature which agrees with 
it. The “spiritual reformers”, on the other hand, know nothing 
but the Spirit, its freedom and its inward impulse. They are 
“Antinomians” and obey the light of conscience which has been 
unveiled by the Indwelling Christ. The Anabaptists laid passion- 
ate stress on Adult Baptism as the external sign of the covenant 
with God. To the “spiritual reformers’* Baptism was a matter of 
supreme indifference. They recognized solely the “Baptism of the 
Spirit”, and they taught that only those who were spiritually 
gifted were able to recognize those who belong to the true, pure, 
Spiritual Church, or fellowship of the Spirit of Christ. The Ana- 
baptists had external organizations and ceremonies: the Lord’s 
Supper, the feet-washing, a constitution. The “spiritual reformers” 
would admit nothing but the worship of God in spirit and in 
truth; they recognized no external united Christian body, and, 
at bottom, they had no use for sacraments. The Anabaptists 
obeyed the external Word as their literal rule of life and their 
external authority. The “spiritual reformers” depended upon the 
Inward Word, the Logos, the Divine Seed, or the Divine Spark, 
through whose impulses alone they were able to understand the 
external Word, which they (who also held firmly to the doctrine 
of inspiration) interpreted in an allegorical manner. The Ana- 
baptists organized congregations, and appointed their members 
to different offices ; they used ordination and carried on mission 
work. The “spiritual reformers” dwelt within the Invisible Church, 
in which the Spirit does all, and in which it is not necessary to 
know each other according to the flesh. The Anabaptists formed 
a community ruled by Christ and composed of genuine saints. 
The “spiritual reformers” did not recognize a visible Church 
at all, but they looked for the Third Age in which all men will 

478 On this point cf. the very valuable writings of H. Heppe: Geschichte der 
pietistischen Mystik in der katholischen Kirche , 1875, Geschichte des Pietismus und der 
Mystik in der re/ormierten Kirche namentlich der Niederlande y 1879. The latter book 
maintains its very considerable value alongside of RitschVs Geschichte des 
Pietismus . — There is a one-sided ascription of mysticism to Catholicism in 
Herrmann: Verkehr des Christen mit Gott, pp. 16-21 (English translation, Communion 
with Gody pp. 19 ff.). In the school of Ritschl both mysticism and the sect-type 
are referred back to Catholicism, in order that they may be excluded the more 
surely from Protestantism. 



PROTESTANTISM 


743 

be illuminated and led by the Spirit Himself; for them Christ 
ruled only by the Spirit, which is identical with direct religious 
experience. The Anabaptists also took the Apocalypse literally, 
and calculated the Advent of Christ and the coming of the 
Millennium. The “spiritual reformers * 5 spiritualized even the 
Millennium, transforming it into an inward return of Christ to 
hearts which at last are open to the Divine Love. The Anabaptists 
laid great stress on the teaching of the Synoptic Gospels, on the 
Jesus of History, and on His proclamation of the coming Kingdom 
of God. The “spiritual reformers” appealed to Paul and to John : 
they did not know Christ after the flesh, and through the Spirit 
they were ever pressing on into an ever new and deeper knowledge 
of God, which to them was alone the true work of God. These 
differences are fundamental; their ultimate causes lie in the 
Bible itself. 

The distinctive sociological peculiarities of this kind of “spiritual 
religion” are also manifest. Mysticism is a radical individualism, 
very different from that of the sect. While the sect separates 
individuals from the world by its conscious hostility to “worldli- 
ness” and by its ethical severity, binding them together in a 
voluntary fellowship, established upon mutual control and peni- 
tential discipline, laying upon individuals the obligation to follow 
the example and submit to the authority of Christ, increasing 
individualism by placing it within the mutual influence of group- 
fellowship and worship, — mysticism lays no stress at all upon the 
relation between individuals, but only upon the relations between 
the soul and God. It regards the historical, authoritative, and ritual 
elements in religion merely as methods of quickening the religious 
sense with which, in case of need, it can dispense altogether. 
“Spiritual religion”, in particular, in its intense emphasis upon 
“first-hand experience”, actually tends to sweep away the histori- 
cal element altogether, and in so doing it eliminates the only 
centre around which a Christian cult can be formed. Thus this 
kind of religion becomes non-historical, formless, and purely 
individualistic, although certainly in very varying degrees of 
consistency. So long as it remains consciously Christian, the 
Bible and the historic Figure of Christ still play an important 
part; this aspect, however, is never stressed sufficiently strongly 
to produce a firmly established community, with a common 
centre of worship, history, and authority. Whatever organized 
forms it does adopt are loose and provisional, mere concessions 
to human frailty, without any sense of inward necessity and 
Divine inspiration. Its individualism, therefore, differs entirely 



744 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

from that of the sect. The sect characteristics — personal confession 
of faith in Christ, and the ever-renewed creation of fresh forms 
of fellowship through the mutual influence of individuals upon 
each other — are absent. Instead there is simply a parallelism of 
spontaneous religious personalities, whose only bond of union is 
their common Divine origin, their common spirit of love, and their 
union in God, which is the free and invisible work of the Divine 
Spirit. In itself, this kind of spirituality feels no need for sacraments 
or dogmas, for a ministry or for organization. Its spirit of fellow- 
ship, like the religious illumination itself, is solely the work of the 
Spirit, which is the same in each soul, and can be recognized 
alike by each soul, from which also in each separate instance there 
arises the interior union of souls and the active expression of 
Christian love. The individualism of the Anabaptist movement 
has been transcended, since this “spiritual religion 5 ’ dispenses 
with all mediate and organized forms of worship and fellowship, 
placing faith and feeling in an entirely independent position. On 
the other hand, this kind of individualism is much weaker than 
that of the Anabaptist movement — (with its emphasis upon 
continual activity and the active holiness of its members who are 
united in a vital fellowship) — since its main tendency is towards 
quietude and abandonment, in which love is exercised only in 
individual instances. Individualism can, indeed, mean very 
different things, and have a very different effect, according to its 
basis and its setting, as we have already seen in the difference 
between mediaeval individualism with its emphasis upon 
differentiation and gradation, and Protestant individualism with 
its stress on the equal autonomy and equal obligation of all towards 
the community. 

So far it might seem as though this kind of “spiritual religion 55 
had no positive sociological character at all, or as though it only 
achieved fellowship incidentally through lack of clarity. This, 
however, is not the case. First of all, as we have already seen, 
“spiritual religion 55 presupposes both the unity of the “Divine 
Ground 55 which is the source of all personal religion, and the 
unity of aim which binds all souls together in one. Only it does not 
strive to create fellowship and unity by its own human activity — 
by founding organizations and societies — but it leaves this work 
to the Divine action through the Spirit. Further, this “spiritual 
religion 55 is still Christian. This does not mean simply that the 
Spirit is fully incarnate and visible in Christ, thus gathering 
believers into an historic and definite unity, but also that the 
ethical element of Will in the Christian and prophetical idea of 



PROTESTANTISM 


745 


God, urges it towards active charity and self-giving to the 
brethren. 

Sociological Theory of “Spiritual 
Religion” : The “Invisible Church” 

Hence at this point there arises the idea of fellowship peculiar 
to this kind of “spiritual religion” : the idea of the Invisible Church, 
of the purely spiritual fellowship, known to God alone, about 
which man does not need to concern himself at all, but which 
invisibly rules all believers, without external signs or other human 
means. The conception of a purely spiritual fellowship, which is 
carried forward independently by the power of the Spirit, is the 
background of this sentiment, and in this the individual is there- 
fore relieved of all obligation to organize and evangelize, and 
from all connection with ecclesiastical and sectarian organization. 
There is no need to make any efforts to prove and maintain the 
historical basis of faith ; it appears spontaneously wherever the 
Spirit beholds Himself. Since in reality all Christianity is identical 
with the stirring of the divine “Seed” in the soul, Christ also is 
omnipresent, not merely in His historical form, but also in every 
true believer. Non-Christian religious souls can thus also be revela- 
tions of the Christ. Once again, however, this means that all forms 
of religion, viewed from the Christian standpoint, are regarded 
as identical with Christianity. The best method, therefore, of 
making this fellowship an active and practical force is the practice 
of toleration, coupled with faith in the power of God to make this 
fellowship effective by the might of His Spirit. Thus the “spiritual” 
man everywhere seeks to reach others at the deepest levels of the 
soul, wherever these are at all accessible. He exercises Christian 
charity, however, not in founding institutions or societies, but 
in practical life, wherever the claims of love present themselves 
in the guise of homely duty. Thus in this Christian “spiritual 
religion” there is an element of fellowship which is closely related 
to Luther’s earlier ideas; the only difference is that Luther 
required the “spiritual life” to be kept in close relation with the 
Word, the Sacrament, and the ministry, whereas the “spiritual 
reformers” proclaimed the need for the free and untrammelled 
movement of the Spirit, an increase of knowledge and of freedom 
in opposition to “the letter” of Scripture. 

But the sociological element in mysticism goes still farther. 
Even the mystic is human, and he feels the need for the give-and- 
take of intimate fellowship with other souls. In the mystic, too, 
this is no mere human weakness but a Christian duty, inculcated 



746 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

plainly by the example of the pure love of the Primitive Church 
as a command of the Spirit of God. Where, however, mystics 
do form groups they do not intend them to take the place of the 
great Invisible Church (sis a sect would tend to do), or to interfere 
with God’s own work of spreading the influence of the Spirit; 
the aim of these groups is purely personal; they are intimate 
circles for edification. This kind of fellowship expressed itself in 
various ways, as for instance in Philadelphianism ; and in the 
formation of groups round spiritual directors and deeply experi- 
enced leaders. There was nothing rigid about these groups; 
they formed and re-formed naturally and easily, according to the 
situation in any given place. At other times this spirit expressed 
itself in organizations which were formed on the family pattern; 
these groups were formed by religious people who lived a com- 
munity life which was similar to that of the cloister; they were 
controlled by ideas which were in entire agreement with the 
mystical ideas contained in monasticism. They had no intention, 
however, of claiming to be “the true Church” or “the Christian 
community” ; they were merely personal and casual in character, 
groups within the Invisible Church which the Spirit calls into 
being, through which, in some incalculable manner, He influences 
the whole . 474 Only in an intimate group of this kind can worship 
be offered in purity and truth, arising out of a spiritual fellowship 
in which love has been truly kindled on the altar of intimate 
friendship and union in God. In this method of worship there are 
no magical “means of grace” and no ritual ordinances; all the 
stress is laid upon the mutual fellowship of hearts — “representa- 
tive action” as Schleiermacher very unecclesiastically describes 
the cultus. Within such groups the Lord’s Supper and the Xgape 
can be renewed and spiritualized in their true mystical meaning, 
in a way which is impossible to the Church of the masses, or in 
the quarrelsome exercise of discipline among the sects. As the 
polemical writers of that day used to say, “spiritual religion” is 
super-ecclesiastical, “syncrctistic”, “indifferent”, or “fanatical”. 
In reality this movement reabsorbs rigid historical dogma into 
the living movement and development of the Spirit; in the 
psychological processes themselves it seeks the essence of revela- 
tion and a present redemption. 

Effects of “Spiritual Religion” on Dogma 
Since all mysticism first arises in opposition to objective dogmas 
and forms of worship, it assumes in a very aristocratic way that 

474 See p. 964. 



PROTESTANTISM 


747 

the concrete forms of worship will continue to be the religion of the 
masses. It is its mission, however, to call the true children of God 
out of that external worship in order to lift them up into the 
Kingdom of God which is purely within us. From every side it 
sees souls growing into this Kingdom. From this point of view 
these more intimate groups are merely personal and changing 
forms of fellowship, which express in a particular circle, with 
enhanced vitality, the universal unity of the Spirit. That is why 
so many mystics remain within the Church, which they do not 
wish to replace by any other new organization; they look upon 
their own circles as special groups which can quite well exist 
within the Church itself. Several, of course, do reject the Church 
altogether and live an isolated existence, but they comfort them- 
selves with the thought of a better future, of a “third revelation” 
when all shall be taught of God, and when an “unsectarian 
Christianity of love” will unite all Christians in one fellowship 
of love. Mystics are far less inclined to separate from the Church 
than are the sectarians. 

Naturally this whole way of thinking reacts upon the world of 
doctrinal conceptions. As the main doctrines of the Church — of 
Christ, the Trinity, the Work of Redemption through the Atone- 
ment, and the sacraments which appropriate this redemption — 
are closely connected with the ecclesiastical idea and with the 
worship of the Church, the mystical movement stands out in 
opposition to the current ecclesiastical doctrine of Redemption 
and of the Sacrament. It recognizes no “finished salvation” with 
which the Church is endowed as an organ of grace, but only, 
primarily, the facts of revelation and redemption in the present 
religious experience of each soul. Thus it feels no need of the 
doctrine of the Atonement, and it sees in it only the logical, ethical, 
and metaphysical inconsistencies which cause its disintegration. 
“Spiritual religion” of this kind does not admit the possibility 
of appropriating the benefits of redemption through worship, the 
sacraments, or through Church organization. It rejects the whole 
idea of an objective deposit of salvation upon which the Church 
can draw in order to impart its benefits to those who need them ; 
its main emphasis is upon the example of Christ as the source of 
His continuing spiritual influence. Primarily it does not know 
the “Christ after the flesh” at all, and it has no interest in the 
doctrine of the Incarnation ; it sees the Divinity of Christ solely in 
the Spirit of Christ of which the Jesus of History is merely the 
concrete symbol. Therefore it either deifies Christ entirely, even 
in His human nature, or it loosens the connection between 



748 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

the Divine and human elements in Christ. Thence there arise 
now and again attacks upon the doctrine of the Trinity, which 
come very near to placing Christ within a Neo-Platonic Emana- 
tionism . 476 This type of religion does not strive after a mass 
Christianity, for which, naturally, the forgiveness of sins stands in 
the foreground, as a release from the unattainable degree of sancti- 
fication without giving up the comfort of salvation ; in it the for- 
giveness of sins recedes into the background, and it is replaced 
by a direct experience of God and actual victory over sin through 
the deification of the soul . 476 

In all these aspects, however, “spiritual religion” is also opposed 
to the sect, which presupposes the God-Man as the ruler and 
founder of the religious community, and the work of salvation 
as the complement of the efforts of a life of sanctification which 
is still always imperfect. Nor has it any use for the ideas of the 
sect with its literal historic Christ, and its retention of the Synoptic 
message of the Kingdom of God. Only where the sect merges into 
mysticism do we find it exercising this kind of doctrinal criticism, 
as, for instance, among some Baptist and Quaker theologians. On 
some other points, however, mysticism approaches the sect point 
of view in doctrinal matters, but, characteristically, for very 
different reasons. This applies, above all, to its repudiation of the 
doctrine of predestination. The coupling together of the doctrine 
of original sin and reprobation, with the doctrine of election, 
seemed to these “spiritual reformers” to imperil moral seriousness, 
and also to destroy the very foundation of mysticism : that inward 
Divine Seed which in some mysterious way is present and active 
within every soul. These “spiritual reformers” were also akin to 
the sect-type in their insistence on the necessity for focusing fafth in 
a simple, experimental, and tangible unity of thought, as originally 
Luther also had desired to do, a desire which reappears indeed 
in every fresh impulse towards inward and direct religious experi- 
ence. It was, therefore, not merely the moralistic Anabaptist 
movement which strove against the ecclesiastical and orthodox 
tendency to develop this practical and simple heart of religion 
into a doctrinal system ; 477 the Protestant mystics of that period 
also threw all their influence into that effort. 

476 This has given rise to the suggestion that various “spiritual reformers” 
ought to be numbered among the Anti-Trinitarians, a group which in the 
average history of doctrine is still continually presented to us, whose members, 
however, belong to quite different connections, and which can only be gathered 
together in this group from the external, heresiological point of view. 

476 See p. 965. 477 See p. 965. 



PROTESTANTISM 


749 

Through this criticism of doctrine, and through the appeal to 
a permanent unchanging “Divine Ground” within the soul, 
which is only quickened into life when it meets with the Bible and 
the message of Christ, mysticism establishes another still closer 
relationship, namely, the relationship with rationalism. We need, 
however, merely to glance at the Humanistic theology, at Socirian- 
ism and Deism, in order to notice the important distinction which, 
for all that, still exists between mysticism and rationalism. 
Several Humanistic ideas have crept in, as is quite clear in the 
case of Sebastian Franck, Castellio, and Coornheert. But in 
principle a great distinction remains. Mystical “enthusiasm” with 
its constant “illuminations”, and divine “openings” and “com- 
munications”, spiritual idealism with its asceticism, its rejection 
of the “letter” and of the external knowledge of the senses, is still 
at heart hostile to the spirit of scientific rationalism. Scientific 
rationalism is more at home in the rational apologetic and 
scholasticism of the churches, and genuine rationalists, like the 
Socinians, preferred to remain within the churches, because 
purely critical scientific theology has no fellowship principle of 
its own. Where they were forced into a separatist attitude they 
certainly did create their own communities, which, however, 
were more like schools than religious fellowships of like-minded 
people bound together in love. Nevertheless, this kind of spirit- 
uality has many points of contact with the general intellectualist 
spirit of rationalism; and when its mystical glow fades it easily 
slips into it, as was the case with Spinoza, Edelmann, and a section 
of the Deists. 

Mysticism which draws its nourishment from the immediate 
perception of the Presence of God, is a process which is repeated 
everywhere and always in the same manner, and thus it comes 
into touch with the autonomy and universal validity of scientific 
thought. Both assimilate each other. Further, to the extent in 
which mysticism of the Neo-Platonic type bases its experience on a 
universal cosmic foundation, regarding it as the actualization of 
the Divine Spark contained in every soul, mystical religion in 
general becomes a process which completes itself in attaining to 
the knowledge of God through the intellect, and the redemption 
of the spirit through that knowledge. It thus leads to a Universal- 
ism which recognizes in all the concrete positive religions that 
fundamental process which arises from the essential relationship 
between God and the finite. In spite of its reverence for the Bible 
it still reduces the sense of difference between Christianity and 
the other religions, and recognizes the Indwelling Christ also in 



750 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

the non-Christian faiths. It places the universal religious con- 
sciousness which is interpreted as an inward necessity, over against 
an active and personal faith, which has an objective historic basis. 
In so doing, however, it leaves the realm of positive theology 
and enters that of the universal philosophy of religion. With the 
disappearance or decrease of the gulf between the Christian and 
the non-Christian world this school of thought approaches the 
system of comparative religion and criticism, for which Erasmus 
had already prepared the way. It turns its attention, first of all 
towards those elements in traditional theology and worship which 
constitute the greatest stumbling-block to the mystic — against 
the practice of isolating the Christian facts of salvation and making 
them static, which is so uncongenial to the mystical thirst for 
direct experience. The historic time-element and the magical sense- 
element are willingly handed over to a more or less penetrating 
criticism, and, in place of these elements, stress is laid upon the 
timeless and universal element which Christianity contains. Thus 
the full significance of this kind of spirituality does not emerge 
until it appears in mystics like Franck, Coornheert, and Castellio, 
who, together with their mysticism, had also imbibed the spirit 
of Humanistic culture and criticism. 

Finally, this movement exhibited a spirit of tolerance which 
went far beyond the Anabaptist demands for toleration. In the 
view of the “spiritual reformers” toleration did not consist in 
merely refraining from forcible compulsion in religious matters, 
coupled with the conviction that one’s own section of the Church 
contains the whole and the sole Truth ; it was a spirit of religious 
toleration which granted to each individual the actual right to 
his own convictions; its outlook is relative, since in all that is 
relative the Absolute is present. It was that relative conception 
of Truth which was current neither in the churches nor in the 
sects, and which alone completely eradicates the urgent desire 
for the sole dominion of an absolute conception of Truth. Luther’s 
strongly mystical statements about toleration sank into oblivion 
because instinctively he would not and could not give up the 
absolute conception of truth and Revelation. On the other hand, 
the toleration preached by “spiritual reformers” did gain ground, 
because it everywhere recognized Truth and Revelation in every 
relative approach to the one Truth, which, ultimately, could 
only be experienced in the present. Only among the “spiritual 
reformers” was there liberty of conscience within the religious 
community, whereas the sects and the Free Churches recognized 
liberty of conscience only from the standpoint of the State, and 



PROTESTANTISM 751 

alongside of the ecclesiastical organizations. But in this respect 
also this “spiritual” movement differs from strict rationalism, 
which, with its absolute demand for the truth of its ideas, tends 
rather towards intolerance, like the churches, and is only ready 
to tolerate the opinions of others out of contempt and opportunism. 
Real toleration was and is found only among those rationalists 
who have steeped themselves at the same time in mystical and 
“spiritual” ideas . 478 

These conclusions, however, only represent the final develop- 
ment of these ideas. Few of the “spiritual reformers” in early 
Protestantism went as far as this. Their chief aim was simply to 
breathe new life into the Christian movement, and to make it 
active and effective ; most of them therefore did not go beyond a 
Christ-mysticism of the type of St. Bernard. Schwenkfeld is the 
leader, or at least the type, of most of them. The doctrine of 
Original Sin, too, which increased the gulf of separation between 
the Christian and the non-Christian world, was indeed forced into 
the background by the idea of the “flesh”, and of that selfishness 
which revealed itself in external matters; but the underlying 
dualism was still rarely completely dissolved. These reflections are 
only modern deductions from these ideas, which were certainly 
latent within these doctrines, but which did not reveal their 
significance until they were developed to their full logical 
extent. 

The early “spiritual reformers”, even the most radical, were 
still very sure of their essentially Christian faith, and they particu- 
larly liked to appeal to similar “spiritual” expressions of Luther’s 
early period, when Luther, too, had expected everything from 
the Spirit who is contained in the Word. Everything centres in 
confidence in the Spirit, who, wherever He may be, is always the 
Spirit of Christ, and who Himself will make humanity Christian. 
Ecclesiastical differences are softened or even removed; but 
Christianity itself was not drawn into this relative outlook ; these 
results of a relative point of view were still only latent. The outward 
Church has been dissolved, but the inward Church and the sup- 
port which it provides still exists. The main interest of these 
thinkers is not intellectual but emotional. They hold that the 
religious spirit is not produced by criticism of doctrine and of 
the Bible, but by the opposite method. The starting-point of all 
criticism is the need for direct experience, the ethical seriousness 
and the sociological standpoint of the mystic or the “spiritual” 
man. Doctrines, so far as they are opposed to this, or which have 

478 See p. 965. 



752 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

become unnecessary for the emotions, certainly come under its 
criticism, which is further strengthened by Humanistic and other 
forms of criticism. The main interest, however, is religious, and 
the whole relative element is felt to be a possible point of view 
within the Christian position. This main religious and Christian 
tendency could not be destroyed until it came under the influence 
of modern natural science, and of the new philosophical systems 
which were erected upon this foundation. Only since then has this 
type of spirituality been fused with a really rational “universal 
Theism ”. 479 


The Ethic of “Spiritual Religion” 

The ethic of this “spiritual religion” also is peculiar. It is an 
ethic which aims at holiness and at perfection, and it reproaches 
the churches particularly for their ethical laxity and their effortless 
acceptance of the objective aspect of Christianity in their faith 
in the vicarious removal of the curse of sin by the Death of 
Christ. At this point “spiritual religion” seems to come very close 
to the sect, and often enough it has been fused with it. It has points 
of contact also with the Catholic ethic, which therefore it often 
praises more highly than the Protestant ethic. This “spiritual” 
ethic of sanctification, however, is quite differently interpreted 
from that of the sect. Its ideal is the untrammelled freedom of the 
Spirit; not control, community discipline, and the strictness of 
the law of the Sermon on the Mount. It was just at this point, 
too, that this school of thought came into contact with Luther, 
and it was fond of appealing to his earlier expressions of opinion. 
In the moral sphere, also, the freedom of the Spirit is paramount. 
Here again there is nothing literal and nothing external. Within 
this movement there was a strong sense, it is true, of deep opposi- 
tion to the world, a hatred of the carnal and selfish worldly temper ; 
in this respect it was much closer to the ascetic ideal than were 
the churches. As a movement, however, it lacked that other ele- 
ment of asceticism, the legalistic spirit and the practice of regular 
discipline. It recognized a method of degrees in the life of com- 
munion with God, and of self-discipline for the aim of “deification”, 
but it felt no need of a moral purification with a supernatural 
end in view, or of a gradual process of sanctification which proves 
the existence of a “state of grace”. This form of spirituality is 
as remote from the sober and legal spirit of Calvinism and of 
Puritanism as it is from that of the Anabaptists and the Mennon- 


479 See p. 966. 



PROTESTANTISM 


753 

ites. When it did take root in Puritanism (as in Dell and Francis 
Rous) it appealed to Luther and to Catholic literature. Further, 
there is at this point a distinct difference between Calvinistic 
and Lutheran mysticism. Tersteegen considered Count Zinzen- 
dorf superficial; the latter represented more logically the ethic 
of this mystical spirituality. The goal of this movement is an 
immanent, free happiness, which does good quite spontaneously, 
and which is as little bound to the conventions of men as it is to 
the moral law of the Bible. Nor has the idea of the natural moral 
law any special significance for this school of thought. Its followers 
prefer to speak of the Inner Light, of the Illuminated Reason, 
of conscience as identical with the revelation of Christ which 
awakens it to life. The primary aim of this ethic of freedom is 
the enjoyment and practical proof of personal salvation. The 
outpouring of the Divine Love upon the brethren is only something 
additional, though it is strongly and particularly emphasized. 
Religion is placed above ethics. It is perfectly natural, therefore, 
that problems of secular morality, of the State, of Society, and of 
economics are regarded as unimportant ; in fact they are actually 
treated with entire indifference. Wherever people attempted to 
solve these problems in smaller groups they either formed 
societies on the model of the family or the cloister, or they assimil- 
ated certain features of the sect ; every ethical experiment, indeed, 
brought the “spiritual reformers” into closer relation with the 
sect-type, with which they were already on the verge of fusion 
at many points. In actual practice both of these religious types 
were constantly merging into each other. The sect aspired to the 
inwardness of mysticism ; mysticism strove to actualize the sacred 
fellowship of the sect. “Enthusiasm” — the result of great excite- 
ment and of the oppressive hostility of the churches — also played 
its part in drawing both these groups closer together. But incon- 
sistencies and tensions, due to this partial fusion of the two types, 
still remained . 480 

This general description must now be supplemented by con- 
crete examples. In so doing we are as little concerned with a new 
presentation of the subject-matter as we were in dealing with the 
sect ; our one aim is to shed light upon the sociological significance 
and social influence of particular groups, in which their opposition 
to the group-fellowship and the social ethic of the Church becomes 
plain. 

480 See p. 967. 


VOL. II. 



754 


THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF *THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 


Thomas Munzer 

Thomas Munzer is the first instance of this pronounced opposi- 
tion to the Protestant church-type. At first he shared Luther’s 
views, but from the outset he was influenced by the mystical 
writings recommended by Luther, and he was also conversant 
with Joachimite literature. Further, while he was pastor in 
Zwickau, he came under the influence of the conventicles which 
existed in that town, and he imbibed their idea of a fresh outpour- 
ing of “spiritual gifts” before the swiftly approaching End of the 
World. His theology consisted of the mystical doctrine of passive 
deification, and the doctrine of the Holy Spirit, revealing His 
presence independently within the soul, merely stimulated and 
authenticated by the Word; this view he combined with the 
Zwickau fanaticism. From the outset also he united with this 
doctrine the ideal of establishing an exclusive community of 
mystical adepts and of the elect ; this ideal was broadened until 
it included ideas of communistic social reform. It seems probable 
that this later development was due to the influence of Hussite 
and Taborite ideas, because when Munzer was driven out of 
Zwickau he went to Bohemia, where he hoped to realize his 
ideals. This hope, however, was doomed to disappointment. 
From that time he developed still more strongly the idea that, 
since in these latter days the authorities had failed, it had now 
become the imperative duty of the laity to use violence in order 
to realize the ideal of the perfect spiritual community. From the 
same standpoint also he deduced the rejection of Infant Baptism, 
on the ground that external sacramental ordinances belong to 
“the flesh”. Munzer did not belong to the Anabaptists. It is true 
that the Zurich Anabaptist movement which had just come into 
existence welcomed him, but its members warned him against the 
use of violence, and they blamed him for laying so little emphasis 
upon Believers’ Baptism. 

Munzer represents a reawakening of mystical ideas combined 
with fanatical Hussite and Taborite revolutionary ideas. This com- 
bination, however, was merely accidental ; it did not represent 
a real fusion of these various elements. It can only be explained 
by the character and destiny of this restless man, who was always 
eager for peculiar and spectacular activities. In the end the waves 
of the Peasants’ War engulfed him. The so-called “Zwickau 
Fanatics” are also connected with Munzer, through his residence 
in Zwickau. These men, however, are of no special importance 
for our inquiry, save that of being representatives of “spiritual 



PROTESTANTISM 


755 

enthusiasm”, and the “spiritual” criticism of the sacraments, in 
the sense of an excited religion of the common people which was 
nourished by fragments of mysticism . 481 

Karlstadt 

The mysticism of Karlstadt was far more important and 
influential. It led to a passionate disagreement with Luther, who 
clipped the wings of his former colleague first of all by exile, and 
then by internment in a place where he was kept under observa- 
tion, until at last Karlstadt fled to Switzerland, and thus gained 
his freedom. Karlstadt also could not accept the doctrine that 
salvation consists in the mere acceptance of the forgiveness of 
sins by the soul which has trembled before the awful majesty of 
the Law on the bare authority of the Word, and its proclamation 
by the ministers of Christ. He also, after the manner of the mystics, 
conceived salvation to be a gradual process leading upwards from 
self-emptying to complete conformity with the Will of God. In 
his view this sanctification was to be realized not merely on the 
bare authority of the Word of Scripture, but rather by the free 
inward movement of the Spirit which is merely aroused and 
controlled by the Scriptures. Moreover, he felt that the genuine 
character of the purely inward process ought to be recognized by 
its practical results, by the ethic of love and self-sacrifice made 
possible through spiritual conformity with the Will of God. This 
led him — in line with the true mystical tradition — to exalt the 
“spirit” above the “letter” ; to a “spiritual” criticism of the sacra- 
ments; to the idea of a lay-religion of spiritually enlightened 
souls, who are to be shepherded by particularly gifted spiritual 
men^ recognized and approved as such by the whole “illuminated” 
group; to the free formation of congregations exercising their 
individual choice of such a “spiritual” man as their pastor; and 
to a strong emphasis upon the practical results of conformity to 
the Mind and Will of God; through these ideas he came into 
contact with the social reform movements of his own day. In this 
instance, as a result of his contact with these ideas of social reform, 
mysticism seemed to be approaching the ideal of the sect. In 
reality Karlstadt’s main concern, however, was not with the ethic 
of the Sermon on the Mount, but with the spirituality of self- 
negation, not with Adult Baptism as the sign of mature Church- 
membership, but with a “spiritual” explanation of the sacraments ; 

481 Cf. the article on Miinzer by Kolde: PRE . 8 , Gottfried Arnold , //, 14-17 , with 
the characteristic expression of opinion: “Even although at the beginning 
he may without doubt at times have received grace from God, yet Nature 
retained the upper hand’* (K. Muller: KG ., II, 310-326 ). 



756 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

not with the formation of a “holy community”, but with the 
gathering together of individuals who are freely moved by the 
Spirit, for whom all visible fellowship is a merely external matter. 
Although he withdrew from co-operation with Mtinzer, yet, later 
on, he did not join the Anabaptists. 

Karlstadt laid down his spiritual offices and dignities at a time 
when everyone was still making ecclesiastical experiments, for 
he wished to form a community at Orlamimde which in itself 
would not have been wholly against Luther’s earlier principles. 
Luther, however, was alienated from Karlstadt on the following 
points : Karlstadt replaced the doctrine of justification by faith 
by the doctrine of the degrees of salvation ; he set the freedom of 
the Spirit in contrast to the Word ; he linked the demand for 
practical proof of the reality of the inner life with the demand for 
social reform, and, above all, he assailed the rights of the patron. 

Luther’s passionate hatred regarded Karlstadt simply as 
another comrade of Miinzer, and a muddle-headed fool. So he 
drove him into misery and want, from which the Swiss churches, 
with their more lenient views of mysticism, rescued him. The 
conflict was, however, not a personal one; it was purely objective. 
It meant that an essentially individualistic, irreconcilable form 
of mysticism (which, moreover, had incidentally come into touch 
with the democratic reform tendencies of the small Communes), 
stood out in opposition to Luther’s idea of a mediated salvation, 
bound up with an objective authority, which, for that reason, 
was capable of leading to an ecclesiastical organization. Other- 
wise, however, Karlstadt tried to unite the “Word” and the 
“Spirit” just as Luther had tried to do in his early days; Zwingli 
also had made the same experiment. This is why the problem 
was never really solved. The only result of the controversy was 
that Luther coined some decisive polemical formulas which 
came into permanent use . 482 

ScHWENKFELD 

The doctrine of Schwenkfeld, and his organization of con- 
venticles, marks a distinct step forward. Schwenkfeld was a most 
delightful man, and one of Luther’s noblest followers and most 
spiritual colleagues in the cause of reform; his “spiritual religion” 
always remained moderately ecclesiastical. He had been influenced 
by the teaching of Luther’s early period, and also by German 
mysticism, particularly by Tauler. Later he came into touch 
with Karlstadt, and with the Basel and Zurich Reformers who 

482 See p. 968. 



PROTESTANTISM 


757 

were very sympathetic towards mystical ideas. The impulse to 
his particular form of mysticism arose out of his evangelistic work 
in Silesia, where he discovered the hopelessness of a people’s 
church which was simply a mass of baptized individuals ; his desire 
was to combine Luther’s “spiritual” idea of an inner circle with 
the Scriptural primitive conception of a society for worship 
endowed with spiritual gifts. In order to achieve this end the 
merely objective “Word” was insufficient ; what was needed was 
the quickening Spirit, as distinct from the “Word”, whose presence 
can be felt, and its reality proved by its fruits. Accordingly 
Schwenkfeld’s idea was that of the present inner activity of the 
converting and renewing Spirit of God, and the absolute necessity 
of practical religious and ethical fruits to prove the reality of this 
activity. In order to protect the inner movement of the Spirit 
from dissolving into a purely psychological process, like Luther he 
laid the most vigorous emphasis upon predestination and the 
self- witness of the Spirit as true in the elect. He admitted that the 
inward activity of the Spirit is mediated through the objective 
authority of the Word and of preaching to the extent that he 
regarded the Word or the Bible only as a vessel which contained 
a deposit of inner spiritual experience, and he admitted its impor- 
tance in kindling a similar inward spiritual movement, like that 
out of which it had itself arisen. The Bible was also useful as a 
standard by which the inner working of the Spirit could be tested. 
He also accepted the doctrine of the Atonement through the Death 
of Christ, but in this he laid all the emphasis upon the appropria- 
tion and imitation of this “dying of Jesus” through the absolutely 
real indwelling of the Exalted Christ within the elect. 

To*Schwenkfeld salvation did not consist in faith in the validity 
of the Gospel proclaimed by the Church, nor in the salvation 
which the Church holds in trust for humanity, but in a personal 
direct Christ-mysticism of dying and rising again with Christ. 
This belief led him to emphasize very strongly the great differ- 
ence between the “letter”, the “flesh”, and the “creature”, and 
the directly Divine element in life, the Spirit, the inward result 
of “election”. Above all, he deduced from all this the idea of 
the Divine Christ whose Nature must not be stained with any 
“creaturely” element at all, for even His human Body from the 
very beginning of creation was a spiritual and supernatural Body. 
This remarkable dogma formulated by Schwenkfeld, which is 
connected with speculations of the ancient patristic mystical type, 
and which also gives form and substance to the mystical idea of 
the process of salvation, was, in reality, only an attempt to express 



758 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

his desire to erppty the idea of Christ of all historical content 
while retaining the Christological dogma. 

One result of this doctrine was to empty of meaning the external 
sacraments. At the most they might possibly be regarded as 
outward tokens of the spiritual fullness which was already present. 
Therefore, in spite of the fact that Schwenkfeld rejected Infant 
Baptism, and that he happened to be on friendly terms with the 
Anabaptists, inwardly he held himself aloof from their movement. 
The only baptism which he could admit was the Baptism of the 
Spirit ; the only law, that which works through the Spirit, the only 
religious community, that which Christ Himself has brought into 
being, conventicles endowed with spiritual gifts and ruled by 
the Spirit, which, while they may continually change their form, 
are the leaven and the salt working within the visible churches. 
In Schwenkfeld’s theory these conventicles were to be smaller 
groups of genuine communicants, which were to be kept as pure 
as possible by means of discipline. The Primitive Apostolic Church 
has passed away; it soon became formal, and from the time of 
Constantine it became purely secular. The visible Church, which 
has been in existence since that time, and which at the present 
day is divided into four sections : Baptist, Lutheran, Zwinglian, 
and Anabaptist, may continue to exist as an auxiliary institution 
for the protection and furtherance of the true Church, the spiritual 
community of those who have been truly “born of the Spirit”. 
Connection with the State is an evil; force in religious matters 
is wholly unchristian. The conventicles are persecuted because 
they oppose the spirit of the world. Only an apostle obviously 
raised up by God, or the Return of Christ, will make it a final 
organization, or lead it to victory. Here again we see hofa the 
Chiliast idea always springs up afresh when there is a clash 
between universal hope and actual failure. This conception of the 
Church was certainly sharply opposed to the idea of a Church 
composed of those “born again through baptism” proclaimed by 
the Lutheran preachers, who were only thinking of a church in 
terms of a mass movement. This is why it aroused in Luther such 
intense anger that he soon made it totally impossible for “Stenk- 
feld” to live in any Lutheran country. Schwenkfeld was to share 
the fate of Karlstadt . 483 In a wandering life of self-imposed exile 
from his homeland of Silesia, protected mainly by aristocratic 
members of his own class of society, Schwenkfeld created con- 
venticles which consisted of believers united by ties of personal 
fellowship who shared in the life of the churches but abstained 

488 See p. 968. 



PROTESTANTISM 


759 

from the use of the sacraments, waiting for the settlement of this 
vexed question by the Protestant leaders. 

In many respects Schwenkfeld reminds us of Zinzendorf; but 
Schwenkfeld was much nearer to true mysticism than Zinzendorf. 
Schwenkfeld’s ideal was that of smaller groups within the churches 
who are to be guided and built up in the faith by a truly “con- 
verted” preacher, who, naturally, will be really effective; this 
pastor may, of course, be a layman. Like the Moravians and the 
Methodists at a later date, his followers were forced by persecu- 
tion to form independent communities of their own. Only a few 
groups survived these persecutions, and in Silesia, towards the 
end of the sixteenth century, they united with the Baptists. After 
1720 the few who remained fled from oppression to England, 
Holland, and America. 

Schwenkfeld’s ideal may be broadly described as a union of 
the sectarian principle with mysticism ; it was, however, influenced 
less by the sectarian and mystical tradition than by Lutheran, 
Scriptural, and Patristic ideas. It is non-ecclesiastical, with a 
supra-confessional outlook, but it also recognizes and uses the 
churches as the outward means of preparation for making the 
world Christian. The real rebirth of the Church is still to come, 
and pure conventicles are only a preparation for that consumma- 
tion. But this rebirth will be a work of Divine miraculous power 
and the outpouring of the Spirit before the End. 

The influence of these ideas was great and widespread. Nearly 
all the “spiritual reformers” show traces of its influence, and the 
English Congregationalists in particular can possibly only be 
explained from this point of view, even though their outlook was 
also’strongly coloured by Calvinism. 

Weigel 

Valentine Weigel, a disciple of Schwenkfeld, at a later date 
carried the mystical element a step farther, at least in one of its 
aspects. Weigel despised the mere externals of religion to such an 
extent that all his life he passed for an orthodox Lutheran pastor. 
It was only after his death that his writings made known to a 
horrified world his view that salvation was bound up entirely 
with purely inward, directly personal movements of the Spirit. 
He developed the purely philosophical foundations of mysticism 
in a very logical way, the idealistic conception of the idea of God 
in humanity. His ideas, therefore, are more significant for philo- 
sophy than for Church History. 4833 

483a See p. 970. 



76o THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Although the mysticism of Schwenkfeld remained within the 
borders of the Church, making a distinct effort to establish a 
relationship with the specific organized Christian communities, 
it went far beyond these limits in the most important and inde- 
pendent representatives of this school of thought. It became an 
entirely individualistic principle, akin to the critical Rationalism 
of the Humanists. Its spokesmen were distinctly hostile to the 
Reformation, which was beginning to settle down as an objective 
ecclesiastical organization. This is why the Reform movement 
regarded this type of religion as its most dangerous enemy, and 
pursued it with such deadly hatred and persecution. The chief 
leaders in this movement are Sebastian Franck, Sebastian 
Castellio, and Dirck Coornheert, alongside of Erasmus and the 
Reformers (Reformatoren ) . 

Sebastian Franck 

The most original member of this group was Luther’s contem- 
porary, Sebastian Franck. Greatly distressed by the sterility of 
the new teaching, by the impossibility of making men good simply 
through the proclamation of the Word, and by the inconsistency 
of a concrete ecclesiastical holiness which gave up all idea of 
subjective results, he resigned his post as a Lutheran pastor, and 
lived as a literary prophet of the sole redeeming power of the 
Spirit and of the Inward Word, supporting himself at the same 
time, like Paul, by the work of his hands. To him the central 
point of the whole of Christianity came to be summed up in the 
inward power of the Spirit, expressed in the terms of mediaeval 
mysticism, ascending through the different degrees from self- 
renunciation and detachment to the heights of ecstasy and deifica- 
tion. This power of the Spirit must then issue in the practical 
ethic of self-conquest and brotherly love ; beyond that the State 
and Society must be left as they are, since God permits them to 
exist. In Franck’s experience there are few genuine Christians 
with a personal experience, and most of these are scattered about 
all over the world without any cohesion or connection with each 
other, united only in the Spirit, and mutually recognizing each 
other through the voice of the Spirit. A Church does exist of those 
who have been led by the spirit in a marvellous manner into 
communion with God. This Church, however, is present to faith 
alone ; it has no external form of worship, no external bond, no 
outward means of grace and no mere authority of the “letter”. 
This Invisible Church is created by God alone. The very spirit 
which brings it forth, however, is a spiritual movement arising 



PROTESTANTISM 


761 

from the centre of the soul, from the immanence of God in the 
creature, from the Divine Seed and Spark in man; everywhere 
it is the same, since it arises out of the subconscious sphere, and 
harmonizes with the Spirit of Christ. This is the Logos or the 
Indwelling Christ, whose spirit is poured out upon all flesh, and 
it identifies all genuine piety with the Christian faith, which is 
visibly represented by the Incarnation of the Logos. The only 
advantage of the Christian revelation is that it is able to offer this 
universal, unchangeable substance of truth in a complete manner, 
since through the Scriptural tradition it is summed up in Jesus, 
who was filled with the Spirit, and in the Biblical writers, and it 
is from this source that the Spirit within us is quickened into life. 
This, however, only takes place where the inner spiritual Spark 
goes out in search and longing to meet the incarnation of the 
Spirit in the Scriptures. The Spirit alone can interpret the Bible, 
which represents in an allegorical manner the eternal inward 
truths of spiritual experience in the form of the historic myths of 
the Fall and Redemption; otherwise the Bible in its literal form 
is something completely human and historical which can only be 
quickened into life by the Spirit. This point of view leads Franck 
to a Theism which is expressed in the terms of the universal history 
of religion; it recognizes only an eternal and unchanging sub- 
stance of truth, along with an allegorical interpretation of Scrip- 
ture which is ever on the watch for the transformation of general 
conceptions into historic myths. This, again, leads to a universal 
philosophy of history, which interprets the whole of history in 
terms of an ever-recurring conflict between a faith which is 
directed towards invisible, spiritual, and disinterested aims, and 
an uftbelief which is bound up with visible, external, and selfish 
aims. Franck is, therefore, completely indifferent to churches, 
parties, or sects. In his view a new Reformation is unnecessary, 
since every reformation only produces a new Church. Of course, 
if a spiritual prophet were to arise, obviously sent by God, he 
might possibly be the leader of a new movement. But so long as 
such a leader does not appear all that can be done is to maintain 
an unsectarian, independent, purely personal, and individualistic 
type of Christianity, of sanctification and brotherly love, with 
no outward ceremonial and no external authority. Franck believes 
that the ultimate stage in the history of Christianity will be 
reached when churches and sects disappear, and the Invisible 
Church, the “community of the Spirit”, will alone remain in 
every land, to serve as the spiritual “salt of the earth”. This last 
idea is evidently a modified adaptation of Schwenkfeld’s idea of 



762 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

a coming Reformation through an “apostolic man”, possessing 
Divine credentials ; it also means that in the coming outpouring 
of the Spirit the Church will play no part ; the whole expectation 
is “purely spiritual” in character. In this doctrine Franck comes 
very near to the old mystical doctrine of the evangelium aeternum or 
the Third Era. From the point of view of his contemporaries these 
views made him an impossible person. Everywhere he was an 
outcast; finally he disappeared, leaving no trace. Through his 
writings, however, he continued to exercise a living influence in 
Holland and in England . 484 

Castellio 

Just as Franck was the critic of Lutheranism, so Castellio was 
the critic of Calvinism. As an outstanding Christian-Humanist 
and Principal of the College he seemed destined to become the 
Melancthon of Geneva. But a difference of opinion in Biblical 
criticism separated him from Calvin, who was the dominating 
theological authority of that period. From that time forward the 
great task of Castellio’s life was the protection of personal freedom 
of conviction as the palladium of a genuine Christian Reformation. 
As the friend of Occhino and David Joris, and as an admirer of 
the Theologia Germanica , Castellio based his convictions upon the 
spiritual and mystical doctrine of the power of the Holy Spirit, 
through which alone the Bible can be rightly understood, and its 
vital power experienced, apart from all human effort. He also 
shared the views of those who taught the doctrine of the degrees 
of the interior life, from detachment and death to self, up to the 
sphere in which the Spirit of Christ is in full control. He rejected 
the doctrine of imputed righteousness, and taught that forgiveness 
of sins springs out of the Heart of God, who reveals Himself 
through the Spirit, and who can only be conceived as angry and 
unreconciled by defiant and unilluminated souls. At the same time 
his mysticism was strongly tinged with moral and active ideas, 
and verged on an ethical Rationalism. Castellio was, however, 
never an Erasmian; his whole outlook was that of a “spiritual 
reformer”. His view of the Bible (which in his immense industry 
he translated into Latin and French) coincided with that of 
Sebastian Franck. Although he believed in the inspiration of the 
Bible, his philological and critical attitude towards the Bible was 
both inwardly free and amazingly bold. This was due to his 
theory that the Spirit alone can interpret the Scriptures, for He 
alone can recognize His Presence in the inner inspiration of the 

484 See p. 970. 



PROTESTANTISM 


7^3 

writers of the actual text. Above all, after the burning of Servetus, 
Gastellio fought for the principle of the relative character of all 
the outward forms of the Spirit, which, however, does not in itself 
destroy the identity of the Spirit. He became one of the great 
early champions of religious toleration based on spiritual and 
mystical ideas. He supported his point of view by appealing to 
the teaching of Luther’s earlier period, and to Sebastian Franck, to 
the theory of the separation between the temporal and the spiritual 
authority; in his view the spiritual authority may use no other 
weapons than those of the Word and the Spirit, in entire depen- 
dence upon their final and purely spiritual victory. This is not 
the toleration of scepticism or of opportunism, but the tolerant 
spirit of mysticism, which regards every kind of dogmatic formula- 
tion as merely approximate knowledge. Through these views he 
hoped to overcome the horrible physical cruelty and the moral 
unfruitfulness and dogmatic externalism of the Reformation. 

We cannot now discover on what grounds he believed it would 
be possible, under these circumstances, to maintain a popular and 
national Church, whose existence he accepted without hesitation. 
Apparently he believed in the invincibility of the Spirit, in the 
possibility of a dogmatic simplification which would unite all 
Christians, and he regarded excommunication or exclusion from 
the community (which he also desired in the interest of ethics) 
as a measure which need rarely be used. In any case he did not 
accept present conditions in the resigned spirit of Schwenkfeld, 
nor did he share his eschatological expectations. Living in the 
little town of Basel he may have felt that such an ethical simplifica- 
tion and spiritualization of the whole Church would be possible ; 
influenced as he was by Humanism, too, his ethic was more 
suited to practical life than that of Schwenkfeld or Franck. His 
enemies at Geneva, however, saw clearly how dangerous these 
“relative” ideas would be to the idea of a Church of the people 
with the infallible authority which such a Church would need. 
They denounced his idea of the victory of the Spirit and of the 
Word as “fantastic”, pointing out that we must not reckon on 
miracles taking place, for “we do not relieve the starving by look- 
ing for the intervention of angels, but we make suitable provision 
for them ourselves”. 

Castellio, meanwhile, had taken refuge in Basel ; his opponents 
tried to make his life there impossible, but they were unsuccessful. 
After his death both his published and his unpublished writings 
were used afresh in the struggles of the Remonstrants, and, like 
the writings. of Franck in the Netherlands, they exercised an 



764 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

influence which they were unable to exert during the lifetime of 
their author . 486 

COORNHEERT 

The important Dutch Humanist and politician, Coornheert, 
represented a point of view similar to that of Castellio. He wished 
to translate all Castellio’s writings, and he actually translated a 
certain number of them. At the time when he lived and worked, 
ecclesiastical conditions in the Netherlands were still unsettled. 
This was the period when the Baptist communities, which have 
already been mentioned, were being reorganized. Coornheert 
urged on his contemporaries the need for a Christianity of the 
“Inner Word”, which would reveal its reality in practical life. 
Entirely rejecting the idea of forming any kind of new Church, 
Coornheert wished to do away with all denominations and parties 
within the Church, and to retain no doctrinal basis beyond that 
of the Bible and the Apostles’ Creed. At the same time he did not 
accept the literalist attitude of the Baptists towards the Scriptures ; 
his one desire was to make way for the free inward dominion of 
the Spirit, who alone can open men’s minds to understand the 
Scriptures, and who witnesses to His presence within the hearts 
of men by the fruits of tranquillity, self-sacrifice, and brotherly 
love. He urged that the presence of the Spirit and of the Indwelling 
Christ ought to be manifest in everyday practical life, and that 
it should be actually realized in its utmost perfection. The Spirit 
Himself can convey the forgiveness of sins, and there is no need 
to refer to the supposed connection between the forgiveness of 
sins and the historic fact of the Atoning Death of Christ. This 
Indwelling Christ reaches out far beyond the actual borders 
of Christendom, since, apart from the Scriptures, the Logos has 
brought new light and life to many souls in the non-Christian 
world. 

In all these ideas Coornheert’s mysticism, like that of Castellio, 
has strongly marked rationalistic and practical features; he has 
no desire to probe into the deeper mysteries of the Trinity or of 
Christology ; he wishes only to see them made effective. Although 
he approved of the simplification of the Gospel proposed by 
Erasmus, he differed from him in his definitely Protestant doctrine 
of Grace, in his mystical strain, and in his entire repudiation 
of the visible Church. Otherwise, however, like Erasmus and 
Castellio, he made the Christian ethic harmonize with that of 
the Stoics, and in so doing he modified their “spiritual” Dualism. 

485 See p. 971. 



PROTESTANTISM 


765 

Under these circumstances his attitude towards the ecclesiastical 
organizations of his own day, and to the whole idea of a com- 
munity bound together by a common form of worship, is particu- 
larly characteristic. Like Franck he rejects the whole idea of a 
reformation and of the establishment of a purified Church, since 
he believes that the visible Church is inherently wrong. At the 
same time he holds that it is quite possible to take part outwardly 
in the old forms of worship, since a bad form of worship does not 
make a man bad, nor a purified form make a man good. It is 
possible to take part in everything and yet to remain inwardly 
independent and remote from it all. It is, however, also possible 
to take the other line, and to live in a spirit of pure inward holi- 
ness and brotherly love, apart from sacraments and external 
worship. Like Schwenkfeld and Franck he will only admit the 
possibility that a new Church might arise if a prophet were to 
appear endowed by God with supernatural powers . 486 He does 
not believe that he himself is called to be that prophet any more 
than any of the Reformers. Nor does he recognize this man of 
God in the visionaries of his day, like David Joris and Heinrich 
Niklaes. In case Christians may still think they need some form 
of fellowship, however, he outlines a programme of fellowship 
which is certainly most peculiar. Faith is to be based simply 
upon the Bible and the Apostles’ Creed, and it should be urged, 
above all, to prove its truth in practical life. These groups, formed 
on a free and voluntary basis, are to receive as members those 
who accept this very simple form of faith, and who avoid the 
grosser forms of sin. For the sake of the weaker brethren it is 
permissible to make a rule that obstinate and hardened sinners, 
and # all who oppose the Glory of God, should be avoided ; this, 
however, should be done without splitting hairs over trifles, and 
without censoriousness. For the sake of the weaker brethren, the 
sacraments of Baptism and the Lord’s Supper may be observed 
as outward signs of the New Birth, but all in complete freedom. 
There is no authoritative teaching ministry, but only exhortation 
from the Scriptures for edification. These congregations should 
be quite free, and no one should be compelled to join them. 

This whole scheme seems to be a modified and rationalized 
form of Schwenkfeld’s ideal ; indeed, in many particulars it 
resembles it very closely. It is, indeed, a highly Utopian Church- 
programme; if it had ever been put into practice it would 
have led to interminable “splits” in the different congregations. 

486 See Hegler, pp. 256 ff. As already in Franck this idea also reappears in 
Coornheert, especially against the Anabaptists. 



766 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Indeed, it could only have been carried out in the spirit of Castellio, 
and of Luther in his early days, through confidence in the spon- 
taneous power of the Holy Spirit to unite men’s hearts in love. 
Thus it is not surprising that its practical influence was slight, 
and that it did not arrest the development of ecclesiastical 
organization in the Netherlands. 487 

The Collegiants 

The later influence of Coornheert can only be clearly discerned 
in the movement known as the Collegiants, or the Rynsburgers. 
Their position was peculiar ; they represent a kind of half-way 
house between a Free Church (or sect) organization, and a purely 
individualistic mystical fellowship of kindred souls. Outwardly 
they were obliged to belong to the Baptist denomination, although 
they had no desire to encourage the establishment of a Baptist 
Church; when a number of Remonstrants joined the move- 
ment it became strongly tinged with rationalism. Pre-eminently, 
however, the movement bore the impress of the idealism and 
mysticism of Coornheert. 

The Nineteen Articles of Galenus Abrahams and Spruyt (about 
1650) declare that the Apostolic Church, with its obviously 
miraculous gifts, had long been extinct. They can discover no 
command in the Bible to attempt to erect it once more “solely 
by means of the Scriptures which are all that is left”, and they 
find no encouragement in the new churches, since they are all 
(including the Mennonites) divided by constant controversy. A 
prophet who can be compared with the apostolic teachers, and 
whose mission is attested by signs and wonders, has not appeared ; 
thus there is no possibility of restoring the Church at the present 
time. Therefore they declare that their Society is a purely human 
institution, instituted without Divine commandment or Divine 
authority. They base their whole confidence on the hope “that 
the Great Father of the Family will still be pleased with it, and 
that, in so far as their efforts are made in good faith, He will 
regard it graciously out of the depths of His Infinite Mercy”. They 
believe, therefore, that in the churches of their own day the office 
of the ministry, the various forms of service, the ritual, the work 
of teaching, and the sacraments of Baptism and the Lord’s Supper 
“do not possess the same value as in the Early Church”. The 
most that can be said for them is that “they are permissible if 
they are exercised without any claim to authority, in all lowliness, 
with patience and endeavours to rectify them, without any 

487 See p. 972. 



PROTESTANTISM 


767 

attempt to bind men’s consciences very closely to this doctrine 
and to the observance of the same”. Provided due care is exercised, 
“Believers’ Baptism and the Lord’s Supper may still be observed 
with profit”. The real truth, however, lies in a “pure inwardness” 
of spirit and in the Invisible Church. A more detailed declaration 
of 1659 says that “at the present time, when the visible Church 
is decaying, among many nations, there are believers, who turn 
away with their whole heart from all discord and from all 
sectarianism ; who in the midst of divisions possess an undivided 
heart, built up as a united body upon the one and only founda- 
tion, even upon Christ Himself, completely one in the ground 
and the power of God”. As in Coornheert himself, these senti- 
ments are a clear echo of the ideas of Schwenkfeld, although 
they have been somewhat altered. The only elements which are 
missing are Schwenkfeld’s pronounced supernaturalism, sub- 
stantial mysticism, and his eschatology. 4873 

Mystical Ideas and the Baptists 
It is also well known that a section of the Baptists adopted 
mystical ideas, and on that account both groups have often been 
identified with each other. These ideas, however, were only held 
by individual Baptist theologians and their followers. In itself 
the Baptist Movement was non-theological and needed nothing 
beyond the Bible. When, however, the more reflective minds 
within this movement studied the theological ideas which the 
Bible contains, there was certainly aroused in them a sense of 
need for a firmer basis and for clearer conclusions which opened 
the cjpor to a more spiritual religion, as soon as men wished to 
escape from the crude literal meaning or the inconsistencies of 
the Bible. Then, too, the fanaticism which arose in times of perse- 
cution, when men tried to justify their “new revelations” by pro- 
claiming that the new situation was the beginning of the End of 
the World, by the very fact that in making these statements it 
had advanced beyond the literalist interpretation of Scripture, 
had formed a bridge which led to a more “spiritual religion”. In 
themselves, however, fanatical Anabaptists and spiritual mystics 
still differed greatly from one another. On the other hand, 
mystical thinkers who wished for religious fellowship could not 
find it in the churches, so they sought for it in the ethical lay- 
religion of the Baptists. Franck, for example, made this experi- 
ment at one stage of his career. 


4478 See p. 972. 



768 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 


Hans Denk 

This was also true of one of the most human and attractive 
personalities of the age of the Reformation, Hans Denk. He was 
a disciple of Tauler, of the Theologia Germanica and of Humanism; 
yet, as principal of a school at Nurnberg, having come under the 
influence of Karlstadt, Miinzer, and Staupitz, he could no longer 
agree with the Lutheran ecclesiastical doctrine, which he re- 
proached for its ethical sterility, and its rigid depreciation of 
the individual in comparison with the reconciling grace which 
belongs to the Church.* 

Henceforward Denk led the life of a fugitive and a wanderer, 
which seemed the appointed destiny of souls of this type. For a 
time he was in communion with the Baptists ; in the end, however, 
he left them also, commending himself wholly to the redeeming 
power of the Inward Word, and of the Eternal Christ, who every- 
where inwardly creates His Church, among circumcised and un- 
circumcised, Catholics, Zwinglians, and Lutherans, if only one 
will allow oneself to be led by the Spirit into quietness of spirit 
and brotherly love. In his view, Christ and the Bible are the Spirit- 
filled means by which the inner “Seed” or “Spark” is quickened 
into life. God carries out His work of redemption through the 
kindling of this “Spark”, which is everywhere latent in every 
soul, and has to be fostered by the surrendered will; Christ can 
only be described as “Redeemer” in so far as he sets these inward 
processes in motion. But in order that Christ may do this, the 
Spirit must already be in man. It is only because the Divine Spirit 
in man meets the Divine Spirit in the Bible that redemption 
becomes a fact which triumphs over externalism, the flesh, selfish- 
ness, and worldliness, leading to the love of God and the brethren 
as the sign and seal of every genuine experience of salvation. 

It was because he held these views so strongly that Denk 
opposed the externalism which clung to the contradictory 
“letter” of Scripture, the substitutionary theory of the Atonement, 
the exclusive limitation of salvation to the historic Christ, the 
division of men into the two groups of the elect and the damned, 
as a denial of the Divine source of souls, the current exaggerations 
of the doctrine of sin, the division of man’s final destiny into heaven 
and hell, ecclesiastical Christology and the ecclesiastical ethic 
which compromises with the world. He admitted the necessity 
for the State, but he counselled Christians against accepting 

* That is, “grace” as a doctrine was exalted almost at the expense of the 
individual. — Translator’s Note. 



PROTESTANTISM 


769 

official positions under the State. Hatzer, Bunderlin, and Entfelder 
held similar views. They were disciples of Denk, and, together 
with him, they influenced Sebastian Franck. Theobald Thamer’s 
position was peculiar; he interpreted the Spirit in terms of the 
natural conscience or the natural moral law, a remarkable 
anticipation of the transformation of Christian thought into 
moralistic Deism which took place two centuries later . 488 

Mystical Natural Philosophers 

The mystical natural philosophers of that period, Ludovico 
Vives, Campanus and Servetus, Agrippa of Nettesheim and 
Paracelsus, enter far more deeply into the Neo-Platonic and 
natural philosophical argument for the Spirit, and of the struggle 
between the flesh and the spirit. From the religious point of view, 
they all represent an inwardness of temper which is indifferent 
to the churches, and a mystical love which overcomes selfishness ; 
most of them also remained within the Catholic Church, but their 
main influence was exercised among Protestant mystics. Servetus, 
in particular, in his revival of the Gnostic elements in the Bible 
and their connection with Neo-Platonic speculations, was one 
of the most interesting and brilliant thinkers of the day. To some 
extent Sebastian Franck also had been influenced by all these 
thinkers. 

Bohme, Gichtel, and Others 

The theosophy of Jacob Bohme, too, was founded on impressions 
received from Paracelsus, Schwenkfeld, and Weigel; from the 
religious point of view it was essentially mystical and combined 
with* an orthodox reverence for the sacraments of the Church. 
Gichtel, Poiret, van Helmont, and Fludd (both father and son) 
also belonged to the same school of thought. When all heretics 
were banished from Germany and Switzerland, they took refuge 
in the Netherlands and in England, where the spiritual piety of 
the period of the Revolution was, to a large extent, nourished on 
their writings. Bohme’s works were printed in Holland and then 
translated into English ; thus his influence was exercised in these 
countries just as Franck’s influence had spread to Holland and 
to England. 

Kepler 

Among great natural scientists, Kepler had leanings in this 
direction ; it is, indeed, otherwise a well-known fact that he had 

488 See p. 973. 

X 


vol. n. 



770 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

a close affinity with Neo-Platonism, which in principle is the 
underlying philosophy of all mysticism. He compared his new 
doctrine of Nature with the Bible in the limitation of revelation 
to the religious “intentions” of the Spirit, and through the Spirit’s 
“accommodation” through the “letter” of Scripture to the popular 
way of thinking and speaking; he also had to wage a furious 
conflict with the theologians, and he only saved his mother’s 
life (she was accused of witchcraft) by a heated literary con- 
troversial campaign. 

Comenius 

Another of the important reformers and prophets of the future 
who belonged to this group was Amos Comenius, the last Bishop 
of the Bohemian Church of the Brethren, who, after terrible 
sufferings, like so many others, found a refuge in Amsterdam. 
In natural matters, like the Pietists and Quakers at a later 
date, he was the champion of an empirical-sensationalist- 
utilitarian conception, which also formed the point of departure 
for educational reform. On the other hand, from the religious 
point of view, he held Chiliast views, and was a Platonist and a 
mystic. He looked forward to the spiritual unity of mankind, and 
hoped for the time when all religious denominations would 
disappear. Like Sebastian Franck, he belonged to the number of 
those who are secretly pledged to a better future; only to-day 
can his hopes be completely understood. 


David Joris 

The Jorists and the Familists belonged originally to the entirely 
different realm of frenzied and fanatical mysticism. The idea of 
the approaching End of the World, which was closely connected 
with the collapse of the previous Church — an idea often expressed 
by Luther — and the examples of the “enthusiasm” of the Early 
Church and of the Apocalypse, were closely akin to that kind of 
fanaticism, especially to that of the Anabaptists, with their exclu- 
sive emphasis upon Scripture. This expectation was intensified 
by the terrible nervousness produced by the horribly cruel 
persecution to which these people were exposed. Both these 
groups represented the development of a more settled mystical 
and “spiritual” movement which had emerged out of this un- 
disciplined fanaticism; thus they became significant forces in 


489 See p. 973. 



PROTESTANTISM 77 1 

the formation of the great mystical movement which issued later 
on in the English Revolution and in Pietism. 

The Jorists arose with David Joris, a Dutch contemporary 
of Luther, who took part first of all in the Reform movement and 
then in the Anabaptist movement. He sought to unite the two 
wings of the Anabaptist movement — the radical violent wing and 
the passive section — in the one supreme principle of mysticism. He 
taught a mystical ethic consisting of serenity and brotherly love ; 
but within his teaching there were some traces of Libertinism 
and Antinomianism, deduced from the principle of the freedom 
and perfection of the Spirit. The peculiarity of this movement, 
however, lay in the fact that he made this mysticism the basis of 
a community which, without worship or sacraments, was attached 
to his own person, since in wonderful visions he described himself 
as the herald of the Spirit of Christ, or as “the third David” at 
the dawn of this new era in world-history, of the Third Dispensa- 
tion, the era of the Spirit. At the same time he gathered round his 
own person a group of individuals, based on the family principle, 
for which in fantastic “revelations” and “messages” he demanded 
recognition from the authorities in Church and State. He claimed 
for himself that miraculous vocation which Schwenkfeld, Coorn- 
heert, and the Collegian ts had just as emphatically disclaimed. 
He united the sense of this vocation with his doctrine of the three 
eras of world-history, and of a special indwelling and unveiling 
of the hitherto imperfectly revealed Spirit of Christ, gathering 
all this up in his own person. This is why Coornheert, who 
otherwise agreed with his mystical principles, attacked him so 
vehemently. Joris was willing to conform outwardly to any form 
of religious worship ; meanwhile he lived in Basel as a respected 
citizen, secretly controlling a large and widespread movement 
with many branches, which likewise only grew in secret. Long 
afterwards radical Pietists were accused of being “poisoned by 
Joris”, for his writings were still being reprinted at the close of 
the sixteenth century. The indignant citizens of Basel, who had 
only seen in him a noble foreign gentleman of exemplary piety, 
were only able to exercise the law against heretics on his corpse. 
The modern sect of the Nazarenes is an interesting example of 
a similar movement; their prophet, Wirtz, claimed a similar 
position for himself and the movement was also propagated in 
secret; in other way? it was in line with the primitive mystical 
tradition, and circulated its literature . 490 


4,0 See p. 973. 



772 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 


Hendrik Niclaes and the Familists 
At the same time there arose alongside of the Jorist movement 
an important counterpart, the “House of Love” or the “Familia 
caritatis”. This movement was founded by a merchant named 
Hendrik Niclaes. Niclaes had left the Roman Catholic Church, 
and, without joining any of the Reform parties, he had swung 
over into a visionary “Enthusiasm”, combined with the familiar 
ideas of German mysticism, of “deification” and of “tranquil- 
lity”, of the “Divine Spark” of Light and Love; he also taught 
an ethic of religious perfection with its victory over “the flesh” 
and “the letter”. He found his sphere of influence, however, 
first of all in Protestant circles, since he represented himself as 
the Prophet of the Last Days on the strength of his visionary 
vocation and of his “deification”; proclaiming the well-known 
three eras of the religious history of the world, he took upon 
himself the role of the prophet of the last era. In this last era the 
inwardness of the Spirit is dominant, as it was formerly in the 
Primitive State ; pure ascetic holiness and love prevail, and that 
complete freedom from law, history and the “letter”, which is the 
ultimate sign of a full-grown fanaticism. It is, however, significant 
that this “prophet” did not merely bind the members of his 
community together in a personal way round himself, but that 
he created a hierarchical and communist organization. In creating 
this Society Niclaes had a twofold aim: (i) after the example of 
the Anabaptists, he sought to create the pure community of the 
New Jerusalem ; while (2) after the example of Catholicism, this 
Society ought to represent a holy priesthood; the second aim, 
however, could only be realized through an inner “election”. 
Coornheert also opposed this group, since it renewed the idea of 
the hierarchy, and because its fanaticism spoiled the disciplined 
simplicity of the Spirit’s ministry made known to us in the 
Scriptures. But these ideas spread far and wide, especially in 
England, where Bunyan transformed the allegorical mystical 
journey of the Prophet into his Pilgrim's Progress and where 
almost all fanatical phenomena could be traced back to the 
Familists. The so-called “Ranters”, in particular, a very eccentric 
“spiritual” group, were supposed to derive their ideas from them. 
At the English Revolution the movement disappeared. The 
Catholic-Apostolic Church of Edward Irving is a modem move- 
ment which bears a certain resemblance to the Familists. Along- 
side of these two groups there were still several smaller “prophetic” 
communities of a similar kind, but of less historical signi- 



PROTESTANTISM 


773 


ficance, consisting in part of the dissatisfied members of both 
groups . 491 

Labadie 

While these movements, which have just been described, arose 
at the time when the ecclesiastical situation in Holland was still 
unsettled, the Labadists represent a domestic community founded 
on monastic and communistic lines, in opposition to the Calvin- 
istic State Church system of the Netherlands. Jean de la Badie 
was originally a Catholic priest, and had been in close touch with 
the Jesuits. He fell under the spell of Quietism, and of the doctrine 
of the “Inner Word” ; he adopted Augustinian views on grace, 
free-will, and predestination. Finding that he had more in common 
with the Reformed Church he went over to Calvinism; he was 
soon driven out of France, however, and then found an enthusiastic 
welcome among the Dutch Pietists. He became pastor of a French- 
speaking congregation at Middelburg; here, however, he began 
to reorganize his congregation on the basis of the “Inner Word”, 
the “ladder of contemplation”, and of strict asceticism, striving 
to form a new community of the “Heavenly Jerusalem”. In 
consequence his old friends deserted him. Uniting the mystical 
principle with that of monasticism and of the Chiliastic Anabap- 
tists, he then created his communistic house-community, which 
was doomed to an unrestful wandering life until it finally dis- 
appeared; but during its short existence it had succeeded in 
scattering seeds of mystical thought in all directions. This move- 
ment thus belongs to the history both of the sect-type and of 
mysticism — a double aspect which we have been forced to admit 
several times ; this, however, does not do away with the fact that 
both types are distinct . 492 

Mysticism in the Netherlands 
in the Seventeenth Century 

In addition to these movements, about the middle of the 
seventeenth century a fresh tide of mystical life swept through the 
Netherlands, similar to the movement which was spreading at 
the same time through England. This awakening was in line with 
the Dutch religious tradition ; early mystical influences from the 
fifteenth century continued to affect the religious life of the 
country, for in the pre-Reformation period Holland had served 
both as a centre and a place of refuge for every imaginable kind 
of mystical movement. As we have already seen, the Pietistic 
491 See p. 974. 4M See p. 974. 



774 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Puritanism which came into the Netherlands from England led 
to a form of mysticism which regarded the ecclesiastical doctrine 
of salvation, public worship, and the story of Redemption as 
matters of absolute indifference. The younger Teellinck, Loden- 
steyn, and Brakel in the seventeenth century, and Schortinghuys 
in the eighteenth century, pressed this theory to its extremist limit, 
and very nearly succeeded in entirely destroying the connection 
between the “inner life” and the salvation offered by the 
Church . 493 Others, like the followers of Jakob Verschoor or 
Pontiaan van Hattem, tended towards Pantheism. The whole 
atmosphere provided the background for the ethic both of 
Spinoza and of Geulinex . 494 The Collegiants awakened out of 
their quiet life, and, in the person of Galenus, they carried their 
spirit of Independency, and of “prophesying”, and their doctrine 
of the Inner Light, into the Baptist movement, with reforming 
power; this activity aroused deep and passionate controversy 
down to the eighteenth century. New prophets of “enthusiasm” 
and of holiness arose, urged forward by the passionate tension 
caused by the great new Dutch struggle for existence against 
Louis XIV. 

Lutheran mystics and the followers of Bohme, as well as the 
heralds of French Quietism, spread their message far and wide. 
Quaker missionaries also awakened in the Netherlands the idea 
that the real Reformation of Christendom was only now beginning, 
since the Reform of Luther and Calvin had merely resulted in a 
fresh form of Catholicism, which had left Christendom inwardly 
unchanged. Thus, in the second half of the seventeenth century, 
mysticism in the Netherlands developed into a widespread move- 
ment, touching large masses of the population. It affected all 
classes of Society, even though the various groups differed greatly 
from one another. The Pietism which was simply the complement 
of the Church, remained quite distinct from the non-ecclesiastical 
“religion of the Spirit”, although in the end the Pietist mystics 
were only separated from it by their desire to remain loyal to the 
Church. 

In practice this “spiritual religion” usually gained a footing in 
the following manner : first of all it penetrated into the Baptist 
movement, which for some time past had already made its peace 
with the State ; once that had been achieved, and in spite of very 
strong opposition from the Baptist sect itself, it proceeded to use 
the Baptist movement as a kind of springboard from which it 
plunged into a purely non-ecclesiastical mysticism; then it 
493 Cf. Heppe, pp. 169-204, 375 - 489 • 494 See p. 975. 



PROTESTANTISM 


775 


revived the old passion for social reform which marked the earlier 
stages of the Baptist movement. This process of development, 
therefore, accounts for the fact that from the very outset this 
movement also revealed a practical, fanatically reforming ten- 
dency, a characteristic which it did not possess in the time of 
Sebastian Franck and Coornheert. However greatly these groups 
differed from each other, in this respect they were all one : they 
all repudiated the sacramentalism of the Church and the literalism 
of the sect, popular Christianity and external authority, and all 
the previous history of the Church from Constantine down to 
Luther and Calvin. Everywhere this movement exhibited the 
traits of an extreme form of the “religion of the Spirit”, with its 
radical individualism, its criticism of all literalism, authority, and 
doctrine, with its impulse towards “direct” subjective experience, 
and its exclusive dependence on the “inward Christ”, apart from 
external Christianity with its historical miracles. 

Its forms of fellowship were certainly most varied and curious. 
Some of its adherents, as we have already said, for a time utilized 
the Baptist movement, upon which they exercised an inwardly 
disintegrating effect. Others maintained purely individualistic 
groups of the “prophetic” order, or exclusive fellowship groups 
meeting in private houses like the Labadists. Others again 
sought to found new associations, or even denied all need for social 
organization at all, looking for the entirely free activity of the 
Spirit in a new era with a purely spiritual Church. 

Their ethic also was equally varied, though everywhere it 
reflected the main characteristic mystical asceticism, with its 
desire to conquer the “flesh” and the “world”. In individual 
cases, however, we find a purely passive Quietism, the purely 
spiritual, super-sensible freedom of those who have been “born 
of the Spirit”, combined with an entire independence of all the 
conventions of bourgeois morality, even in sex questions. This 
movement also revealed that asceticism of labour and the 
“calling” which is characteristic of Puritan Pietism; all this was 
combined with a more or less detached attitude towards State 
institutions, and the customs of Society, with fantastic expectations 
of world peace, and the renunciation of all use of the law, of 
authority and force, in every sense of the word ; above all, it was 
combined with that indifference to all morality in general which 
belongs to this type of extreme spirituality, and finally with an 
inner impulse to the most self-sacrificing labours of charity. In 
this ethical system, of course, the following ideals are taken for 
granted : toleration and freedom of conscience ; exclusion of the 



776 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

State from all religious matters ; the ideal of a State built up as 
far as possible upon love, peace, and the common good, combined 
with an active opposition to the existing order of the State, with 
its tyranny, its use of force, and its “carnal” selfishness. In spite of 
this attitude towards the State, however, the leaders of this move- 
ment stated explicitly that all reform must come from within, 
through the power of the Spirit, quite naturally, without revolu- 
tion and without external violence. Therefore, greatly to the 
annoyance of the presbyteries and the ministers, the civil govern- 
ment in general left these people alone, so long as they did not 
become a practical danger to its institutions and to generally 
accepted customs. Like all exaggerated idealism, this movement 
gradually faded away and died out. Its emphasis upon the “Holy 
Spirit of Christ”, which, indeed, it interpreted in the sense of 
conscience, reason, and Natural Law, finally (as usually happens) 
changed into rationalistic and philosophical reason . 495 

Mysticism in England in the 
Seventeenth Century 

The spirit of mysticism had a still more important development 
in the conditions created by the English Revolution. 

The English, whose practical sobriety and common sense we 
are accustomed to consider a racial trait, had their great mystical 
period. It is true that the mysticism which waits and suffers in 
silence, looking for deliverance only to the power of the Indwelling 
Christ, plays a smaller part than the more aggressive and practical 
forms of Christian morality, expressed first of all in the political 
religion of the Presbyterians, and then in the ideals of the radical 
Baptists. But alongside of and beneath all this more aggressive 
movement there flowed a strong current of “spiritual religion” 
which bore to the masses of the people the ideas of complete 
separation between Church and State; of a radical lay-Christ- 
ianity ; of freedom to preach and prophesy ; of an ethical renewal, 
springing out of all this, and characterized by readiness for self- 
sacrifice and brotherly love; of a pure doctrine free from all 
academic scholasticism, freely springing up from within. It was the 
impact of these ideas which first inclined the masses of the people 
to turn partly to Independency and partly to the Baptist move- 
ment. Both these tendencies were full of elements which provided 
a favourable soil for mystical ideas. On the other hand, however, 
mysticism also led easily to the conclusion that a Free Church 
movement was needed, in which the sacraments should be dis- 

m See p. 975. 



PROTESTANTISM 


777 


pcnsed only to those who were worthy of them, just as those 
movements were accustomed to proclaim. From this point of 
view also it was not difficult to persuade Puritan Pietism to give 
up its ecclesiastical way of thinking. Where mysticism steered 
clear of all these fusions, or freed itself from them, there it created 
groups which concentrated on “inward religion” like the 
“Seekers” or “Waiters”, and the Quakers, or orgiastic-libertine 
groups like the Ranters. Thus it came to pass that at this time 
mysticism became a power in the general life of the English 
people in a way that it had never before attained, and which 
it never reached again. 

The sources of this movement lay deep in the history before the 
period of the Commonwealth. Pietism had already opened its 
gates to mysticism through Hall, Francis Rous, and James Jane- 
away. Even under the Stuarts there had already been radical 
mystics, of whom John Everard, whom a Dutch writer regards as 
the precursor of Quakerism, is an outstanding example. Everard 
was a preacher and writer who lived at the beginning of 
the seventeenth century ; he translated Poimandres, Dionysius the 
Areopagite, the writings of Tauler, the Theologia Germanica , the 
Widerruf of Hans Denk, and other mystical works into English, 
while he himself, in his Treasury of Revelation , expounded the 
most advanced ideas of the “Inward Word” and of redemption 
through interior union with God. In support of his views he quoted 
from Plato, Plotinus, Proclus, Origen, Augustine, Bernard, and 
St. Francis of Assisi. During a life of continual conflict with the 
authorities in Church and State, in which he suffered greatly, 
Everard gained a large band of adherents, with whom the 
Fanulists and other branches of mysticism seem to have been 
fused. 

Further, there were the groups composed of the disciples of 
Jakob Bohme, whose works reached England by way of the 
Netherlands, and were translated into English at this time. 
This movement had a strong influence on George Fox at the 
beginning of his ministry, until he turned away from it because 
the followers of Bohme retained the sacraments. 

Neither must we forget the great school of the Cambridge 
Platonists, the real philosophical Enlightenment of the England 
of that day, which illuminated the darkness of ecclesiastical 
Aristotelianism, and proclaimed a mystical ethic of a Neo- 
Platonic kind. The rationalistic technical philosophy of progress 
of the court-official Bacon, which belongs to the same period, 
had no practical significance. 



778 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

The movement did not culminate, however, in this scientific 
intellectual mysticism which was based upon stable, eternal 
spiritual principles. There arose alongside of it, nourished by 
Baptist literature and Dutch influences, and intensified by the 
terrible confusion of the period, the “Enthusiastic* * mysticism of 
visionaries, ecstatics, and “prophets’*. This form of spirituality 
had a strong tinge of Chiliasm, while doctrinally it was entirely 
at the mercy of all kinds of sudden and changing ideas and 
whims ; still, it contributed something to the spiritual life of the 
day by awakening the desire for first-hand religious experience, 
and by the endeavour to prove the reality of its religious experi- 
ence in ethical and ascetic practice. Then, in a thousand different 
ways, this “visionary** movement merged into genuine mysticism. 

This wave of mystical experience was not confined to small 
groups, but it permeated the religious life of the time. Even 
statesmen and generals acted according to “lights** and “revela- 
tions”, and listened respectfully to the “prophets’* who arose at 
this time, believing that they might possibly have a real “word” 
from God. Cromwell, for instance, believed that further inter- 
course with George Fox would lead him into agreement with his 
views; Fox, however, rightly maintained that Cromwell was 
mistaken. 

Another element of the seething religious life of that period was 
the rise of the anarchic movement of Independency. Originally 
it was a purely Calvinist tendency which merely claimed the 
independence of congregations consisting of genuine Christians, 
but it subsequently developed the desire for liberty into licence. 
The Independents demanded and exercised entire freedom to 
preach, both for men and women ; they claimed to have received 
“direct illumination” from God and the “witness of the Spirit”, 
and they developed the inferences drawn from the principle of a 
regenerate community into a theory of advanced individualism. 
Alongside of the General Baptists, whose outlook had been 
strongly influenced by the Mennonites, the rest of the Baptists 
displayed their old tendency towards “Enthusiasm” and 
mysticism. 

Out of all these groups and influences there arose the “spirit- 
mongers”, as they were called by the bitter polemic of the 
Puritans. Thus we are able to understand how it was that both 
the great preachers at Cromwell’s Headquarters, John Dell and 
John Saltmarsh, were enlightened mystics. 

John Dell taught that the true Church ought to be founded 
solely upon the Word and its inherent miraculous power, because 



PROTESTANTISM 


779 


the Word is the spontaneous source of the congregational life 
which clusters round it : the one essential is to permit it to follow 
its free course, unhindered, as Luther had taught in his earlier 
days. When men raised this question : How then are believers to 
know which is the true teaching, and how are they to recognize 
the genuine Heralds of the Word? he replied that true believers 
were endowed with the faculty of recognizing one another. 
In Dell’s teaching certainly “the Word” is always the “Inward 
Word”, which is immanent both in the Scriptures and in the 
heart of the believer, which, like the Logos, is timeless and broods 
over both. 

John Saltmarsh preached the old mystical doctrine of the 
three dispensations: from Adam to Christ, from Christ to the 
age of the Spirit, and from this third era, which has now begun, 
to the Celestial Jerusalem. In this Third Dispensation there is 
no longer any need for the “letter” of Scripture nor for the law, 
neither for an ordained minority nor for an external Church at 
all; everything is summed up in the Indwelling Christ, who 
reveals Himself in love. 

We have already met these ideas in Sebastian Franck, Coorn- 
heert, and the Collegiants; there is also much in them which 
reminds us of Schwenkfeld. As in the mysticism of the Netherlands, 
there were many different exponents of this “spiritual” move- 
ment, and yet all had something in common. Some of them 
formed new communities of their own for worship; under the 
regime of freedom others accepted appointments within the 
Church, while others again strenuously opposed all official 
ecclesiasticism, and every organized form of worship. Some 
accepted the system of tithes and the official ecclesiasticism which 
was built upon it; others rejected both. 

This movement affected all classes of Society. Everywhere it 
was characterized by that asceticism which extreme fanatics 
easily transformed into the “liberty of the flesh”. All these groups 
found the question of war, and of an authority which is based 
upon external compulsion, the most difficult problem of all. 
Some held that a “holy war” was justified in “the Last Days”; 
others repudiated this idea. Some wished to recognize the State 
and the law under Christian auspices only; others were willing 
to accept existing institutions for the sake of order. 

The whole movement represents an enormous variety of ideas 
and opinions. Yet underlying it there was an immense Utopian 
idealism, which confidently hoped that the “Age of the Spirit” 
would make it possible to establish a social order free from all 



780 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

compromise with the world, which would be “Christian” in the 
true sense of the word . 496 

These “spiritual” hopes met the same fate as the dream of 
world-renewal cherished by the radical Baptists: they were 
shattered by the hard facts of political and social life. These 
struggles resulted in the Protectorate on the one hand, followed 
by the Restoration and finally by Whig Liberalism, and on the 
other by the revulsion from all Christian super-idealism, the 
secularization of the “Spirit” into Reason, with which Deism 
initiated the great period of the criticism of the history and 
philosophy of religion of the new era. All that remained of the 
mystical upheaval was “the Children of the Light” or the “Society 
of Friends”, as the Quakers called themselves. In the final form of 
their doctrine they are the direct descendants of the spirituality 
of the Reformation period, heralds of the Inner Light, of an 
individual rebirth through the Eternal Christ, in whose message 
the Spirit in the regenerate soul and in the Bible is one ; heralds 
of the presence of the Divine Light, that Light which lightens 
every man coming into the world, and which is only released 
from the prison house of the flesh when it comes into contact with 
the Bible. It would, however, create a false impression, if we were 
to interpret them from this point of view alone. In reality the 
Society of Friends represents the union of this mystical doctrine 
with the Baptist ideal of the pure and holy voluntary community, 
based on genuine conversion and freedom from State control. 

The Society of Friends 

The Quakers overcame the natural anti-social, or rather 
individualistic, tendency of mysticism by adopting the Mennonite 
constitution, and, above all, that of the Collegiants. Like them 
they have an inner and an outer circle, elders and overseers for 
poor relief, meetings and love-feasts, free lay-preaching — (to the 
lay-preaching they add the Meeting for silent worship, where the 
members wait on God together for light) — community discipline 
and excommunication. The sign of admission into membership, 
however, is not Adult Baptism ; the candidate for admission simply 
has to satisfy the Society that he is “converted” or “born again” ; 
the candidate’s outward behaviour is also taken into account, 
and this matter is left in the hands of the overseers. The free 
community of the Spirit must act on the assumption that the 
Spirit bears witness to Himself in the election of elders and in the 
acceptance of candidates. 


496 See p. 976. 



PROTESTANTISM 


781 

So far this Quaker constitution is very similar to Luther’s 
original “spiritual” ideal of a congregation. The problems which 
arise out of this ideal, in connection with the reception of new 
members and the election of elders and overseers, are solved by 
committing all to the guidance of the Spirit. But they had to 
discover through experience that this Society, formed by the 
Spirit in freedom, became, through the sheer force of the habit 
of community-life, an inherited membership handed down from 
one generation to another, a “birthright” membership, instead 
of the free adherence of all who are truly converted to the Society 
of Friends. 

It was not only their constitution, however, which linked the 
Quakers with the Baptist movement. In ethics also, like the 
Baptists, they avoided Antinomianism, took the Sermon on the 
Mount as their ethical ideal, and required their members to 
renounce all worldly honours and official position ; further, they 
were to take no part in war, nor in the administration of the law ; 
in all exercise of authority over others, on the positive side, the 
members of the Society were urged to practise a most generous 
love of the brethren, and charity towards the poor. 

At this stage of its development — as has been often pointed out — 
the Society of Friends represents the final expression in its purest 
form of the Anabaptist Movement. Later, however, like the 
Mennonites, to whom they were closely akin, they became 
distinctly bourgeois. They found it impossible to continue to live 
in their original detachment from the world ; more and more they 
combined the Calvinistic ethic of the “calling” with their ascetic 
way of life. Then God “blessed their business” with those eco- 
nomfc results which this ascetic Protestant idea of the “calling” 
usually brings with it. Thus a religious body which sprang into 
existence out of an entirely unworldly spiritual movement, 
developed into a community with an entirely different ideal ; in 
its ultimate form it exhibited the following characteristic traits: 
a high sense of the duty of labour ; the limitation of the kind of 
work which may be undertaken to useful and practical under- 
takings in trade, industry, manual labour, and agriculture ; strict 
personal economy and a minimum amount of luxury, with a 
maximum amount of effort for the welfare of the community; 
supervision by the Society of the business honesty and solvency 
of its members, of family life, of the education of the children ; 
in short, it is the same ideal as that of Geneva in the days of early 
Calvinism, the only difference being that this community is 
founded upon a voluntary basis. The Quakers, therefore, became 



782 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

bourgeois precisely because they had accepted the Puritan 
ascetic idea of “the calling” ; this only harmonizes with Bern- 
stein’s theory that asceticism is a “bourgeois” virtue, that is, that 
it produces the bourgeois attitude towards life. 

It is, however, particularly significant that, in the person of 
Penn, the greatest of the Quakers, who expressed their ideals in 
their purest form, the Society of Friends had the opportunity of 
forming a State and a society upon the virgin soil of America, 
with the aid of this most severe, and in many respects most 
logical, conception of a true Christian ethic. The Quaker State of 
Pennsylvania was the “Holy Experiment”, the creation of a real 
Christian State upon the joint basis of the freedom of the Spirit 
and a strict ethic. It was a State without compulsory religious 
organizations, and with complete separation between Church 
and State. In actual practice, of course, it was affected by the 
fact that the Quakers were in the majority, and their Christian 
spirit influenced the State ; this situation was maintained by the 
general confidence felt in the Quakers, whose representatives 
were continually re-elected to public office. In this colony, where 
civilization was only in its initial stages, the circumstances were 
favourable : the only possible conflicts that could arise were those 
between the colonists and the Indians, or with neighbouring 
colonies. Simple, quiet, God-fearing farmers, who lived in a small 
circle where everyone knew the affairs of everyone else, freed 
from all the hindrances of a crowded population, were able to 
simplify their lives and order their affairs in peace. They were 
able to establish relations with the Indians by peaceful methods, 
and within the State, at least in the beginning, most personal 
difficulties were settled by friendly arbitration, apart from lhw or 
compulsion. When this method did not succeed, no objection 
was raised against formal proceedings in a court of law, nor even 
against capital punishment. The exercise of force towards im- 
penitent disturbers of the peace was regarded as being in a 
different category from that of war; it was, indeed, considered to 
be the duty of a Christian Government to deal with such matters. 
Finally, after an existence of seventy years, this Christian State 
went to pieces over the problems of war and of religious toleration. 
This is how it happened : the colony was forced by the Mother 
Country to take part in the war between England and France. 
The Quakers then refused to take part in the administration of the 
colony, in order to avoid giving their consent to the imposition 
of war taxes. The result of this was that the other religious de- 
nominations in the State, which had always been tolerated by the 



PROTESTANTISM 


783 

Quakers but not converted to their views, gained the upper hand. 
With their loss of influence in the administration of the Colony, 
the Quakers also lost their spiritual influence. When the great 
War of Independence broke out, the Quakers had to submit to 
the tragic fate of being mere passive spectators of a struggle which 
was being waged, to a very large extent, for their own ideals. 
From that moment they came to the conclusion that public life 
was not for the Christian at all, and they gave up the “Holy 
Experiment* * for ever. Another section of the Society, however, 
among whom was Franklin, gave up the early Christian idea of 
non-resistance, and threw itself all the more ardently into the 
democratic movement, as a directly Christian duty. But the main 
body, which was increasingly forced into a minority existence, 
withdrew into the life of the religious Society itself, closed its ranks, 
and developed a magnificent philanthropic activity. In spite of 
that, however, the process of secularization was not arrested. 
The glory of this later period was the successful campaign for the 
liberation of the slaves and for the humane education of the 
negroes; while the Quakers were dominant they had already 
shown the way by personal example, and so far as they were 
concerned they had freed all their slaves. 

European Quakerism developed along similar lines, and it 
arrived at the same result, the only difference being that it reached 
its term far more swiftly than in America, since the detour of the 
“Holy Experiment” was absent. European Quakers excel in the 
economic virtues, in honesty, and in Christian philanthropy; 
lacking the propagandist spirit, however, they do not increase in 
numbers ; this also is very significant for the understanding of the 
religicflis life from the sociological point of view: the spirit of 
toleration and “inwardness” which is produced by opposition to 
compulsory Christianity is not favourable for the maintenance of 
an organic body. 

Within their own society the Quakers were content to solve the 
problems of Christian social life upon the basis of private pro- 
perty, honest hard work, and the care of the poor. Beyond their 
own circle they worked through philanthropic and humanitarian 
movements. It is particularly interesting that one of their number, 
John Bellers (d. 1725), recognized the inadequacy of these 
bourgeois ideas, and proposed, first of all to the Friends, and then 
to Parliament, a Socialistic scheme of productive co-operative 
societies founded on Christian, as well as economic, social, and 
political ideas. At the same time, however, he took into account 
the whole general situation — with its bourgeoisie and its capitalism 



784 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

— as well as the habits of the Friends. For all that, he went right 
to the root of the problem of poverty and riches, since, in addition 
to a better organization of labour, he also proposed a more just 
and equal division of the fruit of toil for the sake of the Gospel. 
Thus in the nineteenth century Richard Owen appealed to 
Belters* ideas, and found some of his best helpers among the 
Quakers . 497 

With Quakerism the wave of mysticism in England was spent. 
Even the Society of Friends itself increasingly lost its spiritual 
vitality. From that time forward either the modern bourgeois 
spirit of “enlightenment”, which took place in connection with 
the rise of the middle classes, or an ecclesiasticism, which, in its 
better section, was inclined towards Pietism, has been the 
prevailing feature in the situation; both these elements are 
characterized by that utilitarian spirit which Calvinism so often 
evinces towards secular questions, and which only too often also 
affects the spiritual life. 

Methodism and Pietism 

The second great period of religious awakening, therefore, the 
Methodist Revival, was not based upon mysticism at all. Certainly 
it felt a very urgent and deep desire for a direct personal experi- 
ence; but it satisfied that desire by indulging in “Enthusiasm” 
and emotional revivalism. We have already seen how sidely this 
differs from “spirituality” and mysticism, and how very differ- 
ently it works out in the organization of a religious community. 
The overwhelming effect of the Methodist Revival upon the 
masses, an effect which was constantly renewed and apostolic in 
its power and fervour, was based explicitly upon this embtional 
revivalism; it was along this path that Methodism was able to 
reach individuals and classes of Society whom it would have been 
impossible to reach in any other way. This form of “Enthusiasm” 
certainly contained within itself the danger of an anarchical 
individualism ; but, as we have seen, Methodism met this danger 
by a still more careful and effective system of organization, 
through which the individual was definitely linked up with the 
whole. Methodism is as masterly in the art of organization as it 
is in the art of revivalism. 

On its ethical side, the emphasis upon liberty and joy repre- 
sented the “enthusiastic” aspect of the movement, and might 
very easily have led to Antinomianism. Here, however, the full 
logical result of the mystical idea was forestalled by the introduc- 

See p. 978. 



PROTESTANTISM 


785 

tion of Calvinist austerity, which was the method which pre- 
served and made known the state of grace ; this point, too, has 
already been mentioned. The only really important result of the 
exclusive emphasis upon “spirituality” was an extreme simplifica- 
tion of the practical and dogmatic content of Christian thought. 
After the initial success of the Methodist Revival, however, it 
passed through the experience which, at an earlier period, had 
often befallen the Religious Orders, when a period of ardour and 
growth would be followed by one of complacency and stagnation, 
and a fresh reform movement would be required. Thus, in order 
to avoid the danger of lapsing into secularism and indifference, 
or even into a formal Church life, Methodism in all its branches 
has constantly felt the need for fresh revivals, sweeping the whole 
movement with the wind of the Spirit . 488 

Continental Pietism has been considerably influenced by 
mystical ideas. Pietism has often been described as a phenomenon 
composed of many heterogeneous elements; this is due to the 
fact [which applies equally to Quakerism and to various groups 
within the Baptist movementj of the prevalence of these very 
ideas. German Calvinist Pietism, which was largely influenced 
by the Netherlands and the mystical elements in English Pietism, 
has already been mentioned. To that we can only add, at this 
point, a brief allusion to the deeply spiritual poet, Tersteegen. 
Like Sebastian Franck and Coornheert, Tersteegen was entirely 
aloof from the organized Church life of his own day ; he acted, 
however, as the chosen leader of a group of mystical souls which 
resembled the fellowship of an earlier period known as the 
“Friends of God”. Lavater and Jung Stilling must also be noted ; 
as mystics of the Reformed Church it is true, of course, that both 
of them, under the influence of modern ideas of Immanence and 
of Humanitarianism, did not lay a great deal of stress upon the 
opposition that exists between the world and holiness, between 
the flesh and the spirit. Their faith centred in a Christ-mysticism, 
which was authenticated by experiences of “answered prayer 5 5 ; 
it developed a piety which was full of light and independent of 
all confessions, and it evolved a purely individualistic form of 
group-fellowship. On the whole, however, the mysticism of the 
498 For this Enthusiasm, see Lecky , II, 582-589, and also James: Varieties of 
Religious Experience , London , 1902. The illustrative material for this study in the 
psychology of religion is drawn almost entirely from this sphere. — For the 
mystical element in Methodism, which was mediated through Moravian 
influences, see Schneckenburger: Kleinere Kirchenparteien , pp. 150 ff. ; what Loofs 
says against this point of view in PRE . , XII , 774 and 779, does not seem to me 
to alter it. 

vol. n. Y 



786 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Calvinistic churches, after its first attempt to reform the whole 
Church on sectarian and ascetic lines, to a great extent retired 
into a mysticism which was indifferent to organized Church life 
altogether, and cultivated a strict holiness of life which bore many 
traces of the influence of Quietism. 

Lutheran Pietism was already far more predisposed to experi- 
ence a similar development, owing to the fact of Luther’s high 
estimate of mediaeval mysticism, and to the orthodox doctrine of 
the Unio Mystica. At an early date the Christ-mysticism of St. 
Bernard penetrated into and revitalized its dogmatic Christology. 
The early Lutheran ascetic writers and hymnologists, who laid 
great stress on the need for “inwardness” and fervour within the 
Protestant churches, were particularly open to influences of this 
kind. In this connection Arndt ought to be mentioned particu- 
larly. Arndt did not belong to the rigorous “conventicle” type of 
piety, and his tendency was wholly in the direction of mysticism 
and spirituality; at the same time he was always careful to 
maintain his connection with Lutheran theology, and he laid 
great emphasis upon the power of “the Word”. As a friend of 
Valentine Weigel, and an admirer of Paracelsus, with a thorough 
knowledge of devotional mystical literature, he instinctively made 
a compromise between the Lutheranism of the ministry and the 
Word, and the religion of direct inner illumination, between the 
dogma of justification and the doctrine of deification, between 
the radical doctrine of Original Sin and panentheistic ideas of 
Immanence — a compromise which is full of inconsistencies and 
contradictions, but which still possesses a strong spiritual vitality 
and influence. Arndt’s ideas met with a good deal of opposition, 
but the current of thought which he had set in motion continued 
to develop, and Pietism in particular was greatly influenced by 
it. This tendency was intensified by influences from England, 
the Netherlands, and from Jakob Bohme, in addition to those 
which emanated from the older literature of mysticism. On the 
whole, however, this school of thought did not advance beyond 
this position: it held the doctrine of the “degrees of orison”, or 
the “ladder of contemplation” which led to union with God; it 
adapted the Christ-mysticism of St. Bernard (rather sentimentally) 
in accordance with the tastes of the day, and it fostered a mystical 
hope of the Kingdom of God, which, however, did not expect the 
ministry, the Word, and the Sacrament to be entirely discarded 
until the spiritual Advent of Christ. Ecstasies and visions, miracles 
and prophets also formed part of the phenomena of the move- 
ment. Spener himself, whose scrupulous mind had little in 



PROTESTANTISM 


787 

common with mysticism, certainly loved the mediaeval mystical 
literature, and would often describe the Church as the “hidden 
Seed of the beloved souls in every Church” : a favourite phrase in 
English mysticism. With Spener and his disciples the emphasis 
upon inward experience and its practical results in daily life was 
certainly almost as important as the doctrine of justification by 
faith which constituted the Church’s treasure-house of grace; 
from that standpoint it was easy to pass on into mysticism, 
especially when ascetic holiness was no longer conceived in the 
Calvinistic sense, but was based upon “spiritual” and Quietistic 
ideas. Spener’s chief opponent, Dilfeld, was, however, only able 
to accuse him of “a subtile enthusiasm”. 

Franke 

Franke, who had adapted Pietism to the purposes of theological 
education, and thus to that extent directly assumed the existence 
of the Church, still furthered the “enthusiastic” side in many 
respects by insisting on the doctrine of conviction of sin, and of 
an explicit experience of conversion, with a definite date — a point 
of view which it is difficult to combine with a belief in Infant 
Baptism. This emphasis on the need for a direct “consciousness” 
of the “state of grace” had a certain mystical tendency. Thus 
Franke used to quote Tauler with great approval as an illustration 
of a praxis interioris Christianismi , and he also translated a treatise 
by St. Catherine of Genoa. This is why Loscher was able to accuse 
Pietists of that type of great offences against Church life: “An 
indifferentism which had the appearance of religion, lack of 
appreciation of the means of grace, and particularly of the 
preacfiing of the Word ; a tendency towards mysticism, Enthusi- 
asm, and Chiliasm ; a habit of talking about the “image of God”, 
in Nature, and in Man ; a confusing of Nature with Grace ; talk 
about “begodded” (deified) men; faith interpreted as experience 
and spiritual feeling ; the harbouring and defending of fanatics.” 

At this point the way for a transition to real mysticism had been 
opened up, but, on the whole, this did not often happen, for 
German Pietism is essentially definitely ecclesiastical, and “En- 
thusiasm” and Christ-mysticism of the St. Bernard type, which 
belongs to the non-intellectual realm of fantasy, did not appeal 
to it. 

Arnold and Dippel 

Apart from all kinds of narrow-minded groups and dishonest 
hypocrites, the only names we need to consider are those of 



788 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Gottfried Arnold and Dippel, both of whom, it is true, were men 
of outstanding importance. They were thoroughly individualistic 
mystics, who refused to join any organized Christian body at all. 
Their particular theories may be summarized thus : they believed 
that Christian fellowship only existed in its purity in the Primitive 
Church, before the time of Constantine ; that the significance of 
Christ and of Redemption consists in quickening the Divine “seed” 
which is latent within the soul of every human being; they 
emphasized the fact that religious men within the non-Christian 
faiths possess a similar faculty in the “Divine Ground of the 
soul” ; from the spiritual nature and spiritual unity of mankind 
they deduced the doctrine of ascetic holiness, and an attitude of 
indifference towards the existing social order which is based upon 
Nature; they taught that the “Inward Word” is the same as the 
natural moral law of love of humanity, and they looked for the 
coming of the Kingdom of God, in which there would be no 
ministry nor compulsory religion, nor a State Church. 

In the last resort these are the characteristic features of a 
Spirituality which is based upon a substructure of Neo-Platonism, 
combined with the Spirit of Christ, and through Him with the 
history of Christianity. From that position the interesting and 
sarcastic Edelmann passed over to a Monism which openly 
declared that historical Christianity was a sham and a delusion — 
a point of view which must have given infinite pleasure to Arthur 
Drews and his friends. 

Thomasius 

Christian Thomasius also belonged to the friends of the mystical 
“Indifferentists” more than to those of real Pietism with # whom 
he was at first connected. Upon that “Indifferentism” he built 
up his system of church-order, and sought to unite Christians in 
self-denial and in love, apart from the organization of any religious 
society, which, under present conditions certainly, always has to 
reckon everywhere with the positive order of the State Church. 
His anti-ascetic temper, however, separated him from the mystics, 
and thus he arrived at a Christian position which otherwise 
resembled that of the “Enlightenment ”. 499 

The Moravian Church 

The mystical element within genuine Pietism reached its zenith 
in the Moravian Church. The Count himself was its most out- 
standing representative — indeed, it was Zinzendorf who expressed 

4,1 See p. 979. 



PROTESTANTISM 


789 

this type of piety in a form which was intimate and spiritual, but 
also in extremely bad taste ; the language and the hymns used by 
the earlier members of the Church of the Brethren usually drive 
the modern reader to distraction. Zinzendorf no longer regarded 
Pietism as an attempt to reform the Church; to him it was a 
voluntary association of individuals who are united with the 
Saviour who is spiritually present and who can be found in 
the Word, just as he regarded the Early Church as due solely to the 
personal influence of Jesus and as a personal union of believers. 
He transformed Spener’s conventicle ideal into a form of free 
Christian social life, through which he and the brethren, in this 
community, guided by Providence, have been granted a special 
relationship with the Person of the Saviour. 

It is evident that here we are not dealing with a spirituality 
which regards Christianity as an all-pervading spirit, which is 
merely present in Christ in a special way, but with a Christian 
mysticism which retains the doctrines of the Church, while, like 
St. Paul and later St. Bernard, it entwines the objective fact of 
Redemption with the sense of direct inward experience and 
feeling. In this respect Zinzendorf was in thorough agreement with 
the Jansenists. The only difference was, as Ritschl, with his usual 
acuteness, rightly divined, that this Pietist Christ-mysticism, 
and especially that of the Zinzendorf variety, always regarded 
this direct experience as an entirely personal and private relation 
with the living Saviour, whereas the older Christ-mysticism 
satisfied the desire for a personal relationship in a much more 
general manner. Pietism thus looks back over the whole history 
of the development of Christian individualism, and already it has 
a tinge of modern sentimental aesthetic individualism. In other 
directions, however, the relation between Moravian mysticism 
and ecclesiasticism is most obscure. Zinzendorf always considered 
himself in agreement with Lutheran theology. In reality, how- 
ever, he only agreed with certain sections of Lutheran doctrine. 
With the ecclesiastical and sociological side of Lutheranism he 
certainly did not agree. As we have already seen, with the help 
of the Moravians, he was obliged to form a sectarian organization. 
This sectarian idea, however, was again and again contradicted by 
the Count’s peculiarly personal motive which was contained in 
his strongly “spiritualized” Christ-mysticism. Behind the strong 
emphasis upon a direct experience of the Living Christ, and the 
extremely personal nature of the soul’s relation with the Saviour, 
there lay concealed a certain indifference towards the historical 
aspect of Christianity, and a certain warm affection for individual 



790 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

religious peculiarities in their relative values. The disintegrating 
results of this type of mysticism began to appear in the so-called 
“sifting period” in Herrenhag, when Jesus was styled the “chief 
elder” in the Moravian Church; they appeared also in the stress 
which was laid on the “general spirit” of the Bible instead of on 
literal interpretation; and in the emphasis upon a “general” 
interest which extended far beyond the existing denominations, 
in the depreciation of the importance of religious denominations, 
which was expressed in the idea that they existed merely as 
different methods of educating souls for the true love of Christ. 
Above all, however, the exclusive emphasis upon personal piety — 
which the Moravians displayed in their practice of mutual 
confession, in their habit of including reports on the inner life of 
individuals, in their practice of reading aloud these confessions 
for purposes of personal edification — had a great influence, far 
beyond the borders of the Moravian Church itself. In this sense 
Schleiermacher and Novalis always remained true to the ideals 
of Herrnhut ; they merely developed explicitly the ideas which 
were implicit within them. In Fries also the clothing of the 
universal religious idea with an individualizing and relativizing 
symbolism was probably mainly due to the influence of the 
Moravian Church . 600 

Pietism at the present Day 

This whole world of ideas has endured down to the present 
day. It appears under various forms in the whole Pietist move- 
ment with its various branches, and also in the foundation of 
fresh mystical or even directly “spiritual” groups. There has 
never been a time when the old mystical treatises have not been 
read and studied, and people are still reading and expounding 
them to-day. These movements are undercurrents of religious life 
which mostly pass unnoticed ; socially, too, they chiefly affect the 
lower classes. To-day, to a great extent, they have joined forces 
with spiritism and theosophy; the only new movement in the 
grand manner is Swedenborgianism ; Swedenborg was really a 
modern Paracelsus, translated into terms of modern natural 
science; with his mysticism he combined occultism . 601 But these 
ideas, however, did not affect a large number of people: in 
America the movement is still in existence ; William James had 
leanings in that direction. 

fi0 ° See p. 981 . 

501 See also on this point Kalbe : Kirchen und Sekten der Gegenwart ; also W. Bruhn : 
Theosophie und Theologie, 1907. 



PROTESTANTISM 


79i 


Place of Mysticism within the 
Philosophy of Religion 

There is, however, another fact to be considered which is more 
important for spiritual life in general. This is the presentation of 
the ultimate spiritual meaning of mysticism and its place in the 
philosophy of religion ; this has become a matter of vital impor- 
tance to all the religious people of the present day who are either 
outside the churches altogether, or who at least do not belong 
specifically to a Church or to a Pietist group. The problem may 
be stated thus : when modern thought came under the influence 
of the conception of universal world laws, and of a universal world 
unity, which meant that morality, religion, and art also had to be 
regarded as universal fundamental laws for the spiritual develop- 
ment of mankind, the only hope of bridging the gulf between this 
type of thought and religion in general and Christianity in 
particular, lay in “idealistic” mysticism. Everywhere already 
mysticism essentially represents the same phenomenon : a 
religious experience based on direct and vital contact with God, 
which, in its ethical and religious content, was obviously related 
to Christian thought ; further, in the historical elements of 
Christianity, mysticism was able to discern an historical incor- 
poration and symbolizing of its own ideas in a specially living 
and primitive form, in so far as it remained linked with the 
historical element at all. All that was necessary was to connect 
this mysticism with the general psychological or epistemological 
ideas of modern philosophy; this yielded the common funda- 
mental conception from which it was possible to open up a way 
to the particular within the concrete religions, after the naive 
age-long dominion of the positive and particular, that is, of super- 
naturally established Christianity, had been shattered. The whole 
of modern philosophy tends in this direction. 

This, however, meant that the whole historical concrete 
element in religion became a problem, and it opened up the 
possibility for the most radical solutions. Since, at the same time, 
the historical element in religion was incorporated in a general 
historical point of view, and was thus open to criticism, very often 
the need for release from historical uncertainty led to the demand 
for the pure immediacy, present character, and inwardness of the 
evangelium aeternum , to the expectation of the Third Dispensation 
in which each individual, out of the depths of his own life, inde- 
pendently and personally, and yet essentially in agreement with 
others, gains his own knowledge of God. The ideas which Sebastian 



792 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Franck had expressed with such depth and clarity had again 
become operative. 

Mysticism of this kind lies at the heart of the philosophy 
of religion taught by Leibniz, however deeply orthodox this 
reconciler of philosophy and religion appeared. Spinoza had 
already taken this path. In a theistic and personal sense Herder 
and Goethe took this line ; Goethe had imbibed these ideas from 
Church History through Gottfried Arnold. Lessing, too, saved 
religion from mere intellectualism and criticism by appealing to 
the emotional piety of the Moravians. Kant, who regarded 
religion simply as spirit and thought, also treated the story of 
Redemption from this point of view, although in other ways he 
was purely ethical and theistic and not at all mystically minded ; 
his spiritualization of doctrines into symbols of eternal truths and 
ever-recurring present processes is entirely in accord with this 
kind of spirituality. There is no need to prove this in the case of 
Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel ; the two last have drawn explicitly 
upon the old mystical religious literature ; and the belated 
Gnosticism of Schelling is a “spiritual’ * theory borrowed from 
Bohme. Above all, however, in Hamann, Friedrich Heinrich 
Jacobi, and Lavater, it is obvious that their infinitely stimulating 
ideas spring either from Christian mysticism or directly from 
general “spiritual religion” itself. If they figure as the Theistic 
and Dualistic opponents of the Monism of the period, the opposi- 
tion is still only relative, and within the common whole. 

As the Monism of those thinkers was impregnated with the 
irrational character of the individual, and was crowned with an 
idea of God filled with an ethical content, so the Dualism of these 
was no mere Dualism of Natural Law and Christian miracle, 
but, rather, of externally mechanical Nature and fullness of the 
Spirit, in short of lower and higher nature. In them spirit becomes 
genius, and the physical is treated as an external intellectualism 
which is calculable and tangible. In them faith is treated as a 
feeling which the Presence of God effects in the soul, in which He 
alone and all His works can be experienced. It is obvious that 
here the old “spiritual” ideas are only being continued, or 
renewed, in a fresh form. The religious-philosophical element of 
Neo-Platonism, which Christian mysticism had assimilated, 
became ever more evident and independent, combined with the 
aesthetic colour of Platonism, which Christianity had set aside 
entirely, and which modern aesthetic culture has renewed in 
such a differentiated manner . 602 

502 See p. 981. 



PROTESTANTISM 


793 


The Romantic Movement 

In this movement of thought Romanticism was the most im- 
portant phenomenon; its religious element was represented by 
Schleiermacher and Novalis, and it influenced the whole group 
in varying degrees of truth and depth. Everyone who has read 
Schleiermacher’s Discourses knows that there is clearly proclaimed 
in them the “spiritual” idea of a direct revelation of religious 
feeling, and a mutual understanding of all Spirit-filled men and of 
all revelations, and that the sociological conclusions are also drawn 
quite definitely from these ideas : a system of loosely connected 
groups, varying from time to time, gathered round particularly 
strong leaders and prophets, serves to unite the faithful in ever 
new groupings for mutual fellowship, in order to awaken the 
spiritual consciousness which all possess; the “spirit” is not tied 
to the historic Christian community, but, reaching out beyond its 
borders, it can allow religious feeling, which is in itself everywhere 
the same, to form ever new concrete groups. The prophets and 
seers, Christ Himself included, are merely those who arouse and 
enkindle that spark of direct religious life which is the possession 
of every human being. 

It is undeniable that this conception has some connection with 
Herrnhut, even though the general outlook is determined by the 
main features of the modern view of the world, and the whole 
tendency towards inwardness and immediacy is intimately con- 
nected with the personality of Schleiermacher. However, whether 
this is simply an analogy or one which is based on history, the 
whole idea is very closely related to Protestant mysticism. In 
Novalis, Moravian Ghrist-mysticism was also placed within this 
setting; later on, Schleiermacher developed this idea still farther; 
here, too, it is, however, a genuine Christ-mysticism, i.e. the 
view which regards the whole of life as full of a power which is 
only concretely incarnate in Christ; the Lord’s Supper means 
that the believer is fed with the materialized and concrete Divine 
Spirit, who indwells the universe; the whole rite is a symbol of 
the unity between the Spirit and Nature, between the prophet 
and the community. 

This religious Romanticism possessed two most important new 
features: (i) On the one hand, under the influence of modern 
conceptions of law and world unity, the dualistic opposition 
between the flesh and the spirit disappears, and with that the 
asceticism which was so characteristic of the older Protestant 
mysticism. Whereas the latter had scarcely reconciled its ascetic 



794 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Dualism with the idea of Divine Immanence by means of the 
Neo-Platonic theory of Emanations, and further, within this 
framework, had made room for the freedom of the creature, the 
new Protestant mysticism tended absolutely and directly towards 
Immanence and Determinism. Where this was not the case, 
freedom is still only the principle of an ascending and victorious 
evolution, not that of an ascetic and dualistic opposition between 
the redeemed soul and the flesh which is tainted with sin. Hence 
the mystical religious philosophy of the present day has a strong 
affinity with the Pantheistic idea of Immanence, and the ancient 
idea of the opposition between the flesh and the Spirit is trans- 
formed into the idea of progress through the stages of an evolu- 
tionary process. (2) The second important change is the coales- 
cence of the fully developed religious “inwardness” and individual- 
ity with the aestheticism of individuality, with the differentiation 
of the altogether individual artistic feeling. This far transcends 
the aestheticism of Platonism which still always clings to the 
universal, of which we hear echoes from time to time in the 
Christian mysticism of the Ancient World, and which reappeared 
at the Renaissance. Under the influence of Christian thought and 
of modern life, this is an extremely differentiated aesthetic of 
entirely individualistic feeling. With that it is only too easy to 
combine that whole aesthetic relativism which regards every- 
thing as right in its own place, and as contributing to the harmony 
of the whole. Although Schleiermacher, Novalis, Fichte, Schelling, 
and Hegel all strenuously opposed this tendency, it has continued 
to grow and increase down to the present day, combined with the 
growth of an aesthetic world-outlook, and under the impression 
of the extreme variety in history. This double combination,* how- 
ever, signifies a most important complement to pure Christian 
“inwardness”. Whereas the older mysticism had absorbed the 
Neo-Platonic doctrine of deification, and natural philosophy, the 
newer mysticism now drew into itself the modern conception of 
humanity and aesthetic individualism. This meant that it was 
now able to play its part in the practical tasks of modern life . 503 

This religious romanticism, together with the aesthetic differen- 
tiation and the mysticism which is connected with the philo- 
sophical idea of Immanence, is the source of that which the 
modern German Protestant of the educated classes can really 
assimilate — his understanding of religion in general. This is the 
secret religion of the educated classes. Mystical and spiritual litera- 

508 Cf. also the article by Koch: <V Beurteilung der modernen Personlichkeitskultur , 
and the reply by J. Muller: Chr. IV., 1908. 



PROTESTANTISM 


795 


ture, therefore, celebrates to-day its resurrection. Lutheranism, 
in particular, provides a very fertile soil for these ideas, since from 
the outset Lutheranism had certain affinities with this type of 
spirituality in its most genuine form. This kind of spirituality 
meets with far less understanding in Anglo-Saxon countries and 
among Calvinistic peoples ; to them it appears unpractical, anti- 
social, non-ecclesiastical, and unethical. Yet from the literature 
of the Emerson group, and in the works of Carlyle — (Carlyle’s 
spirit was, it is true, actively ethical and not aesthetic) — even 
there (among the Anglo-Saxon peoples) this line of thought had 
been pursued for a long time : History is a symbol ; thought wells 
forth eternally, only reaching special intensity in the heroes of 
mankind. Finally the aesthetic spiritual temper entered into 
English life through Ruskin and his school ; this has rightly been 
described as the end of Puritanism. 

The sociological consequences of this fundamental position 
soon became evident. The religious community — both the Church 
and the conventicle — had lost all significance. Public worship had 
become entirely unnecessary, and without any meaning for 
religion. The historical element had simply become a symbol, a 
means of stimulus, while some went farther and regarded it with 
great suspicion. The historical element had almost entirely lost 
any connection with public worship; instead it had become a 
theme for scientific treatment, a subject for the free play of the 
imagination, or a means of stimulating certain moods according 
to one’s own private fancies. Literature, poetry, and the old 
Philadelphianism, the formation of small groups governed by 
personal impressions, took the place of the old fellowship in 
worship, just as Schleiermacher describes in his Discourses , only 
usually with much less earnestness. 

In the meantime also the Naturalistic Monism of modern 
nature philosophers, and Brahmanic and Buddhist ideas, added 
their quota to this confused mingling of ideas; moreover, all 
relation to Christian history, and indeed to Christian Personalism 
in general, was thrown into great confusion, or even into a com- 
plete break with the past and passionate opposition to it. But 
even where this complete severance from the spirit of Christianity 
had not taken place, or had not done so consciously, in these 
romantic ideas the tendency was to identify Christianity with an 
entirely personally differentiated and entirely inward spiritual 
religion . 604 


604 See p. 983. 



796 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 


Mysticism and Modern Theology 

The intellectual formulas of the newer scientific theology, in so 
far as they are in touch with the modern mind, and at the same 
time are seeking religious warmth and vitality, since Schleier- 
macher, Hegel, and de Wette, have also been moving in this 
direction. Certainly the need is here more clearly felt of doing 
justice to history and to revelation, but only on the fundamental 
assumption that salvation is not a static quality, belonging to 
institutional religion, but an experience of the union of the soul 
with God which is new every time it takes place. Therefore the 
meaning of history for faith has also become the central problem 
in modern theology. It is more closely related to Meister Eckhart 
and Sebastian Franck than it is to Luther and Calvin, and all 
that it values in Luther for the present day is his early period 
with its “spiritual” teaching. This all means the revival of the 
earlier mysticism. Its best ideas have either been foreshadowed 
in it or developed from it. It merely transplants them into the 
historico-critical method of thought which has arisen meanwhile, 
and into the modern knowledge of the world. 

This is the theology of subjective experience in contrast to the 
theology of objective revelation ; the sole value it assigns to Jesus 
is that of serving as the original stimulator of the religious con- 
sciousness. This, however, means that so far as the sociological 
situation is concerned it renews the experience of the earlier 
mysticism. It creates no community, since it possesses neither the 
sense of solidarity nor the faith in authority which this requires, 
nor the no less necessary fanaticism and desire for uniformity. 
It lives in and on communities which have been brought into 
existence by other ruder energies; it tries to transform these 
groups from confessional unities into mere organizations for 
administration, offering a home to very varying minds and 
energies. It is opposed to the ecclesiastical spirit by its tolerance, 
its subjectivism and symbolism, its emphasis upon the ethical and 
religious inwardness of temper, its lack of stable norms and 
authorities. Therefore it is obliged to utilize the forms of reorgan- 
ization which the more robust period of the State Church com- 
pulsion had created and which would have never arisen without 
violence. 

Sometimes, however, it goes farther still and envisages a new 
situation altogether, in which it will no longer be necessary to 
connect religion with the decaying churches. Richard Rothe and 
Hegel did not prophesy in vain that the Church would become 



PROTESTANTISM 


797 


merged in the State, that is, the complete autonomy of the 
religious “mind 5 5 directly united with the collective reason and 
its social organization. In an extremely instructive and deeply 
thoughtful summary of Church History 5043 Rothe has laid bare 
the ultimate tendencies and the most difficult problems con- 
nected with this form of spirituality, while at the same time he 
argues that this type of spirituality itself is the logical result of 
the evolution of Christianity. 

Sociological Results of Modern Spiritual Idealism 

All these considerations, however, help us to understand the 
sociological reaction which followed this Romanticism — the return 
to the earlier ecclesiasticism. Even in Novalis this was not an 
impulse arising out of Romanticism itself ; on the contrary, it was 
an attempt to guard against the relativity and radical individual- 
ism which resulted from this type of thought. As Novalis steeped 
himself, in his romantic way, in the study of history he realized 
the utter poverty of modern Society and of its prevailing religion 
in sociological content and the power of producing fellowship. 
From this point of view, and not without good reason, the mediae- 
val period seemed to him richer and more natural. At the same 
time St. Simon also expressed similar views; in his desire to 
discover a new form of social order, which he felt to be an urgent 
necessity, he turned to religious thought, and held romantic 
views of Christianity. French Catholic Romanticism also devel- 
oped along similar lines. The romantic outlook on history and 
the need for satisfaction through symbolism and imagination was 
only^one method of this counter-movement. The true spirit of 
Romanticism did not move in this direction at all. The new 
ecclesiasticism, therefore, freed itself as soon as possible from these 
unsuitable methods, and sought to replace them with others, 
which were contained in Pietism or in pure orthodoxy. To-day, 
in actual fact, within both the Catholic and Protestant Churches, 
the dominating tendency is the very opposite of Romanticism ; 
it is the tendency towards institutionalism, authority, and uni- 
formity. Nothing is left of Romanticism save its phraseology, 
which some theologians like to use who wish to be clever and to be 
considered “modern”. 

Such a reaction, however, in some form or other, was necessi- 
tated by the real nature of Christianity itself, which is never 
merely individualistic mysticism, but is always at the same time 
an ethical driving-power, a recognition of the fact that fellowship 

6043 Sec p. 984. 



798 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

is required by the Divine Will, and which, in the form of religion, 
can only be nourished by a living form of worship. In some sense 
or another, however, this form of worship must be the worship 
of Jesus as the Revelation of God. Thus even Schleiermacher 
discarded his youthful ideals of an individualistic “spiritual 
religion”, and returned to the idea of the Church, centring in 
the worship of Christ, as the original source from which religious 
energy ever flows forth anew. 

In Schleiermacher’s opinion this worship ought to be exercised 
within the territorial churches (so long as they exist) in great 
congregational freedom and with a large measure of elasticity 
for individuals. The whole unified body of the Territorial State 
Church ought to be penetrated with a Christian spirit working 
out personally through the individual groups for worship. It is the 
ideal of a synthesis consisting of the collective spirit of a Church 
and an individualistic mysticism, of a popular National Church 
and a Congregationalist Independency ; of the worship of Christ 
and the shaping of life by the Spirit of Christianity — an ideal 
which requires both from the congregations and from the ecclesi- 
astical authorities the greatest wisdom and broadmindedness, 
circumspection and willingness to renounce one’s personal views ; 
for that very reason this ideal was only realized in a kind of 
caricature, that is, as the orthodoxy of the Territorial Church 
combined with the compulsory toleration of liberal theologians. 
The educated laity, therefore, so far as it is attached to Christianity 
at all, has in reality a religion without a Church or forms of wor- 
ship, a Christianity of “the Spirit” and of disposition, a religion 
of humanitarian activity, and an entirely individual interpreta- 
tion of the intellectual aspect of religion . 605 

The position of Christianity in the modern educated classes is 
determined by all these factors. Another point which we must 
not overlook is the fact that certain religious types tend to belong 
to certain social strata of Society ; this fact has practical significance 
and gives to those types their permanent support. Certain sections 
of Society desire the sect, its stimulus, and its satisfying socio- 
logical organization which gives the individual a share in co- 
operative activity. Others again desire the Church because they 
believe that it provides those sociological and religious features of 
support and authority which form the most favourable equalizing 
and reconciling element for the control of the masses. In general, 
however, the modern educated classes understand nothing but 
mysticism. This is due to the reflex action of the atomistic indi- 

505 See p. 985. 



PROTESTANTISM 


799 


vidualism of modern civilization in general, of an individualism 
which in non-religious spheres of life is already losing its hold, 
and is beginning to develop into its exact opposite. In its depre- 
ciation of fellowship, public worship, history, and social ethics this 
type of “spiritual religion”, in spite of all its depth and spirituality, 
is still a weakened form of religious life, which must be maintained 
in its concrete fullness of life by churches and sects, if an entirely 
individualistic mysticism is to spiritualize it at all. Thus we are 
forced to this conclusion : this conception of Christianity, which 
alone meets the needs of the educated classes, assumes the con- 
tinuance of other and more concrete living forms of Christianity 
as well; it can never appeal to all. Rather, we may even express 
the sure conviction that Lessing’s prophecy of the Evangelium 
aeternum , and of the knowledge of God as the original and equal 
possession of every individual, will never be fulfilled. What the 
actual course of development will be, however, and what signifi- 
cance this modern type of “spiritual religion” will have for the 
future, no one can foretell. To-day the problem of the organiza- 
tion of religious groups is more obscure than ever. The growth of 
sects and of mystical movements, combined with the problem- 
atic character of the relation between Church and State, has 
produced a situation analogous to that which existed at the 
beginning of the period of the Reformation . 506 

This completes our survey of the phenomena of the sect-type 
and of idealistic mysticism. Although both these movements differ 
essentially from ecclesiastical Protestantism, yet both belong to 
Protestantism, since they reveal the ever-renewed aspirations of 
the sect and of mysticism which arise out of the Bible, and which 
accompany every form of church-type, in their specific and 
definite Protestant form, the sect in its final acceptance of the 
Protestant idea of the “calling”, and mysticism in its fusion with 
Protestant autonomous individualism. Thus we see that their 
ideals were already latent within the Protestant churches them- 
selves; the idea of the sect on the whole belongs to Calvinism, 
while mysticism is more at home within Lutheranism. Through 
Pietism, which stands midway between Protestant ecclesiasticism 
and sectarian or mystical piety, these tendencies have constantly 

506 Cf. my work entitled Die Kirche im Leben der Gegenwart in the collection 
which has already been mentioned called Weltanschauung , etc., and the article 
Gewissensfreiheit Ch. W., ign ; also my lecture Die Bedeutung der Geschichtlichkeit 
Jesu fur den Glauben, igio ; Eucken expresses the same views, a.a.O.s ., 136. 
Cf. also Harnack's Dogmengeschichte, 4. Aufl. Ill , pp. go2-go8. 



8oo THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

formed the complement of the Church. The early exclusion of 
the sectarian and mystical groups (which were connected with the 
democratic tendencies of the period) from the main current of the 
Reformation did a great deal of harm at that time to the popular 
influence of Protestantism, throwing it more than ever upon the 
ruling powers for support; this fact again immensely increased 
its natural tendency towards the church-type. But the ideas which 
had been banished reappeared; they then produced the Pietist 
movement, which has had a deep influence upon the churches 
until the present day, the independent sect-movement, and the 
idea of Christian Social reform, as well as that type of “spiritual 
religion ’ 5 which is either free from the Church or indifferent 
to it . 607 

Social Philosophy of Mysticism and 
“Spiritual Religion 55 

Finally, all that we now have to do is to formulate the social 
doctrines of these groups and their sociological significance. All 
that is required, therefore, is a brief summary of the various 
observations which have already been made, and a definition of 
the relation of these social doctrines to those of Catholicism, 
Lutheranism, and the primitive Calvinism of Geneva. 

Spiritual idealism and mysticism — to begin with the subject 
which we have just been studying — has no impulse towards 
organization at all. Only in so far as these groups retain their 
hold on ethical Christian Theism (and among the Quietistic 
and Pantheistic groups only under the pressure of the ineradicable 
natural urge towards fellowship) do these movements produce any 
form of independent social organization as the outcome of their 
religious ideas. As a rule people of this type care solely for the 
individual and his eternal welfare, while they believe at the same 
time in the universal fellowship of the spirit in love. Under 
certain circumstances they emphasize this idea of universal 
spiritual fellowship, but the idea of the Church and of religious 
organization is alien to their thought. Within that “communion 
of the spirit”, however, they only form narrower groups of a 
brotherhood [Philadelphian] kind, or of select circles of spiritual 
leaders and experts. The sense of need for public worship and an 
historical basis, in which churches and sects find the rallying-point 
of their organization, is not evident; it either disappears out of 

607 Cf. also Gobel , /, p. 145. This is also the right element in Barge's Gesamtan - 
schauung vom Verlauf der Reformation , which manifests very little understanding 
of the Church-type, but is accurate in its main characteristics. 



PROTESTANTISM 


801 


sight altogether, or it is changed into a strong emphasis upon a 
personal direct relation with God and Christ, or into spiritual 
exaltation. It is, of course, true to say that these tendencies have a 
sociological fundamental theory, a union of the hearts of all in 
one common aim, and a complete toleration of all other souls on 
an equal basis, because, as Lagarde says, “upon the ascent 
towards God the various lines do not cut across each other but 
converge and meet”. People of this type, however, do not carry 
this fundamental theory systematically and actively into Society. 

This fundamental theory is of value only for those who are 
seeking and experiencing God, and for those who are illuminated 
by Him, and its power can only be extended as the Spirit is shed 
abroad in the hearts of men. Here nothing can be planned and 
organized. The question is only how far this spirit will work of 
itself, and in this respect individuals differ according to tempera- 
ment. Resignation, a sense of superiority, pessimism, Quietism, 
and optimistic expectations all have their place within this 
movement. The result is, naturally, that there is a complete 
indifference, or impotence towards all social problems which lie 
outside the directly religious sphere. Fundamentally, this school 
of thought has no idea at all of the way in which to deal with 
questions of the State or of economics ; it only knows that every- 
thing ought to be altered and begun entirely afresh. When? And 
how? It is, indeed, hard to say. As we can understand, it is only 
within the sphere of the sex ethic and of the family that this type 
of thought displays features which are peculiar to itself, since 
these matters are very closely connected with an entirely personal 
intimate valuation of life. In this respect it is very independent 
and unconventional. Its aim is to spiritualize these most important 
processes, which have such a strong influence on the emotional 
life ; it wishes to effect the fusion of the erotic with the ethical and 
religious element. This is the reason for those phenomena known 
as Antinomianism and Libertinism, of which, both rightly and 
wrongly, these circles have constantly been accused. To-day it is 
just these circles which deal most finely with the problem of sex 
ethics. The spirit of restraint and the possibility of penetrating 
erotic relationships with religious feeling, or also, on the contrary, 
ascetic misgivings about the erotic competition of feeling, are here 
emphasized, and from this standpoint they develop marriage 
ideals which are in strong opposition to the conventional legal 
“property-regarding” viewpoint of marriage, which is legitimate 
from the standpoint of the Church. The very fluctuating details 
connected with this point of view could only be described within 

VOL. II. z 



802 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

the framework of a monograph, but they would present many 
features of great interest. In any case, the connection between 
erotic and religious feeling which in this interior subjectivity 
makes possible a mutual penetration of both, and which does 
away with the coarse ecclesiastical doctrine of concupiscence as 
the result of the Fall, is important. When, however, great idealistic 
mystical thinkers of recent times, like Schleiermacher and Richard 
Rothe, deal with ethics in connection with the practical tasks of 
civilization, their ideas proceed obviously and avowedly from the 
modern world of thought. The difficulty, then, is how to fuse this 
world of thought with Christian spirituality and its supernatural 
character. Rothe, in particular, is a very characteristic example 
of the difficulty of this task . 608 

Turning to the question of the sect, we find that it falls into the 
same divisions which characterized it in the Middle Ages: the 
aggressive, world-reforming type, and the type which endures 
persecution and contempt with patience and is indifferent to 
the world. 

Social Doctrines of the Aggressive Sects 

The aggressive type with its apocalyptic violence burnt itself 
out in the seventeenth century, but through the Great Rebellion 
in England it has certainly exerted an immense influence on 
world history. The only relic of it which now remains is that 
Christian Socialism which, logically or otherwise, and by very 
varied methods, attempts to bring in a new order of Society which 
shall be in harmony both with the Will of God and with reason. 

In Catholicism, which in any case only takes up this problem 
in inter-confessional groups, the sect-type has been almost entirely 
obliterated. There, ultimately, the idea is simply to introduce a 
new class into the social organism which is directed by the Church, 
whose inner harmony will thus be restored by the grace and power 
given to the Church and to its controlling authority; naturally 
that docs not exclude a very energetic and successful activity 
along certain lines, all the more since it has the immense influence 
of the Church behind it. 

Within Calvinism, Christian Socialism finds its main expression 
in the formation of associations, in the endeavour to influence 
public opinion, and in the establishment of co-operative societies. 
Within Lutheranism, where it had no point of contact within the 
churches at all, it has had the greatest development in theory. 
There also, however, it falls into two sections : first there is the 

608 See p. 986. 



PROTESTANTISM 


803 

school of thought which merely tries to influence the general 
ethical temper and to bring the spirit of reconciliation into the 
class war, and there is another, which believes that a socialistic 
renewal of the whole constitution of Society is a Christian duty ; 
and which believes that this movement should be incorporated 
into the steady upward march of progress which is willed by God. 
Of course it is only natural that particular social and ethical 
problems should pale in importance before these general prob- 
lems, which are of fundamental significance. Either they break 
up into an infinite number of questions of detail, or they disappear 
altogether in the very vague and general sketch of a future social 
order. Their special features, which, in part, are very instructive, 
could only be made clear in a special monograph . 60824 

In our present inquiry all that matters is that we should gain 
a thorough insight into the association of ideas. This study, 
however, throws much light on the whole problem of the relation 
of Christianity to the idea of social reform, and forms a definite 
conclusion to the observations on this subject, which have already 
been stated. 

In this respect the Gospel was completely ideological and 
indifferent towards the world, whose transformation it only ex- 
pected from the great miracle of the coming Kingdom of God ; 
in great things as in small it left everything entirely to God ; the 
only thing which was taken into account was the view that the 
poor and the suffering were in a more advantageous position than 
others, since they feel more warmly and humbly towards God; 
beyond that it regarded every act of love which the opportunity 
required as the exercise of the right attitude towards God. The 
Ancient Church absorbed the world into its own life, making a 
few absolutely necessary changes while it preserved a spirit of 
interior detachment from it, and in order to overcome material 
distress it began the work of philanthropy. 

The mediaeval period produced a relative harmony between 
the actual situation and the Christian ideal ; but it only developed 
the dominion of the Church over this life-harmony of Nature and 
Supernature, and dealt with social wrongs no longer through the 
Church and the congregation, but through institutional monastic 
charity, which was made possible by the endowment system. 

Lutheranism left all secular questions to a government which 
was guided by the Gospel, leaving it to struggle with the existing 
difficulties as best it could, certain that the Gospel possesses the 

* 08a On this point see the various works of Ragaz and Rauschcnbusch, which 
have already been mentioned above. 



804 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

power to inspire and establish the order of Nature through 
love. 

Calvinism, which had adopted the sect-ideal of the Holy 
Community, and had come to terms with the State Church spirit, 
for the first time, alongside of the sects, set a Christian social 
ideal in the forefront of its life ; it did this, however, in a thoroughly 
conservative sense ; it held that the existing civil order of the State 
should be maintained, on the assumption that this social order, 
guided by relative Natural Law, along with good-will and the 
necessary earnestness in the pursuit of holiness, could be made 
the foundation of a truly Christian social order. 

The idea of a radical social reform, which regards the existing 
order of Society and property as radically incapable of developing 
Christian personality and Christian love in any comprehensive 
way, was held only by the sects, and by them only in the measure 
in which they passed from patient endurance of persecution, under 
the influence of the eschatological idea of the Kingdom of God 
and in the expectation of its speedy realization, into the attitude 
of a thoroughgoing reform according to the ideal of the Kingdom 
of God and of primitive Reason. Further, the more the idea of the 
Natural Law of the Stoics agreed with these hopes, the more this 
reform became democratic and communistic. These were the sole 
supporters of a Christian social ethic which was radical, allowed 
no compromise, and did not accept the existing social order. 

Then Christian Socialism arose, with its penetrating criticism 
of the existing social order. It threw out a clear challenge, claim- 
ing that the urgency of the situation demanded either a radical 
change in the fundamental social outlook, or the destruction of 
the present economic system in order to make room for a new 
social order, which would be in harmony with the ideals which 
also dominate the Socialistic Reform parties, groups which have 
sprung into existence under the pressure of the economic situa- 
tion. These demands show, however, that Christian Socialism 
again is fired with the old spirit of the aggressive sect; like it, 
it interprets the movements of the day as a challenge to change 
the whole principle of the existing order, a change which can 
be effected by God alone; it renews the hope of realizing the 
Kingdom of God upon earth, and revives the sense of the in- 
timate connection between mind and body; and its ideals bear 
a close resemblance to the ancient Stoic-Christian conceptions 
of absolute Natural Law. Modem ideas of Immanence, and of 
the importance of secular civilization, have also had some in- 
fluence upon it. It regards itself as the product of intellectual, 



PROTESTANTISM 


805 

cultural, and technical development. For Christian Socialism, 
therefore, the day of ascetic “Enthusiasm” and Dualism is past. 
No longer, like the early sects, does it supplement the social 
message of the Gospel by ideas drawn from the Old Testament 
and the Apocalypse, but it utilizes the conclusions of modern 
social science, and the technological conception of progress. It 
therefore renounces the apocalyptic revolutionary idea of violence, 
and looks for a revolution only from within. In so doing, however, 
it severs itself from the Church of the present day not so much 
from the actual institution as from its inner spirit. On the whole, 
the Church requires the masses to acquiesce in existing social 
conditions because they have been appointed by God ; moreover, 
since it is essentially on the side of law and order, its only idea 
of social reform is charitable activity and a Christian control of 
the civil order. Socialistic churches are nonsense. The task 
of the Church is something different from radical-ethical en- 
deavour and the re-ordering of life. But a Christian Socialism 
which is separate from the Church in spirit can appeal to the 
Gospel. The Christian piety of the churches is inwardly very 
different in its outlook from that of a free community, earnestly 
endeavouring to bring in the Kingdom of God. At the same time, 
of course, there are numerous points of contact between the two 
schools of thought. The heart of the problem, however, lies in 
the contrast between an ecclesiastical institution realistically 
focused towards mankind and a free voluntary community 
unconditionally striving after the ideal. 

The Non-Aggressive Sect and Neo-Calvinism 
Th£ passive persecuted sect is represented by the Mennonites, 
the Baptists, the Quakers, the groups which came into being 
through Pietism, and the modern sects. It also has assumed a 
different character from that of its mediaeval and early Pro- 
testant ancestors, like the Waldensians, the Bohemian Brethren, 
and the early Protestant Baptists. They have given up their 
previous attitude of passive resistance, and have accepted the 
State, Society, and the economic order. Based on the Protestant 
ethic of the “calling”, they have all developed into groups 
which, in the sociological sense, must be described as “bourgeois”, 
and which therefore accept existing conditions. Their only con- 
tribution to social reform lies in the sphere of Home Missions 
through evangelistic work and social service, coupled with an 
influence on Society through Christian public opinion and the 
Press. This middle-class development, and the adoption of the 



806 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

ethic of the “calling”, is a natural result of the change in its 
own position, due to a more settled existence, increase in 
numbers, and the inheritance of stable conditions, as well as to 
an inevitably intimate connection with the immensely powerful 
organism of modern political and economic life, which can no 
longer, as in the anarchy and simplicity of mediaeval life, leave 
untouched islands to exist in its current. Another important 
factor in their development has been their Calvinistic environ- 
ment. Both in their own sociological process of evolution and in 
their social ethic they have grown into a very close relationship 
with Calvinism, or, rather, with Neo-Calvinism. On the other 
hand, Neo-Calvinism itself has entirely severed its connection 
with the State, and on the ethical side it has been fused with 
these sects to such an extent that it is practically impossible to 
distinguish them from each other. The main question, however, 
in which these sects still differ from the churches is that of 
freedom from the State, and the demand for the ecclesiastical 
neutrality of the State; but since the churches are now being 
separated from the State in any case, this question is naturally 
less urgent than formerly. 

It is not difficult to see why these sects have followed this line 
of development. The passive persecuted sect is only possible as 
an interim organization, while it awaits the Divine Revelation 
of the Kingdom. If, however, these bodies give up this “waiting” 
attitude, and accept the existing world-order as something per- 
manent, they then adopt a relative standard, and make their 
own compromise with the world. Of necessity, therefore, they 
then develop in the direction either of the churches or of the 
radical sects, or they die out. Thus they have become ecclesiastical 
and bourgeois, just as Calvinism, on the contrary, has become 
Free Church and legalistic. From the point of view of religious 
sociology they have become churches, founded, like the true 
churches, upon the doctrine of sin and grace ; the only difference 
is that, either in theory or in practice, their ideal of Church 
membership is stricter than that of the churches. 

As churches, therefore, which by the very fact of their separa- 
tion proclaim their independence, their freedom from the State, 
and the sovereign power of religion over against a secular 
civilization, and as highly individualistic organizations based on 
personal conviction and on conscious, systematic ethical achieve- 
ment, they evolve from within a sociological fundamental theory 
which may be described as the uniting of individuals in a com- 
mon spirit, which is not the sum but the product of the uniting 



PROTESTANTISM 


807 

individual will, which only exists in and through its active work. 
In one particular direction this spirit of the whole absorbs into 
itself the will of each individual, in order that that may again 
be affected by the spirit of the whole ; in other directions, how- 
ever, it is left free to work out other social ideas in its own way. 
It is no sterile individualism, nor is it an institutional spirit, 
which produces and supports the individual, but it is a vital 
process of interaction between the individuals who compose the 
society ’and the product of this union. 

The idea of fellowship is not determined by inherited moods 
and feelings, by a fixed framework of life which maintains itself 
by its own miraculous power, in which currents of feeling sway 
to and fro between active strenuous effort and passive adherence, 
but by the Divine purpose of Life — clearly recognized and sys- 
tematically realized, making demands on every single soul, yet 
transcending all — the Holy Community, the authentication of 
grace, preparation for the future life. This is a curious blend of 
the ecclesiastical and the sectarian spirit, in which the latter is 
the stronger. Actively and visibly exercised first and foremost 
within a religious fellowship, this spirit spreads outwards to the 
whole of life as a sociological fundamental theory which similarly 
defines the State, the communes, and the whole infinitely sub- 
divided group-life. This produces a certain affinity with Demo- 
cracy and Liberalism, but without the rationalist demand for 
equality, and also without the revolutionary spirit which is 
peculiar to the democracy of the Latin peoples. This kind of 
individualism, indeed, tends to be absolutely conservative, since 
it upholds with care the delicate balance between the individual 
and Society (as a constitution), and endeavours to secure it as 
far as possible from all disturbance. These are matters which 
force themselves upon the attention of every observer of American 
life; they also characterize English Dissent. These peculiarities 
are usually explained as Anglo-Saxon racial characteristics, 
whereas in reality these racial characteristics have themselves 
been produced by the discipline and education of Calvinism . 509 

Ascetic Protestantism 

Thus the development of Calvinism into Puritanism and the 
Free Churches, combined with the development of the Baptist 
movement into a bourgeois body, and the development of the 

609 Cf. the study by Max Weber , which has already been quoted several times, 
on Kirche und Sekte in Nordamerika ; there is a certain amount of material also 
in Tocqueville and Bryce: The American Commonwealth 9 , 1903. 



808 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 


Pietistic sects on ecclesiastical lines, has produced that collective 
Protestant group which has already been described above as 
“ascetic Protestantism”, in order to distinguish it from Lutheran- 
ism and Catholicism. At this point we again pick up the thread 
which we had to drop at the close of the last section. 

It has already been made abundantly clear that Lutheranism 
taught that labour in a calling was both a service rendered to 
God and an outward expression of brotherly love. On the other 
hand, by its emphasis upon the purely inward aspect of religion, 
its lack of a clear standard of moral behaviour, and its acquies- 
cence in the conditions of life which were created by Natural 
Law, but were often extremely unchristian, it was not able, 
on its own initiative, to bring about a coherent and systematic 
transformation of social life in general. Neither in theory nor 
in its attitude to life does it possess a systematic ethic. Again and 
again Lutheranism casts aside its asceticism (which it also pos- 
sesses as the corollary of the doctrine of Original Sin), and gives 
itself up to repose in the blessedness of the Divine Mercy, and 
to the thankful enjoyment of Divine gifts in all that is good and 
beautiful, and whenever it becomes dubious about the world and 
about sin it withdraws into the refuge of its inner happiness of 
justification through faith. 

Catholicism, on the other hand, likewise values the cosmos 
of the vocational system as the means of natural existence ap- 
pointed by Natural Law. But this system of callings is applicable 
to the conditions of natural existence, and is thus merely the lower 
degree of that higher supernatural ethic, which inwardly is no 
longer connected with the claims of the active life, but which in 
the life of contemplation attains the highest degree of supernuture 
or grace. 

Ascetic Protestantism and the “Calling” 

Ascetic Protestantism, however, regards the “calling” as a 
proof, and the ardent fulfilment of one’s professional duty as the 
sign and token of the state of grace. Accordingly it gathers all 
the work of the “calling” into a coherent system of the utmost 
concentration of human faculties on the aim of the “calling”, 
which is appointed to the individual through his providential 
position within the system. The principles and ideals of Ascetic 
Protestantism may therefore be summarized thus: the inner 
severance of feeling and enjoyment from all the objects of labour; 
the unceasing harnessing of labour to an aim which lies in 
the other world, and therefore must occupy us till death; the 



PROTESTANTISM 


809 

depreciation of possessions, of all things earthly, to the level of 
expediency; the habit of industry in order to suppress all dis- 
tracting and idle impulses ; and the willing use of profit for the 
religious community and for public welfare; these principles, 
which may vary in detail, are all in the main similar in character, 
and to a considerable extent also they have been and are being 
realized . 610 

Social Doctrines of Ascetic Protestantism 
These principles also help us to understand the social doctrines 
of Ascetic Protestantism, which affect the sphere of life which 
lies outside religion. Under this head I include Neo-Calvinism, 
whose social teaching, for the same reason, has not been described 
in detail . 6103 


Tiie Sex Ethic 

The sex ethic is, of course, concerned with the preservation of 
the strict purity of family life. All sexual intercourse before 
marriage and outside the marriage state is strictly forbidden. 
This, of course, is the ordinary Christian point of view. Never- 
theless, the ethic of the family itself is conceived in a very peculiar 
way. Asceticism, namely, demands the excision of all those erotic 
and emotional elements which Catholicism and Lutheranism had 
always believed they ought to tolerate as the sensuality resulting 
from Original Sin. The sex life of marriage was to them medicina 
libidinis . Here, however, it is firmly incorporated into the aim 
of the community to serve the glory of God. The life of sex is 
not tef be used for enjoyment, but for the deliberate procreation 
of children. It is not an aim in itself, but it serves the continued 
growth of Society and the Church. Further, the production of 
children involves the duty of bringing up useful members of 
Society and believing members of the Church; this naturally 
implies the duty of providing a suitable education. It was Pietism 
and the sects which evolved the idea of a systematic, useful, and 
practical education, and which established schools for this 
purpose. 

The relation between the sexes, conceived in a very indivi- 
dualistic way, softens the severity of Patriarchalism ; woman 
especially, in the Baptist movement, gains her religious and 
therefore her social independence. From time to time the sects 
(like the mystics) have their feminine preachers and leaders of 
510 Sec p. 986. 8103 Cf. above, p. 691. 



8io THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

meetings. In the Calvinistic “Prophesyings” and conventicles of 
Voet, women were allowed to take a public part. In the com- 
munity of Jean de la Badie, women, and especially the famous 
Anna von Schtirmann, played a decided and independent part. 
Together with other reasons, the well-known position of woman 
in America is also connected with her religious position. It is 
only natural that in the whole effort to attain a more stable and 
more deliberate attitude towards life the attitude of children 
towards their parents should also become more independent. 
Schools and meetings for children, with the development of an 
independent esprit de corps and of independent responsibility, reveal 
the educational ideal of these groups. The Sunday School move- 
ment within the churches, the Young Men’s Christian Associa- 
tion, and other similar movements all tend in this direction. The 
effect of this education, intensified by a democratic way of life, 
is one of the most striking phenomena which attract the attention 
of the European visitor to America . 511 

The Political Ethic 

The political ethic, likewise, regards the State from a purely 
utilitarian standpoint. In this matter Calvinistic Natural Law 
prepared the way which was trodden later by the sects and the 
Free Churches. The only right the State has to exist is for the 
sake of order and of discipline, and thus to provide a basis for 
Society. The purely political conception of the State as an ethical 
end in itself, which was self-evident to the Ancient World, and 
which has reappeared within the modern world, does not come 
into the picture at all. This essentially utilitarian and essentially 
social, non-political conception of the State is indeed, as we have 
already seen in various ways, likewise a common Christian idea. 
It is the natural result of the transference of all true life-values 
into the religious sphere, which means that even in the most 
favourable light the rest of the life-values are only regarded as 
means to an end. Ascetic Protestantism, however, on the basis 
of rationalistic Natural Law, which, like the Puritan ethic, it 
instinctively takes over from Calvinism, goes much farther than 
Lutheranism and Catholicism. 

In Catholicism the State belongs to the natural stage of exis- 
tence, above which there rises the supernatural stage of Grace, 
which is completely indifferent to the State. In Catholicism, 
therefore, the State is sometimes utilized and glorified, sometimes 


511 See p. 987. 



PROTESTANTISM 


811 


treated merely as the material for and presupposition of some- 
thing else, sometimes shorn of all authority and trampled under 
foot by the world-organization of the Church. 

In Lutheranism the State is also a part of the natural order, 
but as such it is a necessary form of the activity of Christian love 
and of the Christian spirit ; but since it is still essentially a pro- 
duct of the natural evolution of reason which punishes and heals 
sin, and as such is guided by God, it gains (whether harmful 
or useful to the Christian aim of life) the supernatural dignity 
of a power which has been directly appointed by God, which, 
above all, must be endured and respected. 

Early Calvinism, like Lutheranism, had an equally strong sense 
of authority, and only permitted a subsidiary ideal of utilitarian- 
rational interference in circumstances where the ruling powers 
of the State were unchristian in their behaviour. Those excep- 
tional conditions, however, were not to be allowed to continue 
long, but as soon as possible they were to yield to an organized 
authority, and restore the social unity controlled by a State 
Church. 

In Ascetic Protestantism, on the contrary, the organization of 
the State is likewise in principle deduced from the Natural Law 
of the fallen state, but it is always estimated according to its 
rational purpose, and subordinated to its responsibility not merely 
to God, but also to the people from whom it has received its 
mandate, whether legally or merely morally. The social unity 
controlled by a State Church has disappeared ; the State no longer 
takes a direct part in the vital interests of the Christian churches 
and denominations ; moreover, it has thus been forced down to 
the level of mere human expediency. The honours, offices, and 
dignities of the State are functions appointed by God and the 
people, but they do not proceed from inherent divine right 
within the government. No honours may be paid to a creature 
which would encroach upon the homage to be paid to God, and 
at bottom all are only functionaries of Providence in the natural 
cosmos of Society, which is designed to serve the glory of God 
by a way of life which is based on strict Christian principles. 
Within the State, therefore, there is a strong sense of the equality 
of all in the presence of God, a sense which is expressed par- 
ticularly strongly only in the well-known customs of the Quakers, 
but which is in no sense an equalitarian view like that of the 
European democracy. This is prevented by the idea of Providence, 
which looks upon the social and political cosmos as divided by 
God, for the express purposes of Salvation, into different groups, 



812 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

faculties, and positions in life. This strong emphasis upon Provi- 
dence is a relic of the doctrine of Predestination. 

We may thus sum up the main features of the attitude of 
Ascetic Protestantism towards the State: it is inclined towards 
a liberal or democratic conception of the State, apart from 
equalitarian theories; it tends to regard the State simply as 
something which must be endured; it glorifies its own national 
inheritance more for its religious mission than for its political 
greatness; and it likes to regulate international relationships 
according to peace principles, which are also reasonable, and 
from the business point of view desirable. Ascetic Protestantism 
views imperialistic and nationalistic movements with a good deal 
of misgiving. Sometimes it rejects them on principle; sometimes 
it is able to justify them as an extension of Christian civilization 
whose sole genuine representative it feels itself to be ; it has been 
entrusted with this destiny by God. It then regards itself in the 
light of the Old Testament as a “Chosen People”, and absorbs 
Imperialism into the aim of Foreign Missions . 5113 

The Economic Ethic 

The economic ethic, finally, teaches (likewise from the general 
Christian point of view) that labour is the result of the Fall, and 
is to be regarded as the penalty and the discipline of sin. But 
this idea is here developed into that of a rational, systematic 
discipline of labour, evolved, above all, in Puritanism, and thence 
taken over in a more or less logical manner; this ethic regards 
laziness and idleness as the source of all evil, and the result of a 
failure to impose discipline. With this systematic view of work (to 
which, incidentally, other than Puritan motives were sometimes 
added, as, for instance, among the Quakers the waiting and self- 
preparation for the Divine illumination), a strong and systematic 
impulse was given to production, while, on the other hand, with 
the same asceticism there is united a considerable limitation of 
consumption and a complete avoidance of all luxury (at least, 
of all that is obvious and that ministers to vanity and arrogance). 
It is only at this point that we see the full effect of that which 
has already been described as the favourable ethical disposition 
of Calvinism for bourgeois Capitalism. Thus this economic ethic 
became middle-class, one might almost say lower middle-class- 
capitalist, and it bore all the signs of the results of the capitalistic 
attitude towards life: systematic division of labour, emphasis 
upon specialization, the feeling for advantage and profit, the 

511a See p. 988. 



PROTESTANTISM 


813 

abstract duty of work, the obligation towards property as towards 
something great, which ought to be maintained and increased 
for its own sake. The owner of wealth or property is “the Lord’s 
Steward”, and administers a Divine gift which has been entrusted 
to him. An ethic of this kind placed at the disposal of the nascent 
modern bourgeois Capitalism both energetic and courageous 
entrepreneurs , and men who were willing to endure exploitation 
if only they could get work. This ethic differs from the Capitalism 
of antiquity and of the later Middle Ages by those very features 
which have just been described, and alongside of it the other 
existing kinds of Capitalism, of course, must not be overlooked. 

This type of Capitalism, however, preserves its special Christian 
character by its taboo on pleasure-seeking and self-glorification, 
the sense of the duty of work for the service of God, strict honesty 
and reliability, the humane obligation to make provision for the 
workers and to give respect to employers, and the extensive use 
of wealth for philanthropic ends. 

The system of fixed prices, the standardization and classifica- 
tion of goods according to their quality, the building up of 
. business upon the strictest formal honesty, the principle “honesty 
is the best policy” — all arose at this point. It is the expression 
of a spiritual and moralistic opposition to the guild system and 
to unfair dealing in individual cases; it means that the life of 
business is constructed upon the calculation of the individual in 
relation to an abstract circle of purchasers, and upon the absolute 
necessity for correctness and honesty as regards estimates and 
deliveries. The inscription on the Bremen Exchange, which states 
that the merchant is the most honest man, should be interpreted 
from* this point of view. The justification for the economic life 
lies in its value to the community, and in this sense it can be 
considered a blessing ; in itself, however, the ideal attitude is that 
of the man whose spirit is inwardly entirely independent of 
possessions. It is even possible to go a step farther and to exalt 
poverty, which preserves from the dangers of wealth, just as, on 
the other hand, wealth, used in a Christian way, preserves the 
community from misery and want. Thus here also there is no 
idea of equality. This is prevented by the whole idea of Provi- 
dence, and above all, where it was still a vital force, by the idea 
of Predestination. The conception is always that of a cosmos 
directed by God, in which the Christian Ethos only works itself 
out through reciprocal activities, division of labour, a variety of 
gifts and capacities. Thus, as Calvinism and the sects are of one 
mind on the question of the development of a voluntary Church, 



814 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

and on the question of separation between Church and State, 
so also their views coincide in the economic ethic of secular 
asceticism which determines the ethic of Ascetic Protestantism, 
renouncing its greater earlier freedom: Calvinism reaches this 
point of view under the urgent sense of need to prove in daily 
life the reality of its faith, and it therefore produces the systematic 
asceticism of labour ; the passive, persecuted sect comes to this 
point by giving up its hostility towards the world, and by fusing 
its ascetic detachment from the world with the Protestant idea 
of the “calling”. Further, both movements shared the following 
experience : on account of their Nonconformity and their freedom 
from the State, they were forcibly excluded from all official 
positions in the State and from its dignities; thus they were 
thrust out of the ruling classes and obliged to join the bourgeois 
middle class ; this still further intensified the bourgeois capitalist 
element. Agriculture was not excluded, but it was only practised 
by the people of this class by farming, and by trading in property 
in land; but it has nothing to do with the feudal ownership of 
land. 

Thus the difference between this ethic and that of the theo- 
retical traditional economic ethic of Catholicism is clear. In this 
ethic, work and possessions belong to the natural sphere alone; 
the desire for gain does not directly concern the religious ethic 
at all ; gain is regarded merely as a method of providing for one’s 
needs according to one’s rank in Society; whatever is earned 
beyond that should be used for charity ; the most genuine charity, 
however, is actually exercised by those who possess nothing at 
all, by those who stand outside the ordinary work of the world 
altogether. 

The difference between this economic ethic and that of 
Lutheranism is equally clear. Lutheranism, it is true, makes the 
task of earning a living part of the “calling” to brotherly love, 
but, in spite of this, it gives preference to the callings which 
belong to a settled order of Society consisting of agricultural 
labourers, manual workers, and officials; Capitalism and the 
calculating spirit which is continually striving to make more 
money is regarded by Lutheranism with detachment and extreme 
misgiving. 

But even contrasted with primitive Calvinism, to which, with 
its State Church point of view, all methods of gaining a livelihood 
were of equal importance, which had not developed the asceticism 
of labour to this extent, and which had no trace of the lower 
middle-class spirit at all — this was something new. This was the 



PROTESTANTISM 


815 

result of that asceticism in which the Puritan, legalistic, organiz- 
ing Calvinism came into contact with those sects which were 
comparatively ready to accept secular civilization; it was also 
the result of the social and political situation in which both 
Calvinism and the sects found themselves over against the official 
world . 512 

Ascetic Protestantism and its Relation to 
General Historical Development 
Surveying all these developments as a whole, it is plain that 
the Christian social philosophy of Puritan Calvinism, of Pietism 
and the sects, and, to some extent, even that of the mystical 
groups, is a great unity, which, for historical significance can 
only be compared with the social philosophy of the Middle Ages. 
As in the Middle Ages, the main point for us is the theory, the 
intellectual orientation of a Christian work of civilization, and 
a Christian organization of Society. Here, as there, convinced 
supporters of the system, who are vitally concerned, will be in 
the minority. But they blaze a trail in the realm of thought, and 
they create ways of thinking which come to be accepted as obvious 
and natural, within which the general Christian consciousness 
and a unified attitude towards life can live and move; it does 
not then matter how much real seriousness there is behind each 
individual instance of this behaviour. The great problem of 
Christian supernaturalism — that of uniting and adapting itself 
to the practical life of Society — was solved in each instance on 
a great scale and in a popularly effective way: in Catholicism, 
by means of a universal Church, which regulates, supervises, and 
finally itself effects the ascent of Nature to Grace; in ascetic 
Protestantism, by a highly individualistic congregational system 
which was in harmony with modern individualism, and through 
the ascetic self-control of individuals who reduce the whole of 
secular and social life to the level of a mere method of glorifying 
God and proving the state of grace. Thus there are certain points 
of contact between the two systems, since both express the 
Christian hostility to the world in a systematic discipline and 
in asceticism . 613 They still differ fundamentally, however, since 
Catholicism places its ascetic ideal in opposition to the lower 

618 See p. 988. 

618 For analogies with Protestant asceticism in the monasteries so far as they 
introduce labour and in so doing develop systematic self-discipline, see Max 
Weber; Archiv XXI , 28 ff. ; for occasional union of mysticism with the ethic of 
the “calling* * as a means of discipline, see XX, 50, and XXI, 22, 



816 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

stage of life in the world ; therefore, the consequences of this lower 
degree break through everywhere, giving to the actual highest 
achievements of asceticism a directly legalistic, mortifying 
character. Protestant asceticism, on the contrary, gathers directly 
all the material of the natural life into the supernatural aim; 
thus it here loses its self-mortifying and dualistic character, and 
becomes a systematic work for the salvation of souls and for the 
Kingdom of God, within the setting of a secular “calling”. 
Lutheranism certainly did not finally close the circle so firmly, 
and the idealistic mysticism which in some ways is so closely akin 
to it fell back very frequently into a purely dualistic asceticism 
with its emphasis upon mortification. 

On the other hand, this inquiry closes with Puritan Calvinism 
and the “purified” communities of the sects. To what extent they 
will be able to dominate the modern civilized world permanently 
in a Christian manner is another question. This school of thought 
is still a power in worldhistory. But it is clear on all hands that 
to a great extent the State, Society, and economic life will no 
longer allow themselves to be dominated by it, and in their 
present position cannot possibly be dominated by it any longer. 

Faced by all these considerations, we arrive at the last question 
of all — going beyond the immediate subject — the question of the 
connection between these views of general social conditions and 
their effect upon the whole of civilization. This question can only 
be answered with the utmost reserve, since, ist : until now the 
facts have only been known in part, and, 2nd : the perpetually 
fluctuating power and range of influence makes it very difficult 
to give any certain interpretation of the facts . 514 

“Spiritual religion” or mysticism is not a product of particular 
social conditions. It proceeds from other causes: the experience 
of the incapacity of the churches to realize their ideal, weariness 
of the strife and conflict of religious parties, the pure inner dialectic 
of religious feeling returning to its ultimate source, the critical 
destruction of dogmas and cults, and weariness of the disappoint- 
ments and confusions of the external life in general. Thus of itself 
it has no social influence upon life in general. Its inner circles 
do not penetrate into the masses, and its purely contemplative 
ideas do not grip the common life, but work purely personally, 
or hover in a literary manner over the whole. In modern times 

614 On the whole subject, which gathers up all his earlier ideas (in Archiv XX 
and XXI , and in the article in the Chr, W.) and carries them out further, see 
Weber's Schlusswort , XXXI , pp. 584-508. Cf. also, above, the exposition of 
asceticism, pp. 604-605. 



PROTESTANTISM 


817 

certainly, its extension depends upon the existence of classes 
which live apart from the crude struggle for existence, and can 
seek spiritual refinement for their own sake, so far as it is not 
hidden in small evangelical sects, which also, however, have 
always a special sectarian trait. Beyond that it is connected with 
the modern scientific cultivation of the autonomous reason, in 
so far as this takes a religious turn. To this extent it reflects to-day 
the universal individualism of modern times, which indeed it 
still further strengthens. It accompanies social conditions, but 
does not arise out of them, nor does it influence them directly. 
Indirectly, however, the fact that it weakens the power and ex- 
clusiveness of the churches means that it has a very important 
social influence. 

The ideal of the radical sects, on the contrary, was never 
developed out of the purely inward dialectic of Christian thought. 
In its primitive form, Christian thought left all such matters too 
much to a future which was to be brought about by God, even 
though it was expected that this would soon be realized, and 
it left all details in God’s Hands, and not to the consideration 
and organization of man. After the Christian faith had adjusted 
itself to the present world and had become a Church, the ex- 
pectation of a complete ethical world-renewal could only be 
introduced into Christianity from outside through the pressure 
of intolerable conditions ; and, somehow or other, that inevitably 
implied human thought and human organization. Particularly 
threatening social and political conditions were then held to be 
the signs of world-renewals which were about to come, as a 
challenge to prepare the way of the Lord for the Kingdom of 
God ; it was a mingled attitude of believing expectation of the 
Kingdom, and an actual effort to cause the new conditions. 
The sect-ideal, therefore, only rose to the heights of its power 
when the existing conditions required reform, when the history 
of the period seemed to point to some catastrophic event which 
God was about to bring to pass, which thus reawakened the 
expectation of the coming of the Kingdom of God. 

Thus the ideal of the radical sect is always aroused only by 
the course of general social development. This is true also of 
modem Christian Socialism, which was only brought into exist- 
ence first of all by the revelation of the results of the capitalist 
system, and, above all, by the great Socialist Movement ; in its 
most advanced groups, in fact, the Socialist Movement is inter- 
preted as a sign of a world-upheaval willed by God. 

For that very reason, therefore, the influence of Christian 

vol. n. AA 



818 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 


Socialism is always of a secondary nature, being exerted along- 
side those more general movements, which it merely interprets, 
appropriates, and rectifies. Christianity does not breed social 
revolution. It can only adjust itself, with a certain sense of strain, 
to the modern social revolution, which, although it is not violent, 
is still very radical in principle. The aim of Christian Socialism 
is to effect a change in the hearts and minds of men which is 
orientated towards God, and not towards the world. The modern 
realization of the fact that spiritual values are intimately con- 
nected with the material social basis of life must always be 
stressed very strongly, if it is to lead to a thorough social reform, 
or even to the revolution of Society. At present it is very difficult 
to estimate to what extent its efforts to educate the wealthier 
classes in their social responsibilities, and the working classes in 
a spirit of confidence and moderation, have actually influenced 
the class-war. The importance of Christian Socialism in England 
is well known. In other countries it is harder to estimate 
its significance. In any case, it exists. In these matters material 
circumstances speak louder than ideas; but they need to be 
filled with idealistic content. In this respect Christian Socialism 
certainly has a mission, although it will scarcely be able to 
build up the new social order. 614a 

Social Influence of Ascetic Protestantism 
On the other hand, the social influence of Ascetic Protestantism 
upon the history of civilization has been penetrating and com- 
prehensive . 616 Through its ecclesiastical ideal, which merges into 
the ideal of the Free Churches, the democratic constitution of 
its individual congregations, as well as of its general ecclesiastical 
structure, its autonomous individualism, based upon the Will 
of God and the fact of Redemption, and its systematic and 
positive industry, it has become one of the basic causes of the 
immense changes in modern Society; this spirit has only been 
brought into Catholic and Lutheran countries from outside ; but 
it would never have been created solely by the new economic, 
political, and technical conditions of the modern world. This fact 
must be regarded as one result of this inquiry. At this point it 
is impossible to make a balanced estimate of the influence exerted 
by the forces which have moulded modern society ; it is sufficient 
to point out that Ascetic Protestantism has made an important 
contribution to the whole. Of course, we might express the 

ai4a Cf. Sombart: Sozialismus und soziale Bewegung , pp. ig i 100 , 252, 362. 

515 See p. 989. 



PROTESTANTISM 


819 

question differently — thus: Did this achievement only become 
possible to Ascetic Protestantism, or was it even forced upon it 
by its adjustment to the surrounding world of progressive Western 
Europe? In the course of this inquiry this point also has been 
discussed several times. The country round Geneva already con- 
tained impulses of that kind ; undoubtedly France, Holland, and 
England contained still more. Also the fact that, in many 
countries, its members were forcibly excluded from the official 
world has helped to shape it. On the whole, however, in face of 
developments which agree with each other in so many entirely 
different forms of civilization, and sometimes in such unfavour- 
able surroundings, it is surely permissible to emphasize here the 
primary significance of the religious and ethical idea, which, 
indeed, from the very outset bore within itself a great power 
of adaptation to practical and average needs. B15a To-day, how- 
ever, its spirit, has very largely vanished from that which it 
essentially helped to create. Its creations have passed into other 
hands, and are being shaped by them according to their purposes. 
This is particularly true of the transformation of the results of 
the English Puritan Revolution by the French Revolution, and 
its intellectual and literary impulses. Against this “Enlighten- 
ment 55 , however, created by the Latin and Catholic peoples, 
which sends out its rationalistic and abstract ideas in every 
direction, there contends to this day everywhere the conception 
of human society and its aims which has been formed in the 
school of Ascetic Protestantism. Pre-eminently its spirit is in- 
carnate in the Anglo-Saxon world. So far as the social struggle of 
the present day is spiritual and concerned with questions of 
principle, it turns upon the question of this conflict between the 
Corporation-idea of Anglo-Saxon Calvinism and the Democracy 
of French Rationalism; Catholic and Lutheran Patriarchalism 
have retired into the background. This general opposition tends 
to modify group differences within Protestantism to an appre- 
ciable extent. Calvinism and the sect-movement have found each 
other. But Lutheranism also is being slowly drawn into the 
forward march of the Protestant social doctrines, and is being 
influenced by Ascetic Protestantism. This process of development 
will increase when, as we may expect with certainty, it is no 
longer supported by the State. 

Protestant ecclesiasticism, which began as the Reform of 
Catholicism, and which had built up a new uniform and com- 
pulsory Christian civilization, was led to an ever greater extent 
516a Cf. above, p. 631. 



820 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

to sever its social doctrines from these early universal ecclesiastical 
developments. The first great structure which arose out of this 
process of separation was Ascetic Protestantism. It has founded 
and evolved the main body of Protestant civilization. But its 
power is weakening, and Protestantism is thus faced by new 
tasks, both in its own sociological development and in its 
corporate connection with civilization. 



PROTESTANTISM 


821 


NOTES TO CHAPTER III 

19 7a (P* 465 •) On this point we must mention especially the well-known 
biography of Luther by Denifle , who emphasizes rightly that Luther was not 
influenced by Thomism, and indeed that he only had a limited acquaintance 
with this philosophy. When, however, this leads him to accuse Luther of 
ignorance of the whole great system of Catholic science, saying that in his 
ignorance he had stuck obstinately to a less valuable scientific form of Catholi- 
cism, and.that therefore all his polemics are misdirected, we can only explain 
this by concluding that this is part of the modern Catholic apologetic. In 
reality, Occamism was the real reason for the break-up of the unity of Catholic 
civilization and theology, whose position had become untenable, and to that 
extent it constituted the natural foundation for a new interpretation and 
development of Christian thought. On this point cf. W. Kohler: Ein Wort zu 
Denifles Luther , 1904. The basis of Luther’s thought upon Occamism is strongly 
and rightly emphasized in the extremely interesting book by Hermelink: Die 
theologische Fakultdt in Tubingen, 1477-1534, 1906, in which for the first time 
there is clearly set*forth the relation between Thomism and Occamism in this 
important transition period (on this point cf. my review in G.G.A . , 1909). 
Linsenmann: Gabriel Biel und der Nominalismus , Theol. Quartalschrift, 1865, takes 
this same point of view which is so important for Lutheran thought. This 
Nominalism, however, still continues the main features of mediaeval Christian 
piety, in so far as it still regards the Universal Church and the Christian nature 
of the whole of Society as perfectly natural assumptions ; the co-operation of the 
laity, of the secular authorities, of the councils is more strongly emphasized in 
this ideal, the rational metaphysical basis of theology is set aside, and its 
authoritative and revelational character is increased. 

ltta (p. 467.) Kautsky's position is naturally that of a man who traces the 
origin of the Reformation to class movements ( Sozialismus in Einzeldarstellungen , 
/, i,pp. 239-251). To him Luther is an agitator who provides a religious sanction 
for the communistic-democratic opposition, and an unprincipled courtier 
who supplies a religious sanction for the rising absolutism ; his great influence 
is supposed to be due to this dual position. The real hero of the Reformation 
is Thomas Miinzer, who did not possess Luther’s second detestable charac- 
teristic. Reasons for these statements are not given in this superficial sketch, 
which is entirely lacking in understanding. A similar view is expressed by 
Kalthoff: Das ^eitalter der Reformation , hg. von Steudel, 1907 , from the point of 
view of the theory of the collectivist interpretation ofhistory. The editor says : 
“In the economic and class struggles K. gives us an insight into the inner- 
most driving forces in that whole mighty upheaval of civilization, and we thus 
are able to understand the personalities which emerge from the fight between 
declining and fresh groups of interests” (VIII). The author, however, makes no 
attempt to carry out this programme. K. contents himself with pointing out 
in a quite general way the bourgeois character of the Reformation, illustrated 
chiefly by Diirer and Hans Sachs. There is certainly something true in this, 
but it does certainly not mean that a class struggle was the chief cause of the 
Reformation — Dilthey: Die Glaubenslehre der Reformatoren ( Preuss . Jahrbb ., 75, 
1894), and Arnold Berger: Die Kidturaufgaben der Reformation , 1895 , and Luther - 
biographie , I 2 , 1908 , emphasize strongly the indirect influence of the develop- 
ment of the towns, the increasing influence of the laity in the Church, and the 
solid virtues of the bourgeois way of life. Here, quite rightly, the Reformation 



8aa THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

movement is placed within the absolutely necessary broad setting of the general 
history of civilization. But, as so easily happens in such a comprehensive view, 
the lines which converge in Luther become indistinct, and the definite concrete 
conception of Luther’s own development also suffers. Luther is still essentially 
a monk who follows the great mediaeval way of the realization and concen- 
tration of the religious life, the way of monasticism, and he is also a theologian 
who first of all comes to his own position through inward experience, and the 
theological study of late Scholasticism, of mysticism, of St. Augustine, of St. 
Bernard, and of the New Testament, and only from this does he enter into 
relation with the tendencies of his time. In these books the authors also overlook 
the fact that Luther starts from the conception of the Church, and gives it 
a new connotation, but that he does not substitute for it a non-ecclesiastical 
form of mysticism and lay religion. This means that from the very beginning 
the aim is laid down which is implied in the ecclesiastical objectivity of the 
Word and the Sacrament, and the further consequence of the conception of 
the Church; further on this subject is treated in greater fullness. Therefore 
primarily Luther is an ecclesiastical theologian, and quite distinct from 
sectarian leaders, as well as from the representatives of a purely lay religion, 
whose outlook is wholly individualistic. Therefore all presentations of the 
subject err which do not conceive him as a Church reformer, but as a represen- 
tative of the purely individualistic lay religion which many modern people of 
the present day prefer, and who, therefore, place Luther in an exaggerated 
historical succession of late mediaeval lay religion and bourgeois thought, 
instead of in the direct line of theological tradition. We have to be surer of the 
facts of the influence of the former element in his pre-monastic period; this 
can only be discovered through the medium of the study of late Scholasticism, 
mysticism, and Humanism, which in any case did contain new sociological 
points of view; this, however, in view of the nature of the subject, would be a 
very difficult task. — The relation between his doctrine, which had already 
been formulated in its main features, and the Lutheran propaganda, to the 
social tendencies of the time is now illuminated in the important work by 
Barge: Andreas Bodenstein von Karlstadt , 77 , 1903. According to this work Luther’s 
own doctrine in its final form is everywhere on the side of government, and 
its interest in order, which desires the reform of the Church, the breaking 
of the power of the hierarchy, a policy of secularization, and a morally 
authoritative control of the excited masses of the population; Luther himself 
is only interested in social reform within these limits, after the first great ideal 
hopes of the Reformation had failed, which he had expressed in his treatise 
To the Nobility of the German Nation , and after the failure of the nobility to meet 
his hopes caused him to turn to the idea of small groups of genuine Christians 
with a Christian Kastenordnung ; the cause of this failure was due to actual 
conditions. To Luther social reform was always only a secondary question ; in 
fact it only interested him in so far as it provided a better basis for the religious 
life. The fact is that Luther’s interests were purely religious, and that otherwise 
his was an entirely conservative nature. At the same time the social revolutionary 
endeavours of the peasants and of the proletariat of the great towns were 
taking place, whose religious elements were more Hussite or Taborite in 
character, and although they were drawn into the agitation caused by the 
Lutheran movement, they were neither spiritually nor theologically deter- 
mined by it. Finally also there was a third group of reform movements 
which Barge especially mentions; it was composed mainly of small artisans 
with whom the clergy and schoolmasters were in sympathy; this group was 



PROTESTANTISM 


823 

strongly anti-clerical, and wished to see a free lay Christianity of the Con- 
gregational type which would entirely do away with Catholic ritual, theologi- 
cally would get rid of the authority of the Church and an official ministry, 
and which wished to introduce all kinds of social and ethical reforms under 
the wing of the State and of the administration of justice, in the sense of a 
severer form of the Christian way of life and charitable activity, and also 
elementary Christian social reform in Society in general ; all this, however, is 
not to take place through the territorial princes, but through the local authori- 
ties and the parish representatives; the latter groups accept radical anti- 
sacramental theology, and provide the soil for the Baptists, since everywhere 
the territorial lords or the stronger neighbouring powers suppress all communal 
independence of that kind. Here also there is an entire lack of any clear idea 
of a comprehensive and uniform reshaping of the Church, like that which was 
developed by Calvinism, at a later date, with similar ideas. These ideas are 
simply local and temporary in character, based on the expectation that in 
some way or another the order of the whole Church will come into being. 
As naturally this order did not arise, these aspirations provided a fertile soil 
for the development of Separatist communities or of the Baptists. Thus, from 
this side also we see that it is quite impossible to describe the Reformation 
doctrine as deterfnined by the outlook of one particular class and its develop- 
ment. As Barge several times points out, a very great part was played, on the 
other hand, by the aversion to the Catholic Church and the independent spirit 
of the laity which had developed during the later mediaeval times ; this latter 
movement was, of course, deeply rooted not merely in an opposition in ideals 
but in real social facts. We also ought not to underestimate the importance 
of Bible study by the masses in a time which was so penetrated with religious 
ideas. The enormous controversial literature, with its extremely detailed 
Biblical exposition which is quite unintelligible to us modern men, can only 
be understood from the standpoint of an independent religious interest in the 
attempt to square life and doctrine with the standard of the Bible. Further, 
we have to take into account the fact of a sediment of demagogy— the kind of 
thing which always forms part of universal agitations of this kind— which 
gives rise to the most varied and wild meaningless and chaotic extravagances. — 

I have just given an outline of the most important ideas in Barge's book, but at 
the same time I have made clear the points in which I disagree with him. 
“Lay Christian Puritanism”, whose apostle, Karlstadt, he describes in a 
strongly partisan spirit (cf. Karl Muller: Luther und Karlstadt , igoy), is neither 
the logical result of Lutheran thought, nor is it a hopeful programme for 
German conditions ; the reason for this will emerge in the analysis of Calvinism. 

200 (p. 469.) Well formulated in Preuss: Die Entwickelung des Schriftprinzips 
bei Luther bis zur Leipziger Disputation , igoi , p. 34; it was the Scholastic doctrine 
that “the sacraments of the New Covenant opere operato are channels of grace 
of a purely positive, as well as ethical and religious power. All that is required 
is that the recipient should place no barrier. This corresponded entirely to the 
whole mediaeval fundamental idea which conceived the relation between God 
and man as something, properly speaking, quite concrete, as an exchange of 
mutual activity, as a relationship of service and reward. This point of view 
(which Luther also shared at the beginning, but which was so little able to 
satisfy him that it almost drove him to despair) was for him, after that funda- 
mental experience, in principle overcome; in place of the old relationship 
there now emerged a relationship which is interpreted as one based upon God’s 
grace, as an entirely personal turning of God towards the sinner, and of the 



824 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

faith of man, that is: his personal confidence in God, his purely personal 
relationship.” The vital point is this : that Luther could find no peace in the 
Catholic sacraments, and that in his preparation for the Sacrament all he 
could feel was conviction of sin, the oppression of the law, and self-righteousness. 
This explains his different religious feeling, and it is from this standpoint that 
he appeals to the Pauline assurance of grace in Christ. Bohmer ( Luther im Licht 
der Neueren Forschung , 1906), who accuses me of a misunderstanding by making 
the doctrine of the Sacrament the starting-point of Luther’s theory when it 
should be regarded as an important result, says the same thing : “Grace is no 
longer conceived by him as a supernatural energy or medicine which is 
imparted to men through the sacraments, and which then ought 0 to bring 
forth spiritual and moral results, but an attitude of God which is proclaimed 
in the Word of God and works through the means of the Word just as otherwise 
the manifestation of a spirit is manifested through a word” {p. 77). That is 
exactly my own meaning, and all that Bohmer says about me is due to a 
misunderstanding. Entirely in agreement with my own point of view is 
Gottschick's definition, Die Lehre der Ref. v. d. Taufe , 1906, p. 13. 

* 01 (p. 469.) On this point and that which follows, cf. my presentation of the 
subject in the Kultur der Gegenwart, /, IV, 1: Protestantisches Christentum und Kirche. 
In it also the literature upon which my views are based is given in full. In the 
second edition of 1909 I accepted the objections which had been raised. 
Essentially in the positive conception they made no difference ; they were only 
concerned with my habit of contrasting the thought-world of the Reformation 
with the modern thought- world. That, however, is a point of view which 
Protestantism as a whole must adopt, because it is only so that we can under- 
stand the crisis through which it is passing at the present day. For the present 
work this point of view disappears. Here we are solely concerned with the 
special subject of the confessional Protestant social doctrines, compared with 
the Latin Catholic and the early Christian social teaching. Here, however, 
also it will become clear that fundamental assumptions have been maintained 
which only Latin Catholicism had gained ; indeed, from the sociological and 
ethical side the continuity is much clearer than from the side of pure dogma, 
which is the aspect with which theologians are usually entirely concerned. 
Since, namely, the exclusive dominion of religious authority and the stable 
constitution of secular society in accordance with that as well as of the secular 
thought of the Middle Ages and of early Protestantism are common to both, 
and since the whole system in both cases is based upon this exclusiveness of 
authority and stability, and since, further, this exclusiveness and stability on 
the spiritual and secular side of an established Christian civilization and society 
both theoretically and actually is the work of the Middle Ages, this then forms 
the presupposition of Protestantism and this thought goes on working out in 
Protestantism. The deep differences are naturally not to be overlooked, but 
they move within a common framework. And it is precisely this common 
framework which the modern world had broken ; indeed, that is the element 
which quite clearly is to be fixed in it alone as its character; cf. my discussion, 
Das Wesen des Modernen Geistes , Preuss. Jahrbb ., 1907. With the breaking down 
of this framework, however, then only will the motives of Protestantism which 
are related to the modern world become free and find a development which 
leads far away from the meaning and spirit of the Reformers in whose minds 
that framework was most closely connected with the subject itself ; see my 
article, Luther und die Moderne Welt in das Christentum , Leipzig, 1907, 

104 (p. 473.) This variation between direct Divine appointment and indirect 



PROTESTANTISM 


825 

causation through Natural Law is characteristic of the strongly religious- 
positivist attitude of Lutheran thought. Both, however, are combined in the 
idea that in one way or another God alone is the Author of all these things, 
and that particular institutions are only direct manifestations of the otherwise 
indirect Law of Nature which mediates the Divine Will ; see Luthardt: Luthers 
Ethiky 1867 , pp . 94 ff.: “The natural ordinances and classes . . . belong only 
to this temporal and natural life. But although they are only secular classes, 
and are subordinate to reason, that does not imply that they are profane, but 
they are instituted, ordained, and willed by God, and God is present within 
them. For God uses His creatures like a ‘mask* behind which He Himself is 
concealed and behind this ‘veil* He does all things. . . . The view of the 
active presence of God in all His creatures and ordinances he has always 
maintained. If, however, these secular classes are the will and ordinance of 
God, and if He is present within them, then also there must be a relation 
between them and the Gospel. For they are both of God even though they are 
different — on the one hand, they are the ordinance of God the Creator and 
now of God the Redeemer.” Here we must point out that it is at this point 
that the conservative conception of Natural Law and Natural Right arises 
within Lutheranism ; cf. Eugen Ehrhardt: La Notion du Droit Naturel chez Luther 
(. Festschrift von Pans fur Montauban , 1901 , pp. 287-320). 

207 (P* 47^0 The sects also had already discarded the idea of an ascent 
from Nature to Super-Nature as has been shown already. But also the late 
Scholasticism of the Occamists with its restored emphasis upon the absolute 
opposition between Grace and Nature had also discarded this conception 
together with the ideas of reconciliation and development which it involved ; 
see Hermelink: Die theologische Fakultat in Tubingen , i9o6 y pp. 111 and 122. For the 
Primitive State this difference has already been set aside, since it is argued 
that there was no ascent from connatural perfection to supernatural perfection, 
but perfection in itself is conceived as a debitum naturae , and on account of 
the weakness of man only needs to be filled with supernatural grace ; see Linsen - 
mann: a.a. 0 . y pp. 648-651. We may, however, say that Luther’s discarding of 
those conceptions was so far original to the extent in which its motive was not 
the radicalism of the opposition but the idea of the essential connection between 
Grace and Nature within the Will of God. It is here that there arises the 
peculiar limitation in contrast with Catholicism that the Lutheran relationship 
between Grace and Nature makes possible on the one hand an inner combina- 
tion, an immanence of Grace in Nature, but that on the other hand, since 
Nature is appointed merely by an act of will as the sphere for the exercise of 
Grace, all inner union and reconciliation between the two disappears and 
genuine Protestantism finds it much more difficult to have an inner relation 
with “Nature”. The Catholic assertion that Protestantism has much less 
inward connection with Nature and with civilization is to that extent right, 
and is based upon this fact, a circumstance which is usually not noticed by 
Protestant controversialists. 

208 (p. 482.) Rudolf Sohm has illustrated his well-known thesis that Church 
and Law are absolutely inconsistent particularly by Luther, to whom he 
ascribes the complete removal of every element of law out of the conception 
of the Church : “Luther declared war on every kind of Church law, every kind 
of Divine Church law, and in principle likewise on all Church order which 
is merely human, historical, and therefore changeable, which gives itself out 
to be such of whatever kind it be” ( Kirchenrecht , 7 , 1892 , p. 461). I cannot 
consider this statement accurate in this form. Luther certainly spiritualized 



826 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 


to the utmost the conception of the Church and of religion, and he knew 
neither a quantitative doctrinal belief, but only a spirit which tended towards 
the Gospel as a whole, nor a compulsory orthodoxy, but only religious instruc- 
tion alongside of the suppression of heretical expressions as a disturbing 
rebellion against the Christian order of Society. But since his spiritualized con- 
ception of the Church still has its outward tangibility through supernatural 
concrete signs in the pure Word which is to be kept pure, as also in the Sacra- 
ment which is to be rightly taught and administered, so, then, there arises out 
of this the necessity of creating an apparatus of legal protection and of legally 
regulated administration for them. Luther only does not attempt this as long 
as he leans wholly upon the idea of the miraculous power of the Word which 
will naturally effect everything by its own power, and as long as the old 
ecclesiastical order continues. Later, however, this super-idealism was dis- 
illusioned. In the period of fermentation and of varied local attempts at reform 
Luther allowed the congregations to try to create their own new order of 
administration and he gave this his sanction. When, however, nothing came 
of this and the Peasants’ War brought in its train a dangerous abuse of these 
reforms, he desired a general new order for the sake of the country, and then 
in the new Territorial Church Luther had to tolerate a human apparatus of 
law for the assistance of the Word, and incidentally he even' had to encourage 
it, for which the early beginnings lay in the purity of the doctrine and the 
sacraments and the necessity for an ordered ministry. Out of these relics of a 
visible and concrete Church there arose once more, as at one time out of the 
visibility of the episcopal office, necessarily a law. Here also this does not 
mean that Luther has denied his earlier position, but the reappearance of the 
consequence of the Church conception which at first had been severely checked ; 
this Church conception implied a supernatural and therefore universal institu- 
tion, which in certain definite aspects also needed to be outwardly tangible, 
with a permanent external constitution. If by a Church a supernatural 
institution is meant which is visible in revelation and in sacrament, this then 
produces also out of these supernatural elements a supernaturally established 
law, whether the basis of this law and its creation is left to the congregations 
themselves or handed over to the civil authority; inferences will always be 
drawn out of a basis of (supernatural) fellowship which demands the formation 
of law. Even though its carrying out may be entrusted to circumstances, 
regarded as purely human and liable to be changed at will, the law itself may 
change, but the demand for its formation remains. Only a conception of the 
Church, which has resolved itself into a purity of doctrine and sacraments 
which can dispense with the visible (which is a purely religious general spirit 
and a purely inner fellowship), can dispense with law. But then this would not 
be a conception of the Church at all, and it was not Luther’s conception of 
the Church. That idea is purely the conception of religion as something vital 
which cannot be touched or defined, and its opposition to law is no longer 
the opposition between Church and law, but between religion and law, which 
certainly is a fundamental and real difference. This points, however, to a 
tension between religion and the Church itself which shows that in reality 
the two are not identical. Out of this tension there always arises the emancipa- 
tion of religion from the objectivity of the institution and of the supernatural 
authority, and the turning towards an unlimited inwardness of mysticism and 
of spirituality, as, indeed, the mystics and Spiritual Reformers of the Reforma- 
tion period have done, believing that they were developing to their logical 
conclusion the ideas of the Reformers. Cf. my discussion. Religion und Kirche , 



PROTESTANTISM 


827 

Preuss. Jahrbb ., 1895. The Church conception of Sohm fluctuated between that 
of a universal and supernatural institution and that of a purely spiritual and 
intellectual connection which consists solely in the wealth of its subjective 
personal effects. That, however, is a Church conception adapted to modern 
requirements. Here I must agree with Hofling’s and Ritschl’s conception, 
which Sohm borrows ( p . 467). The passages from Luther on the contrary, 
which Sohm quotes, do not seem to me to prove his thesis, but only to show 
that Luther found it very difficult to combine the spirituality, voluntary 
nature, and inwardness of his idea of a religious community with the necessity 
of law which was required by the need of a pure message and an ordered 
ministry — that law remains to Luther always something human which only 
has to be tolerated, but that in its necessary issuing forth from the Word and 
the Sacrament in itself still is always, at least at the starting-point, a jus divinum . 
Thence also the development of the conception of the ministry in Lutheranism 
and of the constitution of elders in Calvinism. Here certainly there are incon- 
sistencies, but they are involved in a conception of the Church which asserts 
at the same time that it is visible and invisible, voluntary and universal. 
These inconsistencies belong to the conception of the Church itself; they are 
not due to the cofnbination of law with the conception of the Church. There 
will be more about this in the next section. 

210 (P- 484.) For Luther’s conception of the Church, which from the very 
outset was closely connected with the new idea of salvation, its independence 
of Huss, and its inner difference from the Hussite teaching, v. the excellent 
discussion by Gottschick: Huss , Luthers und Zwinglis Lehre von der Kirche , Z- f 
Kirchengeschichte , VIII, 1886. In contrast with the Hussite idea of a fellowship 
of the elect, which works itself out through the institution of the Church, but 
which makes the divinity of the ecclesiastical institutions and of the priests 
dependent upon agreement with the ethical law of Christ and thus approaches 
the Donatist sectarian idea in spite of the assertion of the Catholic nature of 
the sacraments, with complete exclusion of all sectarian making the Church 
dependent upon the realization of the law of Christ, it is the institution 
of grace, or of the Word which by baptism includes all, but which only rules 
all by the word of grace. Therefore here also his emphasis on Scripture is 
different. P. 377: “Huss’s Scriptural principle differs from that of the Reformers 
in this respect — for the Reformers the standard of ideas which forms the main 
content of the Scriptures, and which they, through the authority of the same, 
maintain against the authoritative demands of the Catholic ecclesiastical legal 
institution, is the Gospel of the free grace of God in Christ which grants 
forgiveness apart from all human merit ; for Huss, however, it is the Gospel 
law.” — The presupposition of all this is Infant Baptism and its general exten- 
sion. Both Luther and the population in general which believed in the unity 
of the Christian Society regarded this as obvious ; when in the Visitations 
Luther came across people who had not been baptized, baptism was adminis- 
tered immediately without anyone thinking that this was a compulsory religious 
observance. Cf. Barge: Karlstadt , //, p. 142. Luther never doubted the validity of 
Infant Baptism, and that means he never doubted the necessity for its universal 
administration, as Karl Muller rightly maintains against Barge ; all he had to 
do was to make his idea of the nature of the baptismal process to agree with 
his general idea of the process of salvation, which he effected by his theory of 
a slumbering faith effected in the children. Cf. Karl Muller: Luther und Karlstadt , 
217-221. Thus Luther’s Church conception can never be understood merely 
out of his opposition to the Catholic Church, but also out of his opposition to 



8 a 8 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 


the sects, and here Infant Baptism and its universal character form the decisive 
element. Then there must be added alongside of this opposition to the Catholic 
conception of the Church the setting aside of the jus divinum of the hierarchy, 
the destruction of the concrete conception of the Sacrament and of Grace, the 
reduction of all the effect of the Church, and of redemption to a purely spiritual 
effect of the Word, that is : all the important features which are implied in the 
Catholic conception of the Church : its institutional character, its objectivity, 
its authority over the individual, universality and its dominion over the whole 
of Society, which is here, however, now conceived solely in a spiritual sense. — 
For the close connection of Luther’s conception of the Church withothe idea 
of Infant Baptism, in which the incorporation in the process of salvation of 
the institution of the Word which is based upon faith is completed and thus 
to everyone a basis is given which is independent of his own efforts; cf. Gottschick: 
Die Lehre der Reformation von der Taufe , igo6. Infant Baptism is commanded and 
I know of no place, even when the spiritual struggle was being most hotly 
waged, when the question of baptizing or not baptizing children was ever 
discussed. With that, however, the main thing has been decided : an institutional 
connection which manifests itself primarily in the general use of Infant Bap- 
tism. — That involves the idea of the Corpus Christianum which has been so 
strongly emphasized by Rieker: Die Rechtliche Stellung der ev. Kirchen Deutschlands , 
1903 , and by J. N. Figgis: From Gerson to Grotius, within which its secular and 
spiritual power are only different sides of one undivided whole. That, however, 
is the mediaeval idea of the unity of Christian civilization and Society. Out of 
this idea there result all the main features of Protestant social doctrine. 
Bdhmer thinks that he is speaking against this thesis when he says : “Meanwhile 
in one theoretical point Luther also, it seems, remained in bondage to 
mediaeval thought, that is, in his view of the Church. To him, as to Catholicism, 
the Church was not a free association constituted by men, but an institution 
established by God whose work it is to proclaim the Word of God, to comfort 
men’s hearts, and counsel their consciences. Thus have we here to do really 
only with a transformation of the mediaeval idea? Not at all ; here we have only 
to do with a new formulation of the general Christian view of the Church in 
which once more the specifically Catholic element, namely, the opinion that 
a definite external legal order is essential to the Church, has been completely 
set aside. For faith in the Church as having been established by God through 
which and in which the Spirit of God is active in the world, is as old as 
Christianity” ( p . iso). Certainly, but the decisive point is this, that alongside 
of the Church-type there is the sect-type, which is equally ancient, and it also 
has its roots in the New Testament; further, that the Church-type only effected 
an inner penetration of the Church and the world through Latin Catholicism 
in the Corpus Christianum or in the Christian Society which implied the 
duty of the Government to protect this unity by guaranteeing and protecting 
the institution, and that this idea is continued by Protestantism and 
therefore that the essentially Catholic element does not consist merely in 
uniting the Church to an external legal order. In its continually increasing 
opposition to the sect-type Protestantism conforms to the Church-type, and, 
indeed, to the mediaeval Church-type with its ideal of a uniform Christian 
Society ; and therefore also its social doctrines in many respects are so closely 
related to those of Catholicism. Whether in that we see a limitation or an 
eternal truth is a matter of theological opinion. The fact remains that in the 
modern world the religious roots of the Church conception and therefore of it 
itself have become very weak, and that means that its social doctrines are also 



PROTESTANTISM 


829 

of a quite different type. — For the Lutheran conception of the Church in its 
intellectual form see Kolde: Luthers Stellung zu Konzil und Kirche bis vim Wormser 
Reichstagy 1876; J. Kostlin: Luthers Lehre von der Kirche , 1853; R. Seeberg: Der 
Begriff der christlichen Kirche , /, 1885. 

811 (p. 485.) The idea that, essentially, the Church ought as far as possible 
to control Society, and at the same time to assimilate civilization, has been 
very characteristically formulated by the late President of the Prussian Supreme 
Church Council, H. von der GoltZy in Grundlagen der christlichen Sozialpolitiky igo8 y 
p. 203: “The Church (which to him is, naturally, the same as the ‘religious 
community’) appears in all three forms of social life (namely, the Family, the 
State, ancl Society), but it is not exhausted by any one of them, and cannot 
be supported solely by any one of these forms. As a Church (and, indeed, as a 
universal united Church, which has only been broken in historically by 
Catholic corruption) she asserts a right to an independent existence and 
activity, apart from all the social groups of natural and earthly life. This 
dominant position of the Church in the social world is based on the co-operation 
of four factors : ( 1 ) On the Christian conception of revelation, which recognizes 
in the historic Person of Christ not only the instrument, but also the content, 
of the revelation /)f the Invisible God, and the Church as the organ of the 
perfect final Word of God to men, as the supporter of the absolute religious- 
moral truth (that is, the objective and absolute conception of Truth) ; (2) the 
transference of the real goal of humanity into the future life, so that all that 
is earthly only appears as a school for eternity, and the Church is the mediator 
of the heavenly good (that is, the sole power of the Church to impart salvation) ; 

(3) the union of the separated groups and classes of the world of humanity into 
an international commonwealth, which ethically overcomes all social opposi- 
tion (that is, the universality which is the result of the two previous factors) ; 

(4) the moral quickening, and the harmonious shaping, of the whole life of 
civilization, from the standpoint of religious principle, as the means of com- 
bining all moral tasks into a unity (that is, the acceptance of the life of the 
world which is the consequence of the claim to universality; the fact that this 
secular spirit is incompatible with the New Testament, von der GoltZy like all 
Churchmen, does not feel at all). Through the combination of these four 
factors the Church succeeded in forming for the spiritual life of religion its own 
historical body, which it made important as the highest and most complete 
form of social life. The Church has its most distinctive foundation in Revelation, 
its main aim is the education and union of mankind for eternity, it works 
through its international organization, and in the cultivation of human life 
in the realm of culture.” This characterization is expressly applied to the 
Church as a whole, that is, both to Catholicism and to Protestantism ( pp . 24-30). 
Only within this common framework do the differences appear between 
Catholicism and Protestantism. P. 284: “This conception of the position of 
the Church in the common life of humanity may, however, be interpreted in 
very different ways. The Catholic Church makes its organism an independent 
aim, and everywhere makes the external form as important as the spiritual 
content (?). Protestantism knows that all that is ecclesiastical only has value 
when it is aiming at an inwardly free, but also absolutely firm and certain, 
union, and (here lies the difficulty of the Protestant conception of the Church) 
of the core of the personality ( !) with God.” This logical and likewise un- 
imaginative statement shows the complicated character of the Protestant 
conception of the Church. It does not become any clearer in the following 
attempt at a closer definition: “The Church may not treat her changeable 



830 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

corporate form and doctrine, ritual and constitution as an aim, but as times 
change these things must be regarded as methods which are adjusted to these 
changes, in order to cultivate communion with God in the hearts of men, and 
to have a purifying and hallowing influence inwardly upon the world of civiliza- 
tion. And even if, in so doing, her rightful influence is threatened, she must 
not cling to external supports, but she must make her services desirable, and 
radiate the righteousness of God as a victorious power into the consciences of 
men. Only with such a high conception of her ethical tasks, based upon the 
right spirit, can the Church maintain her healthy (that is, not compulsorily 
formed, and therefore joyfully supported) relation to the tasks of civilization, 
and to the various groups of natural moral fellowship.’ * In these expressions 
all the peculiarities of the Church conception, and all the particular difficulties 
of the Protestant Church conception, are found together ; the latter consist in 
the combination of inner freedom and absolute stability, of universal dominion 
and spiritual propagation combined with the renunciation of all compulsory 
authority, of a future and eternal goal and a harmonious permeation of 
civilization, of an objective institution and a personal religion of sentiment. 
Also the relation of this Church to “natural” society, which von der Goltz 
constructs, is only a modern form of the Lutheran Lex J{aturae, and of the 
social system which is evolved from it. Similarly, one of the most active 
ecclesiastical leaders of the Conservatives, R. Seeberg , describes a “healthy 
piety” as one which is both “Churchly” and friendly to civilization, that is, 
“pressing into the business of life and sanctifying it” ( Die Kirchlich-Soziale Idee 
und die Aufgaben der Theologie der Gegenwart , Z ur sjyst. Theol. , II, igog, p. 327). 
This is required “both by the nature of man and by the history of civilization 
and of religion” ( p . 328). “All forms of the natural life in the State, and in 
politics, in trade and industry, in science and in art, also all the great doings 
of the mighty ones of the world, and all the work of everyday men and women, 
are to the Christian the workings of God, in which is prepared and realized 
the coming of his Kingdom. The distinction between the State and the Church, 
however important it may be in other directions, ought never to mean that 
God is only active in the Church, or that God’s servants are free from the 
duty of serving Him in the family, in the national life, in society, and in the 
State” (p. 334 ). This means the dominion of the Church over civilization 
apart from the hierarchical methods of authority, and the dominating spirit 
of Catholicism. For Seeberg this is the natural meaning of Jesus, and of the 
New Testament: “The redeeming dominion of God (made effective through 
the Church and the ministry) is the creative and guiding principle of human 
history, and it so organizes this history along lines of development completed 
through mutual influence as to lead to the goal of the Kingdom of God. 
Both these primitive Christian ( !) ideas determine the peculiar world-view of 
Christianity” (p. 333). Therefore, to Seeberg, as also to the Catholics Mausbaeh , 
von Nostitz-Rieneck, and others, the Church is the “principle of progress”. Owing 
to the fact that it is based upon absolute Divine truths, the Church is naturally, 
in the main, absolutely conservative, but “the brake is also a method of progress, 
since without it the carriage would roll over the nearest precipice and be 
smashed to bits”. All these ideas are in reality also the leading ideas of the 
Lutheran conception of the Church, only they have been translated into the 
flatness of modern academic terminology, without any understanding of the 
difficult problems which Luther felt these ideas contained. 

111 (p. 487O For the development of the authority and sole infallibility of 
the Bible, together with the establishment of this infallibility upon the practical 



PROTESTANTISM 


831 

experience of salvation which is the sole experience of redemption in the Bible, 
see Preuss: Entwickelung des Schriftprinzips bei Luther ,1901. On pp. 6, 14, and 60, 
the author rightly distinguishes it from the Humanist principle of Scripture 
which uses historical methods and studies the sources, thus leading it to an 
estimate of the original situation, but in no way leading to a basis of religious 
infallibility. He also treats very aptly the relation with mysticism which ignores 
the mediation of the Church and of the Bible in its immediate intercourse with 
God : Luther modifies the idea of the union of the soul with God to mean the 
union of the soul with the Word, and always relates the general principle of 
revelation !tnd redemption of the Logos to Christ and the Word of Christ ; 
he does this to such an extent that even the glory of the Creation through the 
Logos, the Christian view of Nature, is mediated through meditation on Christ 
and the Word. For the relation between Luther’s free and critical treatment 
of Scripture and his view of the infallibility of the Scriptures which he held 
firmly at the same time, see Scheel: Luthers Stellung zur h. Schrift , 1902 . Luther, 
and above all the Lutheran Church, found in the end that they could not 
unite both and they gave up the former in favour of the latter. That, however, 
was only the logical result of the need of ecclesiastical authority and organiza- 
tion. It could not be helped, there was simply nothing else to be done. The 
attempts of present-day theologians to return to Luther’s earlier theory of 
Scripture, which combined criticism and authority and only used the Scriptures 
as the standard for practical religious life, presuppose first the stability of 
existing churches which could only have been gained by the orthodox theory 
of Scripture, and, secondly, will never be able to create unity, since nowhere 
at all can we draw an authoritative line. The principle of Scripture which is 
bound up with the conception of the Church and of absolute truth, and a 
unity in standard and doctrine, must inevitably develop into orthodox doctrine, 
just as the institution of the Papacy issues in the infallible monarchical seat of 
doctrinal authority, and modern orthodoxy which accepts higher criticism is 
in the same position as Catholic Modernism, which tries to turn the Papacy 
into a system of authority and supervision which is merely pedagogical in 
character. 

213 (P- 49 1 -) Eieker, who has also triumphantly vindicated the significance of 
the mediaeval idea of the Corpus Christianum for Luther, has certainly found 
difficulties in this “Congregational” ideal. He has tried to solve them too easily 
by describing them as a mistaken bias towards the Baptist sect-type (he seems 
to base these remarks on some meagre suggestions by Achelis on this question) ; 
he seems to consider that this phase of Luther’s life was a tribute which he paid 
to the tendencies of the time, with which he had little affinity ( Rieker,pp . 74-86; 
Achelis: System der Prakt. Theol. , /, 99 ff.). Against this interpretation Walther 
Kohler has reacted in a very instructive piece of research : Die Entstehung der 
reformatio ecclesiarum Hassiae von 1926 ', Deutsche Z.f. Kirchenrecht , 1906, pp . 199-232, 
and in an article, Z u Luthers Kir chenbe griff, Christl. Welt, 1907 , pp . 371-377 . 
His view is that the previous theory is a misunderstanding and an under- 
estimate of the Congregational ideal. That was followed by the penetrating 
research of Drews : Entsprach das Staatskirchentum dem Ideal Luthers? 1908, who 
answers this question in the negative, and who pleads that the Congregational 
ideal can very well be united with the fundamental idea of the Church, but 
that it was limited at that time because of the period of transition in which 
it was conceived ; all that matters is the establishment of the Word, the method 
employed to do this is indifferent ; since finally this could only be effected with 
the aid of the territorial lord, whose assistance Luther accepted as a service of 



832 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

love but not as dominion. Still more decided in his views of the connection 
between the Congregational ideal and actual local conditions is Karl Midler: 
Luther und Karlstadt , pp. 217-223) 123, who emphasizes the necessity for this 
arrangement along with the ancient patronage system. Cf. also Hermelink: 
Zu Luthers Gedanken ueber Ideal gemeinden und von Weltlicher Obrigkeit , Z-f- Kirchen - 
geschichte, 1308, pp. 267-322 , where it is shown that this Congregational ideal was 
connected with Apocalyptic expectations, and at the same time the anti- 
democratic attitude of the congregations was represented as far as possible by 
the local authority. For our subject the important point is that in all this in 
any case the idea of the Church itself is preserved, in spite of an apparent 
approximation to the sect-type ; see also Troeltsch: Trennung von Staat und Kirche , 
pp. 9-23. For Luther it seemed absolutely obvious that in all this the religious 
form within a given territory and the territory itself should coincide (Drews, 
p. 99), and all the early renunciation of any attempt at overriding men’s 
consciences still only meant a temporary attitude of laissez-faire based upon 
confidence in the Word ; the civil authority further had to suppress all open 
blasphemy and sedition, that is, all disturbance of the unity of the Christian 
Society. Of this more anon. In these expressions about the Congregational 
ideal of 1522-1525, it is clear that there lies a peculiar problem which was not 
merely local nor temporary, and which is of extreme interest for the sociological 
significance of the Lutheran conception of the Church. It is an attempt within 
the general Christian Society, and the institutional Christianity composed of 
all who have been baptized, to found smaller groups in which radical Christian 
piety will be realized without any intention of allowing these smaller groups 
to remove the general ecclesiastical character from the Church. Kohler calls it 
“a parallelism of a Christian Society which is organized and controlled by the 
State and a system of smaller groups for worship and fellowship”. “When 
Luther gave up the attempt to carry out this idea it was taken over by the 
Anabaptists, thence it was taken over by Bucer and finally from him by 
Calvin” (Christl. Welt, p. 470). The chief point, however, is this: that in so 
doing the Anabaptists cut themselves off from the wider circle of the Christian 
society which was being ruled : they used baptism only as adult baptism for 
mature Christians and they placed the fellowship composed of those who 
had been baptized in that way, in open opposition to the secularized morality 
of the so-called Christendom and the Church. Calvinism, on the contrary, 
transformed “the smaller groups” into the whole Church, and gave them the 
structure of a universal Church within which care is taken to develop the 
personal Christian piety of all the citizens and Church members. The Baptists 
discard the idea of the Church altogether ; Calvinism transforms the ideal of 
these smaller groups into an institutional Church which agrees with the 
territory in which it is placed. In those expressions during the first half of the 
twenties (in the sixteenth century) Luther is obviously seeking a middle way. 
Since, however, from the outset the idea of the Church is absolutely pre- 
dominant, it is not surprising that once a definite order had been established 
he developed the logical implications of the idea of the Church to their fullest 
extent, and gave up both the formation of smaller groups and also the idea of 
transferring the administration of Church-order only to the parishes. He was 
prevented from developing this idea in the Calvinistic sense both by circum- 
stances and by his ecclesiastical idea of grace which was opposed to all legalism, 
while Calvinism in reality replaced the idea of the Church with a sectarian 
element of compulsion. This subject will be treated in greater detail in the 
section devoted to Calvinism. 



PROTESTANTISM 


633 

114 (p. 492.) The idea of a Society inspired by a uniform world-view is 
undoubtedly mediaeval, but it is still a vital problem which has not yet been 
solved. There cannot be a real social coherence at all without the unity of the 
world-view, and it is good for us to remember that in contrast to the modern 
anarchy in the view of the world which has such a disintegrating influence 
upon Society and religious thought, two so very different thinkers as the 
Romantic Novalis and the sober Empiricist Auguste Comte deliberately look 
back to the Middle Ages as the classic epoch of a social unity based upon 
unity of ideas. At the present day we have an example of the same thing in 
social democracy. Also the conservative parties and the Churchmen of to-day 
use the same principle, even though somewhat weakened ; see Loofs: Luthers 
Stellung zu M. A. und JVeuzeit , iqoj , p. ig: “On the other hand, the gulf between 
Luther and the modern day has not been fixed so irrevocably as Trocltsch 
believes. Had we not ourselves until 1874 practically compulsory baptism? 
Is it not a fact that blasphemy is still an offence punishable by law? And have 
we not still to-day a civilization of authority of a Christian tinge which upon 
the whole has compulsory religious instruction? . . . Actually the idea of what 
constitutes blasphemy is interpreted very differently from the ideas of Luther, 
but from the formal point of view the difference is not so great.* * That is 
undoubtedly true, especially for Prussia, but it is still only a proof that the 
same motives are here at work as there were in the mediaeval social order, and 
that the Protestant compulsory civilization is to be interpreted in exactly the 
same sense as the mediaeval. Luther’s retention of the unity of the religious 
idea has certainly not merely the significance of a mediaeval prejudice, but it 
is a result of a unified conception of Society and of an absolute revealed 
knowledge of truth which is entirely logical. When, however, this goal had 
been set up, methods were also desired in order to reach it, and the same 
process will be continually repeated. 

215 (p. 494 ) Here also Luther’s statements are contradictory according to 
the time when they were uttered, and the situation and the collection and 
interpretation of these statements vary greatly ; it all depends upon the object 
which they are meant to serve ; they may be used for apologetic or for con- 
troversy, for history or for doctrine. Wappler has published from the records 
of Zwickau a whole series of the records of religious trials, enactments of the 
Government, professional decisions of the Wittenberg theologians and jurists, 
which reveal the pressure on conscience exercised by the Visitation in a most 
terrible and petty manner ; see Wappler: Inquisition und Ketzerprozesse in Zwickau 
zur Reformationzeit , igo8. He has combined with this a presentation of state- 
ments of Luther and Melancthon which emphasize very clearly the contrast 
between the earlier attitude of toleration and non-intervention on the part 
of the civil authority in the free spiritual struggle, with the later exhortation 
to punish all rioting and disturbance of the peace with banishment in order to 
preserve the external order of Society, and at the same time the Christian social 
order, until it was so far developed as to regard every heretical doctrine as the 
disturber of peace and unity to be punished with extreme severity, even to the 
point of death. When, however, he tests the Reformers by the modern idea of 
toleration which places ethics in the forefront and doctrine in a less important 
position, and then interprets their departure from this ideal because of their 
appeals to the Old Testament as the fruit of the sinister Old Testament spirit 
of revenge, he forgets in the first place that the Reformers Just like the mediaeval 
thinkers, had the same conception of absolute truth to whom the modern 
idea of toleration, with the possibility of various forms of truth (all having a 
vol. n. BB 



834 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

right to their individual existence alongside of one another), would have 
seemed like frivolous scepticism and blasphemy: he also overlooks the fact 
that the Old Testament is here called in in order to find a Scriptural basis 
for things which could not be justified from the New Testament, and 
which yet, because they were inevitable in practice, had to find a basis 
somewhere. Further examples in horrifying fullness are given by Barge's 
Karlstadt in spite of the modifications made by Karl Muller . From the Catholic 
standpoint N. Paulus: Luther und die Gewissensfreiheit y 1905, collects passages 
on the same subject. He explains the earlier demand for toleration as the 
toleration of a minority, that is, as a demand addressed to the Roman Catholic 
princes not to interfere with spiritual matters and not to hinder the Gospel, 
and he shows how at the same time Luther regarded the abolition of the Mass 
by the authority which was sympathetic towards the Reformation as a duty 
of a Christian Government. He also argues that freedom of discussion was 
only allowed to the Anabaptists and fanatics so long as he believed he could 
easily cope with them, but that so soon as real opposition developed this 
toleration ceased at once and was replaced by the severest suppression. In 
general this is certainly in both directions not far from the truth ; but it leaves 
out of account the inner motive which caused Luther to act, not merely out 
of opportunism, but out of the necessity of his conception of the Church; 
this at first led him to lay stress on the purely inward spiritual building up of 
the communities, and a purely spiritual way of overcoming opposition in 
confidence in the invincibility of the pure Word. On p. 27 there is an interesting 
quotation in which Luther replies thus to the argument that the Emperor 
was really in sympathy with his doctrine, and, therefore, that he would not 
take it amiss if he enforced it compulsorily : “We know that he is not certain 
of that matter, and that he cannot be certain because we know that he errs 
and strives against the Gospel : the Emperor is under the obligation to know 
God’s Word and like us to further it with all his power.” This is the real heart 
of the matter, as most of the other students realize by quoting this same passage, 
and it is intelligible that from such a fundamental conviction, amid so much 
obstinate opposition, Luther came to feel finally that force might be used, 
and, indeed, must be used in defence of the truth, both in the interest of the 
defenceless, the weak, and those who are easily led astray, as well as in the 
interest of the Christian unity of the Church and of Society. Paulus rightly 
censures the statement of the modern orthodox Lutheran apologist W. Walther : 
“Every impartial man must feel that Luther did the only right thing when he 
tried to arrange that in each country there should be only one Confession” 
( p . 13). There is no need to point to the Imperial law against heretics, to the 
social and political danger which was caused by the existence of the Anabap- 
tists, to the pressure of the surrounding Catholic States (as the learned pastor, 
Bossert, with a great sense of superiority to Wappler , brings out) in order to 
excuse the Reformers who ought to be judged in a relative manner ( Theol . 
Litztg-> 1908, p- 153)- The new law against heresy, the demand for censorship, 
and the unity of the Confessions, is ultimately due to the Reformers’ conception 
of truth and of the Church, and the inconsistencies are inconsistencies which 
belong to the nature of this conception of the Church, which desires a universal 
Christian Church and social order, and yet at the same time to have an inward 
and spiritual influence. This proved impossible in practice : so force was tried, 
and these duties were entrusted to the civil authority as duties which belonged 
to the exercise of Christian love and were based upon Natural Law, which 
limited the purely spiritual character of ecclesiastical self-propagation to one of 



PROTESTANTISM 


835 

theological exhortation, which preceded the government condemnation- verdict, 
and to the toleration of a mistaken faith which is maintained in secret and 
makes no public expression of opinion. This is in reality the ancient Catholic 
law against heresy, as Paulus says, only “with this essential difference that 
Melancthon grants to the civil authority as the most important member of 
the Church the real decision in matters of faith, whereas on the Catholic side 
the decision of religious doctrine is kept in the hands of the infallible Church. 
Melancthon, indeed, also desired that in doubtful cases the princes would 
allow themselves to be guided by the council of the theologians ; but in the 
last resort tfic civil authority always made the final decision” ( p . 43). In that 
there is expressed the retention of the spiritual methods of working and the 
characterization of heresy as tumult and a disturbance of Christian Society ; 
but also this implies the continuance of the Catholic idea of the unity of 
Christian Society, which for its part is a logical result of the conception of the 
universality of the Church. Within the common whole the emphasis has been 
shifted, and in this shifting of emphasis the spirituality of the new idea of the 
Church has been asserted. This has been very rightly emphasized as the vital 
point by W. Kohler: Reformation und Ketzerprozess , igoi , pp. si-26, who also shows 
how difficult the Reformers found it to give up their original idea of the 
omnipotent character of thought or of the Word, and how finally the trans- 
ference of the heresy legislation to the secular power as the protector of the 
Christian unity of Society still also required the preparation of a purely 
ecclesiastical heresy legislation, upon the basis of which the secular authority 
could then act. This handing over to the secular authority belongs to the 
establishment of the heresy law upon the Law of Nature which Melancthon 
argues (p. 29), which, gathered up in the Decalogue, prescribes the protection 
of the First Table, that is, especially of the office of the ministry, which is here 
sanctioned by the secular authority. The new element, however, is still there, 
that the suppression does not take place in the name of the Church and through 
the Church, but in the name of the Christian order of Society and through the 
State, whereas the only aim of the purely ecclesiastical heresy trial is the 
preservation of the purity of doctrine. The secular arm does not execute a 
sentence passed by the supreme authority in the Church, but the State protects 
Christian Society and itself in its own name. The effect, however, is the same. — 
It is incredible that Hermelink: Der Toleranzgedanke im Ref.~Zeilalter , 1908 , 
faced with all that, can picture Luther as the herald of the modern liberty of 
conscience. Even in the mediaeval system it was not Christianity, but the 
neo-Platonic element mingled with it which was the father of intolerance l ! 
Luther is supposed to have led the Church back to depend solely upon a 
spiritual and inward influence, and when the Reformers handed over the right 
of the punishment of heretics and the duty of establishing a unity of faith by 
compulsion, it only means that they held a conception of the State which had 
not yet been purified by their new knowledge — a conception of the State, that is, 
of the Renaissance, Machiavelli’s Supreme Power of the State ! ! The Baptists, 
on the other hand, are said to have had nothing to do with toleration. “They 
were intolerant towards the State and non-Baptist Christendom in a 
dangerous manner”, with which, in Wappler , one might compare the state- 
ments of the entirely passive Baptists ! ! Luther’s conception of truth in which 
the “spiritual and invisible” is an established truth which God breathes into 
the hearts of believers, and in which “all that fights against this ... is a bit of 
the devil’s work”, is said to be a relic left over from mediaeval Neo-Platonism, 
which only appears in isolated instances ! ! etc. Things could not be twisted 



836 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

in a more mad and stupid way, and this kind of apologetic it is which makes so 
many theological works insupportable to those who are not professional 
theologians. 

216 (P* 494-) O n Luther’s ethic the best book is still that by Luthardt: Die 
Ethik Luthers in Ihren Grundzilgen , 1867. Here, however, all tensions and difficulties 
have been smoothed away, till the whole system looks as though it were com- 
pletely uniform and logical. He has found this easier to do because he does not 
touch practically the whole of the social philosophy. The excellent work by 
Eger: Die Anschauungen Luthers von Beruf \ 1900, is an historical work which 
emphasizes quite rightly the various tensions ; he is, however, only wrong when 
he deduces the tension from the after-effect of monasticism instead of from 
primitive Christian Radicalism, or to the dialectic incapacity of Luther to 
gain a systematic deduction of civilization and the ethic of humanity con- 
ceptually and the inner difficulty of the whole matter. For the early period, 
Braun: Concupiscenz, is valuable. Excellent, and also of value for Luther himself, 
is Hupfeld: Die Ethik Joh. Gerhards. Ein Beitrag zum Verstandnis der Lutherischen 
Ethik , 1908; here also it is precisely the subject of the social philosophy and 
the analysis of the tensions and inconsistencies which is ignored. On the 
contrary, these difficulties are treated with great energy, but without the 
knowledge of the main conceptions which illuminate the whole subject; 
Lommatzsch: Luthers Lehre von Etisch-religidsen Standpunkt aus , mit hesonderer 
Beriicksichtigung seiner Theorie von Gesetz, 1879. Excellent detailed researches 
are offered by Gottschick: Ethik , 1908. For my view as a whole I must refer to 
my work, Grundprohleme der Ethik Z-f- Theol. und Kirche, XII, 1902. 

217 (p* 495-) this point Kapp is excellent : Religion und Moral im Christentum 
Luthers, 1902 ; Herrmann: Verkehr des Christen mit Gott 6 , 1908 ; Thieme: Die Sittliche 
Triebkraft des Glauhens y 1899. The essence of the ethic which is determined by 
religion is this, that here the religious relation itself is the absolute value and 
the absolute obligation, and that therefore all moral values — whether of self- 
cultivation or in the formation of a relation with one’s fellow men — are placed 
at the service of this supreme aim. This is how Jesus understood the matter 
as has already been shown. And thus also is it interpreted by Luther; the 
repetition by Luther is a confirmation of an idea which has been developed by 
Luther; see above,/). 57 (against this and agreeing with Harnack’s objections 
meanwhile, Thieme: Christl. Welt , 1909, pp. 77/ ff.; Bedeutung der Nachstenliebe bei 
Jesus). From this point of view the first duty is that of self-conquest and self- 
surrender to God, and the next duty is love to one’s neighbour for the sake of 
God, with the intention of being united with one’s neighbour in God. That 
both these ideas are the meaning of the Lutheran doctrine of the love of God 
and the love of man, see the apt proofs in W. W alther: Die Christliche Sittlichkeit 
nach Luther, 1909, p. 99, and in Thieme: Triebkraft, pp. 17-53. Let me quote a 
few passages from Luther according to Thieme: “Ingressus in Christum est 
fides, egressus autem est caritas, quae nos justitia Dei indutos distribuit in 
obsequia proximi et exercitium proprii corporis ad succurendum alienae 
paupertati, ut et ipsi per nos attracti nobiscum ingrediantur in Christum” 
(p. 289) ; or the well-known and important passage : “Out of all this we come 
to the conclusion that a Christian man lives not in himself, but in Christ and 
his neighbour : in Christ through faith, in his neighbour through love. Through 
iaith he goes out of himself into God, from God he again descends through love 
and yet remains always in God and in the divine love” (p. 284) ; or : “When a 
Christian begins to know Christ as his Lord and Saviour through Whom he is 
redeemed from death and brought into His glory and honour, his heart becomes 



PROTESTANTISM 


837 

so full of God that he would like to help everyone to enter into the same joy. 
For he has no higher joy than to rejoice that he knows Christ (that is, the real 
ethical fulfilment of personality). Therefore the Christian goes forth from 
himself, teaches and exhorts other men, exalts and confesses Christ before 
everyone, pleads and sighs that they might also come to such an experience of 
the grace of God. That is a kind of divine unrest in the midst of the highest 
repose, repose in God’s grace and peace which will not allow a man to be 
idle, but urges him ever to aspire and wrestle with all his powers, to live only 
to exalt the honour and praise of God amongst men that others also may 
receive such a spirit of grace” ( p . 297). That is the ethic of the Gospel expressed 
in somewhat different language as it has been expressed also by Augustine 
and Bernard in their language as love to God and love to creatures in God. 
Thieme asks the question, somewhat scholastically, whether in all this there 
is not a love of one’s neighbour for his own sake, and answers it rightly by 
saying that it is precisely the highest welfare of the neighbour which is served 
when through showing him the love of God the love of God itself and that 
happiness is kindled within the neighbour himself. This idea lies virtually and 
unconsciously at the basis of the passages where all that is mentioned is help 
and assistance to Qne’s neighbour. This is certainly right, and it explains why 
in the ethic of Luther as in that of Jesus the social conditions of ordinary life 
are of no ethical value in themselves, but they are only regarded as methods 
and opportunities to develop such values out of the religious temper. 

218 (P- 496.) The following quotation illustrates the logical results of these 
ideas : “Now behold, these people do not need any sword or law of this world. 
And if all the world were true Christians, that is, true believers, then no 
prince, king, lord, sword, or law would be necessary” ( Lommatzsch , 2oy). 
Renunciation of one’s own honour ( Lommatzsch , 240) , at the same time 
with the admission that “only a few and very highly spiritual men” are capable 
of such praise. It would be a very good thing if some scholar would give us 
a study of Luther’s relation to the Sermon on the Mount. The aloofness from 
the world which is expressed in the Gospel in eschatological terms, but which 
in Luther primarily has a mystical basis, finds its classic expression in the 
famous treatise on the Freiheit eines Christenmenschen. The chief passages of the 
German text ( Berliner Ausgabe , I 1 ) : “Here then we will answer those who are 
angereef by the aforesaid speeches, and who often say : ‘Oh, then, if faith is 
everything and is enough to make us religious, why then are good works 
required? Let us make merry and do nothing.’ No, my dear fellow, thou must 
not act thus, that were only possible if thou wert an entirely inward and 
spiritual man, but that will not happen till the Last Day. . . . Although man 
in his soul is sufficiently justified by faith, and has all that he ought to have, 
excepting that the same faith must increase into that life, yet he still remains 
in this bodily life upon earth, and must rule his own body, and mix with men. 
This is where works begin : here he must not be idle, the body must be exercised 
with fasting and prayer, with toil and labour, and with all moderate discipline, 
that it may become obedient, and conform to the inward man, and to faith, 
and not hinder and resist it as is its manner where it is not forced” ( p . 306). 
“Thence, each man must learn how to chastise the body in all modesty; for he 
fasts, watches, labours, as long as he sees that the body needs to be kept down 
by the will . . .” ( p . 507). “As Adam in Paradise, in order not to be idle, was 
told to labour, so a believing man also needs to labour, — not in order to make 
him a religious man, but that he be not idle, he is commanded to prepare 
and preserve his body to do such good works solely in order to please God”. . . 



838 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

(p. 308). This must be said of works in general and of those which a Christian 
man must exercise in order to subdue his own body. Now will we speak more 
of the works which he does to other men. For man does not live simply in his 
own body, but among other men upon earth. Therefore he cannot live apart 
from other men ; he must speak with them, and have to do with them, although 
these same works are not necessary to salvation. Therefore in all his works 
his intention should be freely directed to serving, and being useful to other 
people, and to undertaking nothing save that which is of use to other people 
(p. 312 ). “However much the work of Christ was needed and has served to 
produce piety or salvation, so also are His other works, and the works of 
Christians, needed by them for salvation, since they are all services rendered 
freely for the good of others. ... In like manner St. Paul, in Romans xiii 
and Titus iii, exhorts Christians that they should be subject to the authority 
of this world, not that this will make them religious, but in order that in so 
doing they may freely serve others, and the Government, by doing their will 
in love and freedom.” Thus it is also possible for love’s sake to submit to 
unchristian institutions and laws (p. 314). That the latter, from the point of 
view of such an ethic of love, has its difficulties, and requires actions which are 
inconsistent with this ideal, Luther was quite aware ( Lemmatzsch , p. 287) ; 
in any case, however, this motivation means a complete indifference to the 
actual political, legal, and economic values of the world. — It cannot be denied 
that these ideas can be traced to St. Augustine (see Hunzinger: Luthers tudien, /, 
1906) and to German and Bernardine mysticism {Braun: Bedeutung der Con - 
cupiszenz ). The most important thing, however, is to realize clearly that this 
is only the transformation of the radicalism of the Sermon on the Mount 
which became the prevalent point of view after the time of Augustine, the 
mystically based and interpreted exposition of the commands of absolute 
self-sanctification for God, and of absolute brotherly love, with the complete 
disappearance of the secular virtues of conflict and justice. The command to 
renounce rights and worldly honours, and completely to surrender the spirit 
to God has become the command of humility and of the love of self only in 
God, and the command of brotherly love as the manifestation of the love of 
God, has become the mystical love of the brethren in God, with the mortifica- 
tion of all selfishness. The conversio ad Deum means turning towards the only 
true Being, and the union of brethren in this one Reality; the substitution of 
the radical ethic of love for the merely relative virtues, gained in the struggle 
for existence, has become a turning away from the untrue and the unreal 
non-being of the world which leads to selfishness and multiplicity. In this 
interpretation, however, Luther follows throughout the primitive Christian 
Radicalism — indeed, he went into the cloister for that reason, for in the 
monastery alone, however much altered, the radical ethic had been main- 
tained. Thence he only came through gradually to a new development of this 
Radicalism, which carried it into the everyday life of every individual, without 
externally removing it ; in connection with this also the mystical interpretation 
went back more and more to the real meaning of the Sermon on the Mount. 

919 (P* 497-) It is undeniable that Luther’s Gemeindeideal — that is, the regula- 
tion of the calling of pastors and the control of the behaviour of parishioners 
(which starts from the individual) — is connected with an interpretation of the 
Christian ethic in the sense of the communism of love and a strict observance 
of the Christian rules of life ; the Leisnig Ordinance lays stress upon the latter 
element, and the little pamphlets entitled Dass eine christl. Gemeinde Recht habe 
alle Lekre zu urteilen und Lehrer zu beru/en, and Von der Ordnung des Gottesdienstes 



PROTESTANTISM 


839 

in der Gemeinde, emphasize the former; both, however, have the same aim. 
In the preface to the former Luther approves “that you have undertaken to 
make a new order of public worship and to hold goods in common according 
to the example of the Apostles (that is, of the Primitive Church)”. B.A. , IV, /, 
p . in; in the Ordinance itself it is said : “We have received a thorough know- 
ledge that all the inner and outer possessions of Christian believers should 
serve and be used for the glory of God and for the love of one’s neighbour, for 
one’s fellow Christians according to the ordering of Divine truth and not 
according to human ideas” ( p . 117) ; at the same time the congregation has 
provided for a strict Church discipline ( pp . u8ff.). This is undoubtedly an 
approximation to the sect-type ; we must, however, remember that W. Kohler 
not only rightly points out that this is the source of the Baptist and Calvinist 
ideals, but also that other very important things were involved in both of these. 
Calvin especially is less concerned with the exercise of the priesthood of 
all believers than with the founding of a holy community ordered by God ; 
cf. below. Luther is also clear that a community of those who “earnestly wish 
to be Christians and confess the Gospel with hand and mouth” (p. 168) cannot 
be a Church of the masses, at least not at first. Therefore, in the famous intro- 
duction to the Masse deutsch , there is the idea of a more select body of com- 
municants within the external Church who attend the preaching service 
and undergo Christian instruction, thus distinguishing between “an ordered 
and certain gathering within which one could rule Christians according to 
the Gospel”, and the great parish where is “only public stimulus to faith and 
to Christianity.” “In this order one would be able to know, punish, improve, 
cast out, or excommunicate those who did not behave in a Christian manner 
according to the rule of Christ (Matthew xviii. 15). Here also it would be 
possible to ask the Christians all to give alms together ; these would be given 
willingly and shared out among the poor according to the example of St. 
Paul, 2 Cor. ix. 1” (pp. 167 ff.). This is one of the chief passages upon which 
the Pietists later on based their idea of the ecclesiola in ecclesia; Luther, 
however, does not intend a withdrawal out of a secularized Church, but he 
wishes to create progressive kernel organizations of the converting Spirit 
within the Church. Luther, however, finds that he has not got the earnest 
Christians whom he requires, and, on the other hand, he is afraid that “this 
might lead to faction, so I am putting it out of my head”, that is, he would 
not allow it to develop of itself (p. 169). Thus Luther renounces the idea of such 
“peculiar communities” (p. 169). Eger, pp. 77-89, has a right view of this 
subject. 

280 (P* 49^0 On this point, cf. especially the treatise : Wider die himmlischen 
Propheten, 1524 . In this Luther follows Paulinism. But it is important to note 
that in so doing it is the ecclesiastical element of Paulinism which he follows. 
The socially conservative position which Paulinism adopted in its own day 
is not, it is true, like the Catholic ethic, an absorption of the secular institutions 
into the Christian ethic, but it is a waiting and a toleration and an enduring 
and a cautious use of the ordinances of a world which God still permits to exist. 
But even this very restricted acceptation of the world was only possible to Paul 
through his conception of grace, since this conception of grace fills the Christian 
community as a whole with the redeeming energies of Christ, and therefore 
takes away from them the responsibility of fixing a limit by a radical external 
separation and activity of the individual ; see Wernle: Der Christ und die Siinde bei 
Paulus, 1897, pp . 60-72, in which, however, the connection between the Pauline 
“conception of theChurch” and the idea of Grace is not sufficiently emphasized^ 



840 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

This predominance of the idea of grace gives to the whole of religious thought 
in general a bias to accept the existing order as a Divine decree which is not 
to be altered by force. 

221 (p. 498.) This idea of the impossibility of overcoming sin is a remarkable 
divergence from Paulinism, which in the certainty of a complete renewal and 
transformation of Christians considers it natural that sin should be overcome : 
in it also the defects of individual Church members were regarded as stains 
and shortcomings in the real ideal of the Church ; these are to be got rid of by 
discipline, and will be burnt up in the Judgment and End of the World which 
is imminent. Cf. Wernle: Der Christ und die Siinde , and Braun : Luthers Lehre von der 
Concupiszenz, pp. 107-11 2. In that, however, there are also the sectarian elements 
of Paul as they are contained in that Enthusiasm which he proclaims alongside 
of the consummation of revelation in Christ. The sects until the present day for 
this reason continue to appeal to these ideas. In Paulinism both types are 
still together. 

222 (p. 499.) For the naturalness of the idea of the Corpus Christianum see the 
following passages in Lommatzsch , 258, 575, 282, 527 ff. That is plainly shown in 
the description of the three hierarchies of the civil authority, of the household, 
and of the clergy as estates of the Church. Cf. also Rieker: f, Rechtliche Stellung , 
pp. 66-71. Both recognize in this, and rightly, the continuation of the mediaeval 
idea whose origin in the ideas of the primitive Church cannot, however, be 
explained quite so easily and simply. In the second main section of this work 
it was my intention to make this clear. If that result is right, we may then draw 
the conclusion that in spite of all reactions to Paulinism and Augustinianism, 
the Reformation ethic, and the social philosophy which issued from it, continues 
the mingling of the Church and the world in an undifferentiated unity, and 
only rearranges the relation between the elements which compose this unity; 
so also Ehrhardt: La notion du droit nature /, pp. 308 ff. 

223 (p. 500.) Cf. Luthardypp . 76 ff. : “Luther based his position on the distinc- 
tion between the Kingdom of God and the kingdom of this world (as he calls 
it), or, in other words, upon the tenet of the inwardness of Christianity con- 
trasted with the external life in the world, which is based upon the Creation 
(it would be more accurate to say, upon Reason). . . . After the doctrine of 
justification by faith there is perhaps scarcely any other doctrine which Luther 
mentions so often, and propagates so earnestly, as this doctrine of the spiritual 
and inward character of the Kingdom of Christ, and of the difference between 
it and the kingdom of this world, that is, the sphere of the natural created life. 
Primarily, the Gospel has nothing at all to do with the external life ; it is wholly 
concerned with eternal life ; it is not concerned with external ordinances and 
institutions which might come into conflict with the ordinances of the world, 
but with the hearts of men and their relation to God, with the grace of God, 
with the forgiveness of sins, etc., in short, with the heavenly life. The charac- 
teristic element of the Kingdom of Christ is the order of grace (and love), 
the characteristic of the kingdom and the life of this world is the system of law. 
Therefore they are quite different in quality, and do not belong to the same 
plane; indeed, they belong to different worlds. To the one I belong as a 
Christian, to the other as a man (this is the modern way of putting it, Luther 
would have said : T belong to the one through the Gospel, and to the other 
through the Lex Naturae'). For we live in two spheres of life, we are in heaven 
and upon earth at the same time. . . . ‘Christ’s Kingdom*, says Luther, ‘is, and 
ought to be, a Divine Kingdom, and yet the same spiritual Kingdom is inter- 
woven with the kingdom of this world, and Christ and His disciples use the 



PROTESTANTISM 


841 

world, but they do it all as pilgrims and strangers’, just as Christ also has 
done. . . . Hence it is not the duty of Christ, or of the Gospel, to alter the 
ordinances of the secular life, and to set up new ones. All that part of life is 
under the control of its own laws, and of reason, and for that we do not need 
the Holy Spirit. . . . ‘Therefore*, says Luther, ‘we must make a very clear 
distinction between the two spheres, between that in which sin is punished 
and that in which it is forgiven, between that in which rights are demanded 
and that in which rights are renounced. In the Kingdom of God, which He 
rules by the Gospel, there is no demanding of rights, and there is no question 
of law, e^ferything is forgiveness and magnanimity and generosity, and there 
is no wrath, and no punishment, but purely brotherly service and good deeds. 
‘The creatures’, says Luther, ‘are all in existence before the Gospel comes, 
that is, all secular matters and ordinances which have been constituted by men 
according to reason, and by the Divinely implanted natural wisdom* (i.e. 
through the Lex Naturae ). . . . ‘Therefore also the servants of Christ ought not 
to have anything to do with these worldly matters, but simply to preach the 
grace of God. So far as those matters are concerned, jurists may advise and 
help and show people how to act.* . . . ‘Thus everything will go on just as it is 
until the great change comes to all things ; for until then the Kingdom of God 
has only an inward form, and Jesus rules simply in the hearts of men. . . . 
For it is not the outward which matters, but the inward; Christ was concerned 
simply with the inward. This alone is the meaning of the words of Christ — 
especially in the Sermon on the Mount — in which He gives His rules for a 
Christian life, that we ought not to swear, etc. He does not dream of laying 
down rules for the outer life ; He is thinking only of inward and personal 
behaviour. His words do not apply to the external calling, and to the official 
conduct which that implies, but to the individual, and to his spirit, and the 
inward personal attitude of mind and heart. For otherwise, if we are to under- 
stand His Word as applying to external matters, Christ would overturn the 
whole order of the world. For it would give rise to an insoluble contradiction 
between the external behaviour in one’s calling and office upon earth* (in 
this, indeed, he demands obedience to both systems of ethics, the ‘personal* 
and the ‘official’, but, at the same time, he recognizes that inwardly they are 
essentially inconsistent with each other). . . ‘For since Jesus only requires an 
inward attitude, and only asks for an external renunciation when faith and 
personal witness require it, He indirectly confirms all these external things, 
possessions and the rest, and also makes it plain that all renunciation which 
is not demanded by that duty is a dereliction of duty*. (Certainly a very 
indirect and arbitrary compromise with the teaching of Jesus.). . . The 
decisive point, which Luther always brought out in these questions, was that 
he had learnt to distinguish between the inward personal spirit of the Christian, 
and the outward attitude to the duty of his secular office and calling.” — To 
that we must add this sentence of Luther’s : “For thyself thou remainest within 
the Gospel, and thou abidest by the word of Christ, so that thou art willing to 
receive a blow upon the other cheek, and thou dost allow men to take thy 
cloak, if it only concerns thee and thine own affairs. Thus in this way all goeth 
well together, that thou dost satisfy both the Kingdom of God, and the kingdom 
of this world, outwardly and inwardly, if thou dost suffer at the same time 
evil and wrong, and yet dost punish evil and wrong, and if thou dost resist 
evil, and yet thou dost not resist it. . . .” Or the other saying : “So far as I am 
a Christian, I must not care about money, or gather it, but only trust in God 
with all my heart. But outwardly I may and ought to use temporal goods for 



842 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

my own body, and for other people, so far as my worldly person is concerned.” — 
That is quite manifestly a dualistic morality, based on absolutely contradictory 
principles. The question is: How did Luther solve this evident problem? 
Luthardt's explanation is that Luther made a distinction between the order of 
Creation and the order of Redemption, between man as a human being and 
man as a Christian ; from this point of view Redemption is the completion of 
the Creation, and the Christian is the true human being. This, however, is a 
theory which would only be possible to the modern reconciliation theology 
(i.e. the Vermittelungstheologie of the middle of the nineteenth century). For 
Luther the solution lay in the sphere of thought governed by the Patristic and 
mediaeval ideas of Natural Law ; cf. Ehrhardt: La Notion du droit natural , who, 
however, has only an imperfect knowledge of the origin and significance of 
this point of view. While' Ehrhardt first of all rightly confirms and illustrates the 
harsh contradiction between the secular ethic of law and the evangelical ethic 
of love and suffering ( p . 290 ), pointing out that at the beginning Luther even 
went the length of rejecting the Decalogue as a document of merely legal 
morality, he also shows that Luther still retained the legal morality for the 
unconverted who need a discipline, a frenum , and a remedium peccati , and also 
for the real Christians who can only be protected by a system of law against 
the abuse and exploitation of their radical spirit of love and readiness to 
suffer, and, finally, because de lege naturae is necessary in order to secure peaceful 
relationships in the State, the family, and in economic life (pp. 293 ff .) ; for the 
latter see the passage in Luther’s great Commentary on the Galatians : “saepe a 
me audistis, quod ordinationes politicae et oeconomicae sint divinae, quia 
Deus ipse ordinavit et apportavit eas, ut solem lunam et alias creaturas”. 
“This way of thinking leads Luther to affirm that there exists a natural divine 
social order independent of the special revelation of God as such, which is in 
the Bible, an eternal order, and in its principles, at least, unchangeable” (p. 293). 
This is the well-known idea of the Lex Naturae , which is written in the hearts 
of men, and which has now been adjusted to the state of fallen humanity as 
a frenum and a remedium peccati , but which is also a necessary reasonable order of 
natural social things in harmony with the Natural Law. For the relative Natural 
Law, see the passage from the Commentary on Genesis quoted by Lommatzsch , 
p. 286: “Politia ante peccatum nulla fuit, neque enim ea opus fuit; est enim 
politia remedium necessarium naturae corruptae. Oportet enim cupiaitatem 
restringi vinculis legum et poenis, ne libere vagetur. Ideo politiam recte 
dixeris regnum peccati. . . . Hoc enim unum et praecipuum agit politia, ut 
peccatum arceat. ... Si enim homines non essent per peccatum mali facti, 
politia nihil fuisset opus.” Thus he accepts also the relevant passages con- 
cerning the Natural Law both in Roman law and in the Canon Law, which 
otherwise he so sternly condemns. For him, however, the ultimate reason for 
the possibility of combining the natural legal ethic with the Christian love- 
ethic is finally the identification of the Decalogue with the Law of Nature 
on the one hand, and with the moral Law of Christ on the other; further, in 
contrast to his original rejection of the Decalogue he interprets it (in sharp 
distinction from the ceremonial and political law of Moses) as the total content 
of the moral demands of the Primitive State, of the Natural Law, and of the 
Christian Law, and makes great use of the Bible, as well as of illustrations from 
antiquity, in order to prove the source of the Law of Nature. In so doing, all 
the old Catholic ideas have again been completely accepted, as is shown by 
Lommatzsch , pp. 60-90 , more clearly than by Ehrhardt , p. 303. Thus Luther says 
in his work, Against the Heavenly Prophets : “Moses’ law and the Natural Law 



PROTESTANTISM 


643 

are one thing” (“ein Ding”). Cf. also Lommatzsch , p. 63, and the larger Cate- 
chism: “The Ten Commandments are likewise written in the hearts of all 
men, they are symbolical books” ( Muller , p. 460). The Decalogue and the 
Christian law itself contain this dualistic ethic, which, therefore, represents 
the contradiction between legalism and the commandment of love which is 
the result of the adaptation of the Law of Nature to the conditions of the 
fallen State ; thus this is the idea of the relative Natural Law, with which we 
are familiar. The difference between this conception and the Catholic develop- 
ment of the idea consists in this : that the dualistic ethic is not represented as 
a gradual process, or as an ascent from the ethic of the Natural Law to the 
peculiar achievements of the Christian ethic, in which the latter, in its entire 
radicalism, is only binding on a special class of people, but that every individual, 
equally, is laid under the obligation to obey both laws. We shall meet these 
inconsistencies at every turn in the exposition of the social doctrines of 
Lutheranism. Ehrhardt remarks somewhat naively : “But is not this distinction 
between the exterior and the interior man abstract and artificial? and what is 
the relation between justice according to Natural Law (a justice possible even 
to non-Christians) and the justice of God?” (/?. 318). Lommatzsch , p. 606: 
recognizes the inconsistency, and the problem which it contains, more deeply 
and theoretically. In general, however, these writers do not know what to 
make of these statements; the reason for this is that either they have no 
knowledge, or only a very imperfect knowledge of the whole ancient Patristic 
scholastic set of ideas which deal with the Law of Nature, and its organic 
function which makes it possible for the ecclesiastical ethic to accept the world. 
They explain them sometimes as a reaction towards Catholicism, contrary to 
Luther’s own principles, sometimes as personal peculiarities and uncertainties 
of Luther ; a man like Ehrhardt can even deny that Luther identified the Law 
of Nature with the Decalogue (p. 3ig ), and in all these statements he only sees 
an unconscious attempt on Luther’s part to adjust the historical bias in favour 
of Natural Law, newly awakened by Humanism, to the Gospel ! And Lom- 
matzsch can say : “Scarcely ever, however, does Luther display more theoretical 
obscurity than in these definitions, this uncertainty affects nothing less than 
his view of the relation of the supernatural to the natural, or of the revelation 
of GckJ in the wider sense, to such a revelation in the narrower sense” (p. 7/). 
G. Miiller: Luthers Stellung zum Recht , thinks (on p. 26) that the whole matter 
sounds very much like the ideas of St. Augustine, but he thinks that inwardly 
Luther had given them up ! 

284 (p. 503.) The clear recognition that the radical ethic would only influence 
small groups of men, and that therefore the Christian ethic for a mass com- 
munity needed the complement of the secular ethic, comes out in the Schrift von 
weltlicher Obrigkeit , B.A., IV, /, p, 236 : A strict and really Christian fellowship 
would not be possible. “Thou must first fill the world with earnest Christians 
before thou canst govern them in a Christian and evangelical way. This, 
however, thou wilt never be able to do, for the world and the masses are, and 
remain, unchristian, even if all were baptized and called Christians. But as 
the saying is, Christians dwell far from one another. Therefore it is not possible 
that a Christian government (in the sense of the Sermon on the Mount) could 
be set up in common over all the world, or over one country or a great number 
of people. For the evil are always more numerous than the good ; therefore to 
presume to try to rule a whole land or the world with the Gospel is like a 
herdsman who would put together in one stable wolves, lions, eagles, and sheep, 
and would allow them to mingle freely together. . . . Here, indeed, the sheep 



844 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OE THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

would keep the peace and peaceably go to pasture and allow themselves to be 
ruled, but they would not live long, nor would one animal have more chance 
than another. Therefore we must deliberately separate the two kinds of rule 
and allow both to remain, the one which makes men good and the other 
which creates outward peace and prevents evil works; within this world 
neither is sufficient without the other.” All this only makes sense on the 
assumption of the necessity for a comprehensive popular Church. — From 
another point of view Luther says the same thing in his famous introduction 
to the Psalter, in which he points out that the Psalter expresses all the heights 
and depths of religious and moral conditions, and is, therefore, better for the 
Christian community than the mere narratives of the heroic acts of the saints. 
“Finally, in the Psalter (through this presentation of various stages), there is 
certainty and a well preserved guidance, that in it, without danger, we can 
follow the example of all the saints (that is, of the religious souls who express 
their feelings in the Psalms). For other examples and legends from the ‘dumb* 
saints (that is, solely the account of their deeds without an expression of the 
fluctuations of their inward life) produce many works which one cannot 
imitate : indeed, they bring before us works which are dangerous to copy, and 
which often cause sects and tumults and which lead and even tear men away 
from the Communion of Saints (that is, from the Church). But the Psalter 
keeps thee in the communion of saints and preserves thee from tumults ; for it 
teaches thee in joy and fear, in hope and sorrow, to be and to speak as all 
the saints (that is, average religious men) have thought and have spoken” 
(IV,i,p.8). 

225 (p- 5°4-) The Decalogue, which in the Early Church and in the early 
Middle Ages was scarcely used at all in the teaching of the Church, was 
used a great deal in the later Middle Ages in connection with the confession 
(Beichtspiegel ) . ( Kawerau , in the volume which has already been indicated, 
p. 43.) It was only regarded as a central Christian doctrine, by which the law 
and its opposite, grace, and also the doctrine of Substitution and the Christian 
ethic, are tested, in Protestantism, and indeed Calvinism, owing to its stricter 
ethical parish organization, used it still more than Lutheranism ; the foundation, 
however, in both is the same. For the absolute position which it had here 
attained, see Lommatzsch , pp. 60-90. The more detailed development of the 
doctrine, with its underlying theory of the Two Tables (I cannot tell how far 
this idea was peculiar to Luther ; in any case, in its detailed treatment and its 
opinions it is a mirror of the ideas of the Reformation), and with its identifica- 
tion of Natural Law, Christian law, and Decalogue (also it is thus the only 
connection which remains in this quite anti-philosophical theology between 
Reason and Revelation, Nature and Grace) is illustrated by Eger , pp. 99-118 , 
and Hupfeld , pp. 75-104 , and Troeltsch: Vemunft und Offenbarung bei Joh. Gerh. 
und Melancthon , 1891 , pp. 1 37-173; while I was writing this work I was not then 
sufficiently acquainted with the significance of the whole group of ideas dealing 
with the Decalogue and the Natural Law in the whole body of traditional 
theology, nor did I realize its connection with Luther, and I attributed this 
doctrine too much to the mind of Melancthon. In this connection the great 
new element which Luther introduced was the distinction between the justitia 
spirituals and the justitia civilis, between the motus spirituals and general natural 
ethical obligations ; the latter are good in a Christian sense when, as the First 
Table requires, they are exercised “in faith”. For this “exercising in faith” of 
the works which in themselves are required by the Natural Law, see the 
detailed presentation of the subject in Thieme, pp. 19-102. This sentence 



PROTESTANTISM 


845 

throws a light on the whole : “In this work (that is, in faith in Christ) all works 
must be exercised, and from its goodness they receive an influence which is 
like a Divine gift” (p. 76). The difficulties, however, created by this gathering 
up in the Decalogue have not by any means disappeared. In the Primitive 
State the Decalogue and the Natural Law, “the Law of Nature and of Love”, 
are certainly quite the same. At the Fall, however, through the secular order 
of law, the Natural Law was adapted to the fallen State, and now the question 
arises: how far can both of these once more be united in the state of sin? 
Eger ( pp . 92 ff.) also formulates the problem thus, and in a very pertinent 
manner.-f-At this point there are the most important developments of Luther’s 
ethic. The two poles of this development are shown by the works Von Weltlicher 
Obrigkeit, wieweit man ihr Gehorsam schuldig sei 1323, and the Auslegung der 
Bergpredigt, 1532. In the former work Luther says expressly the Catholics had 
thus combined the Sermon on the Mount and the obligations of practical life 
by relegating them to different classes of people, and by making the distinction 
between consilia and praecepta , whereas he regards the claim of the Sermon on 
the Mount and of Paul for the absolute ethic of love, which renounces law 
and force, as binding on all Christians without exception. The same Christians, 
however, are alsd taught to admit the claim of practical life, the recognition 
of law and authority ; in the form, however, which it has displayed since the 
Fall, that is, in the legal order, which has been instituted as a frenum and 
remedium peccati ; this legal order, namely, issues from reason ; it has also been 
explicitly appointed by God (in the Old Testament), and, in the New Testa- 
ment, it has also been expressly confirmed by Christ through His own obedience 
to it, His patience, and His endurance. The Christian now belongs to both 
these separate and contradictory orders of life ; since the great majority are not 
true Christians in the sense of the Sermon on the Mount, and need the relative 
Natural Law, that is, the use of law and force for the good and order of their 
earthly life, and since also Christians need this order as a protection against the 
misuse of their willingness to suffer, he submits to this law out of love to the 
nlass of the unconverted, and out of obedience to God’s law. Both these orders 
are to be kept strictly separate; the civil authority in particular (which has 
been instituted solely for the repression of sin, and, therefore, is restricted to the 
external and secular sphere) may not interfere with the affairs of the spiritual 
and Christian sphere ; least of all may the governments which have remained 
Papist and unbelieving do this, but otherwise their right to exist is not to be 
opposed. On the contrary, however, the spiritual ethic of love may not interfere 
with the State order of law, nor attempt to make its radical Christian piety of 
love into a law and a programme of social reform for the masses. For the latter 
need the law ; the principles of the Sermon on the Mount applied to the non- 
Christian masses of the population would simply lead to all kinds of abomina- 
tions. Christians, indeed, have a double position, and, like Paul, they must 
endure the non-Christian ordering of the world and let it continue to exist. 
It is clear that this treatise in which, in some strange way, people have tried 
to find the principles of freedom of conscience and of the modern State, still 
holds a very crudely dualistic standpoint ; the Sermon on the Mount “certainly 
teaches that Christians should use no worldly sword or law amongst them- 
selves ; but it does not forbid that we should serve and be subject to those who 
wield the temporal sword and administer the law ; but much rather because 
thou dost not need such things, nor ought thou to have them, nor ought thou 
to serve those who have not gone so far as thou, and who still need the same” 
(B. A., IV, r, p . 23 9). This is the relative Natural Law which each Christian 



846 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

has to accept for the sake of the existing masses of non-Christians, even when, 
as an individual, he admits the claim of the principles of the Sermon on the 
Mount ; indeed, no one ought to try to get rid of this obligation and constitute 
special groups of those who are perfect. The right meaning of the Sermon on 
the Mount is “that a Christian shall be so set himself to suffer evil and injustice 
without desiring to avenge himself, nor to protect himself by law, that he most 
certainly will not need worldly power and law for himself. But for others he 
may and should (as a judge, executioner, or soldier) seek revenge, law, protec- 
tion, aid, and in that capacity do whatever he can. Thus authority will also 
help and protect him, whether of itself, or through the acts of others, but 
without any complaint or search of his own. When this does not take place 
he must let himself be accused and despised, and ‘resist not evil*, as Christ 
has taught us. And be thou certain that this Word of Christ is not a counsel 
for the perfect, as the Sophists do falsely say, but that it is a strict command- 
ment binding on all Christians alike. . . . And do not go with the multitude, 
and the common customs, for there are few Christians upon earth. . . . And 
God’s Word also is something other than a common custom” ( p . 245). Here, 
again, the approximation to the sect-type is very evident ; the difference, also, 
is plain, namely, the recognition of the relative Lex Naturae add of natural and 
existing conditions for the sake of the unity of the national Church ( Volkskirche ) . 
This dualism, however, disappears almost entirely in the exposition of the 
Sermon on the Mount. Here the presupposition of action is the official position, 
and class, as it has been appointed by God, and a means of brotherly love as 
well as a Divine command which men ought to obey. The legal order is 
regarded as a system of classes, which, owing to the fact that they have been 
appointed by God, are holy. They are now simply “Divine callings” ( p . 292). 
The exercise of one’s calling, and the estimate of “the calling”, and of the 
social system, as a system which has been brought about by, and maintained 
by Providence for the good of Christendom : this idea now becomes the main 
content of the Lutheran ethic. The love which exercises that which in itself 
is not necessary for a Christian, namely, submission to the legal order for the 
good of one’s neighbour, leads to that idea of obedience, and of faith in 
Providence, which exalts the State, the social order, and the law as Divine 
ordinances, in which it is a simple duty of obedience to remain, and tp serve 
one’s neighbour. Eger has brought this out very well in his informative work, 
and at the same time he rightly points out that in spite of this the world-order 
is not yet considered to possess an ethical value of its own. Men serve God 
in vocationey not per vocationem. In other directions, however, the whole view is 
altered. Since the State no longer feels that it has no right to attempt to 
influence matters of religion because it belongs to a lower order, but that now, 
as a Christian government, it is under the obligation to serve the Church and 
the Truth, so also Christians are no longer to maintain an attitude of merely 
passive endurance towards the law. This is what he now says about the legal 
system: “What does the righteousness of this world mean except that every 
man should do in his class what he ought? What does that same law of one’s 
class mean? What does it mean to have rights as men and women, as children, 
and as domestic servants? or what does it mean to have civil rights? Surely all 
this means that they are to look after and rule other people, and thus exercise 
their office with care and faithfulness, and that also truly and willingly they are 
to render the same service and obedience to others” (/>. 500). “All this has God 
commanded, so it cannot be unclean, indeed it is even the purity with which 
God is sought. Thus, if a judge exercise his office and condemn an evil-doer 



PROTESTANTISM 


847 

to death, in so doing this is not his office and action, but the office and act 
of God. Therefore it is a good, pure, and holy work (provided, of course, that 
he is a Christian), which he could not do if he had not already a pure heart” 
(/>. 306). In explicit contrast to the renunciation of one’s own rights which 
was required in the passage quoted above, people are now exhorted first of 
all to try to live in peace and to get on with people : “If, however, that cannot 
be and thou canst not endure it, thou hast the law and the government of the 
land whither thou mayest go to seek it in an orderly manner” (p. 316). These 
changes are just as decided as those which were described previously in relation 
to the connection between Church and State, freedom and compulsion, and 
both these alterations are related to each other. For the earlier demand for 
freedom and separation from the State was based upon a low estimate of the 
State and of the legal system. In its later form, however, Luther’s ethic remained 
permanent, and the explanation of the Decalogue in the two catechisms has 
given it its permanent classic form down to the present day. 

220 (p* 5°4*) Cf. Eger: Anschauungen Luthers von Beruj \ p. 124: “It does not 
seem superfluous to point out how strongly the study of the Old Testament 
has affected the Lutheran view and caused this constantly increasing openness 
towards the worid. The passages which have been just quoted about the 
value of earthly gifts and possessions have been almost entirely drawn from 
expositions of various writings of the Old Testament.” “In the Old Testament 
there is indeed no trace of detachment from the world, of indiff erence to earthly 
things and earthly conditions ; it is, therefore, under all circumstances a more 
sure method of'gaining a wholesome understanding of that which the earth 
can offer than the New Testament which is exposed to so much misinterpreta- 
tion ( !) The sphere within which the Christian lives and works in trust in 
God is now in Luther’s view God’s world.” Thus in reality Luther’s economic 
ethic and his ethic of the family is drawn very largely from the Jewish Wisdom 
literature. Only this can scarcely be an unconscious effect of the Old Testament, 
but on the contrary an attempt to find in the Old Testament a justification for 
things which the New Testament would not tolerate. We shall see how Calvinism 
had to go much farther in this direction in order to maintain its Scriptural 
character. 

227 (fi* 5°B.) This depreciation of the values of the State and of Society, 
making them mere forms and presuppositions for the loving exercise of faith 
(since the love of one’s neighbour is best exercised through using the institu- 
tions which serve the welfare of Society), still characterizes the ethic of modern 
Lutheranism. At the same time science is granted a certain standard of value 
as a means which is essential for the exercise of one’s calling and for the 
“dominion over Nature” which is absolutely necessary to Society, and art as 
a “recreation” in order to preserve freshness in the work in one’s calling. 
Cf. Gottschick: Ethik , p. 127: “The secular moral associations in their profes- 
sional organization are the requisite means for maintaining the natural life of 
humanity which is the indispensable presupposition for the transformation of 
humanity into the Kingdom of God. Luther’s objective theory of the Lex 
Divina Naturalis as the basis of Society is thus replaced by the witness of history, 
which shows that according to the Will of God the different classes of secular 
callings are intended to serve the purpose of the Kingdom of God. If this is 
true of the civil calling, in which one gains a livelihood, it is all the more 
true of the Christian calling, if to that are added all the moral and other tasks 
which result from the regular relations of the individual in the family, in 
Society, in the State, and in the Church.” Herrmann: Ethik 8 , 1304, p. 138: 



848 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

“We only then show ourselves as Christians in the world when it is natural 
to us to see the working of God in the inexhaustible formative power of Nature 
(that is, the Lex Naturae of Luther, without his application to definite and 
permanent institutions) : hence we should value a s the basis of our order of 
life and as forms of our activity which have been given to us by God, the 
naturally established human associations which we find in the world already.” 
Just as Luther regarded the class guild, absolutist and agrarian form of life 
as a condition which was permanently demanded by Nature, and one 
which could be approximated to Christianity on the side of the external life, 
so here an unlimitedly mobile shaping of these things, including the modern 
militaristic, capitalistic, and scientific and aesthetic civilization, is regarded as 
the “form” of the natural life which is to be inspired by faith. Likewise, in 
v. d. Goltz: Grundlagen der christlichen Sozialethik , who in his “sociological” 
section develops the Lutheran doctrine of Natural Law by a modern doctrine 
of the “natural basic forms in the family, the State, and Society”, and then 
places these “forms” under the influence of the Christian spirit; p. 282: “In 
Christianity religion takes over the guidance of human social life. . . . The 
dominion of the Spirit over nature is here led to a gradual completion, and all 
individual and social disharmonies are smoothed out, ydiile the peculiar 
energies of the various social groups are also brought into harmony.” Likewise 
also Luthardt: Kompendium der Ethik , i8g6 : “Since the spirit is only the truth of 
man and Christianity, the truth of the earthly life, so the truth of the morality 
of the natural life consists in this, that this morality shall be achieved with the 
sense and spirit and moral power which Christianity provides. . . . Gratia non 
tollit, sed sanat naturam.” Everywhere any possibility of an inner opposition 
between the natural forms of the ethic of civilization and the radical spirit 
of love (whose eternal aims ought to fill them) has been entirely forgotten, 
and Luther’s conflicts around this problem are simply regarded as “Catholic 
relics”. The saying of Luthardt reminds us directly of the Catholic principle : 
“Gratia praesupponit ac perficit naturam”, and shows at the same time the 
striking difference. In Catholicism Nature and Grace are different in degree, 
in Protestantism they finally come together as form and content. 

220 (p. 509.) Cf. Eger , pp. 124 ff. : “That which has been said above about the 
alteration in the conception of faith and of obedience to the revealed word of 
God, and of the way in which obedience is ranged against the promises, and 
those again are set over against the commandments of God, finds its clearest 
expression in the passage out of the Enarr. in Genesin : ‘Hacc sunt verae laudes 
obedientiae, quae tantum estvel promissionum vel praeceptorumdivinorum. , ” 
A similar tendency emerges in the fact that the theory of ‘faith and love” 
which was laid down in the Liberty of a Christian Man as the mark of the Christian 
life, is replaced by the principle of “faith and obedience towards God”. 
“After we have placed our righteousness solely upon the promised Seed, 
promising also that we will be obedient to God, and that in this temporal life 
we will do and observe what He has commanded. . . . Therefore both must 
be together, faith and obedience to God.” This makes the works of the Christian 
holy in contrast with those of the pagan because they are carried out in the 
spirit of faith in Christ and in obedience to God. The Kirchenpostil e has similar 
ideas: “God wills that after our sins have been forgiven we should live in 
obedience to His commands.” “That which leads us to obedience is, more and 
more, not the revealed grace of God in Christ which wins our hearts, but the 
formal authority of the Divine word” (p, 125). The parallelism of the knowledge 
of faith and of the moral law is characteristic, both have taken the same course 



PROTESTANTISM 


% 

of development, for the same reason, namely, for the sake of the conception of 
the Church. Curiously enough, theologians have complained a good deal of 
the first development, while they have praised the second, since it provides 
them with that humanitarian theory of Christianity which accepts the world, 
which they find so necessary at the present day. Therefore, in general, the 
limitations of the modern verdict on Luther, which praises his earlier indi- 
vidualism, which was like that of the sect-type, and complains of his prejudice 
in favour of a Catholic negation of the world, while it regards the dogmatism 
of Luther as an older man as a reaction towards Catholicism, and praises his 
attitude of acceptance of the world as modern progress. In reality, both the 
latter arc inseparable from the Church-type, as the two former were insepar- 
able from all tendencies towards the sect- type. This shows how fruitful the 
differentiation between the sect- type and the Church- type which was made in 
//, g is for our subject as a whole. This will also be very evident in dealing 
with Calvinism and the Baptist movement. 

230 (p. 510.) On this point cf. my treatment of the subject in the Kultur der 
Gegenwart. Characteristic passages in Herrmann: Verkehr, p. 208 : “This does not 
mean leaving and fleeing from the world as they (the Papists) imagine; for 
thou mayest be ia whatever kind of life or position that thou wilt — for thou 
must be something because thou art living upon earth — God has not told thee 
to depart from them, but to live among them ; for each man has been created 
and born for the sake of other men. Wherever now thou art I say, and in 
whatever position thou dost find thyself there thou must flee from the world.” 
“Thus I am separated from the world and yet am in the world.” Thus also 
Luthardt says rightly: “Therefore in the sphere of outward activity we are 
not to mark off a special sphere of ascetic activity, but we are to bring the 
ascetic factor into all our activity” ( Ethik Luthers , p. 63). Braun: Concupiszenz • 
“Thus there lies truth in the paradox : by the very fact that Luther drove the 
monastic ideal to its farthest limit he destroyed it in its very root” (p. 57). 
That is what Max Weber and I mean when we speak of an “asceticism within 
this world” of Protestantism, in opposition to the Catholic asceticism, 
which is above — or perhaps better — alongside of, this world. 

23 °a 513.) This statement of the midway position of Lutheranism between 

a systeiy of moderate asceticism and ecclesiastical guidance of Society on the 
one hand, and a sectarian enthusiastic radicalism on the other hand, is specially 
adduced for the Christian social problem of the present day. According to the 
genuine Christian social idea it would be good to retain the free non-legal 
spirit of the ethic of love, and to leave social reform itself solely to political and 
social experts who should draw the spiritual energies they need for their task 
out of this spirit. Certainly R. Sohm expresses himself to me in a letter: “the 
Gospel is understood as containing a social programme. Through that the 
Gospel became a new law which was established now in a relative and now 
in a radical form. But, as I believe, the development consisted in the fact that 
this standpoint was superseded, and I consider that the first great step towards 
progress in this direction was taken in Luther’s Reformation. The second 
step, which led to the present day, came through the Enlightenment. . . . The 
ethical consequence of brotherly love which is given through the love of God 
cannot be gathered up in some law or programme which will hold good for 
all time, and they are, therefore, no essential part of the Gospel, which for all 
time is a message of salvation which is ever valid, whose content is solely 
religious and which brings forth social energies but no social programme.” 
In any case, however, that is not the meaning of Lutheran thought in its 

VOL. H. CG 



850 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

application to social things, for according to Luther’s idea the latter are 
not free and mobile, but through the Law of Nature they are bound up with 
an entirely anti-capitalist tendency; the modern social development was 
rejected by Luther in the name of Nature as well as in the name of the Gospel 
as the next section will show. On the other hand, however, even the Gospel 
for Luther is not the personal spirit of love which offers power to Christianize 
social institutions which in themselves have become necessary in the course of 
history, but an individual ethic of unconditional love and readiness to suffer 
which does not penetrate and shape the official morality of law and property, 
but tolerates and suffers it as an opposition introduced by sin which cannot 
be overcome. Calvinism would come better under this heading, which in 
point of fact penetrates existing Society with the Christian spirit and knows no 
invincible opposition between official and individual morality (public and 
private morality). But all such spirit must in application become a programme 
and a law, and thus it became that also in Calvinism, whereby its law was 
indeed not unchangeable, but it adapted itself with great elasticity to the 
various conditions of life among the Calvinistic nations ; this will become plain 
in the third section. The classic theory formulated by Sohm is rather a very 
modern theory, as he himself seems to suggest. Its assumption is the insight 
into the impossibility of stabilizing social institutions and the judgment of 
these things according to their immanent purely secular necessity, and with 
that precisely the withdrawal of religion to that which is purely spiritual and 
religious. It contains at the same time the equally modern demand that the 
Christian spirit should penetrate the social world, that is, the demand for a 
uniform ethic which, in contrast with Luther’s dualism, should accept the ever- 
changing social world, and still at the same time penetrate and mould it with 
its own spirit. The question is, however, whether and how this is possible at 
all in face of modern social life, and whether it does not make it necessary to 
have a most inward transformation of the Christian ethic in order to draw in 
the secular life values even when a penetration of spirit of the existing neces- 
sities merely is demanded, and even when these are to be seriously conformed 
to the ideal. Here, however, we have reached the problems of the modern 
Christian ethic, which rather resemble those of Calvinism than those of 
Lutheranism; but it is no longer possible to solve them in the traditional 
Scriptural manner (i.c. O.T.) of Calvinism. Not from the Bible, but from 
the Christian spirit, that is, from the progressive Christian principle, these 
questions must be answered to-day, if it is really possible to answer them at all. 
This, however, is rather different from the old Lutheran position. This is a 
modern way of thinking along evolutionary historical lines, as indeed indirectly 
the words of Sohm seem to suggest. The new position is a result of a process of 
progress which arose out of the history of the Middle Ages, passed through 
Protestantism, and which leads from Protestantism to a modern form of 
Christianity which arose out of the latter, but is not identical with it. This 
fundamental content which can everywhere be recognized reveals itself also 
in the problem of the social doctrines of Christianity ; cf. my work on Pro- 
testantism in Kultur der Gegenwart , /, IV > /, pp. 634-649. 

881 (P- 5*6.) On this point see Moller-Kawerau : Lehrbuch der Kirchengeschichte , 
IIP , 7907; Riecker: Die Rechtliche Stellung; and, above all, Sohm: Kirchenrecht , L 
The work of Sohm is not only extremely able, but it also has a very unprejudiced 
eye for the historical and actual which has not been dimmed by modern 
ideas of Church-order. Here the Lutheran doctrine is understood in its most 
inward and real sense. The paradox of Sohm’s argument only arises in this, 



PROTESTANTISM 


851 

that it treats the over-idealistic miraculous Lutheran conception of the Church 
which Lutheranism itself has completed by a very realistic secular Church law 
as something which also without this completion can and should exist ; and 
the vulnerable historical point is the identification of that idealistic Lutheran 
conception of the Church with that of the Primitive Church, which had no 
legal tradition at all and which works not with conceptions which are detached 
from law, but with legal conceptions which have not been defined, and, above 
all, which places the ministry under the Enthusiastic conception of the charisma. 
Of that more anon ; also see above, pp. 481 jj . The point at which I believe that 
I must diyerge from Sohm's treatment of the facts will be treated later; cf. 
Note 236. 

232 (p. 518.) On this, above all, see Sohm : the starting-point, the productive, 
miraculous power of the Word and not of the congregation (pp. 511-513) ; the 
pastoral character of jurisdiction based upon a free spirit of love and sub- 
mission (pp. 522 and 523) ; the charismatic character of the ministry which 
depends upon the willing affection and permission of the congregation, only 
otherwise to be appointed according to order (pp. 500-505, 518) ; judgment on 
doctrine a matter for the pastors, but only as professional organs for self- 
interpretation of tlfe Scriptures or as the mouthpiece of Christ (pp. 521 , 432 ff .) ; 
the order of love in the congregation in contrast with the order of law (pp. 434- 
436). For Lutheranism the decisive point is faith in the wonderful spontaneous 
power of the Word of God to form churches, see the passage in Sohm , p. 432 . 
Similar passages, p. 616; it is the main idea also in the later orthodoxy, see 
Schmidt: Die Dogmatik der ev.-luth. Kirche 8 , 1876, p. 432. This supernatural and 
objective spirituality, combined with the idea that the legal State which aims 
at secular well-being is not sufficient for this sphere but may serve it, is the 
source of the characteristic expressions of Luther about the relation between 
the sacred and the secular even in the case of those which sound most modern. 

284 (p. 519.) Cf. Sohm, 622 and 627 : “And if it were necessary that the 
secular government, on occasion, should take up the question of those who 
despise the ban of the Church” (at first purely spiritual, carried out by the 
pastor and the congregation), in the Wittenberg Concord of 1545, which was 
signed by Luther and which dealt with the future form of Church government. 
Sohm rightly describes this as the specifically Lutheran view, as contrasted with 
the view of Melancthon and of most of the others who wanted to give to the 
Church courts the immediate power “to judge according to the Holy Scriptures 
and also according to the usual laws which are in our country . . . arctiora 
mandata with the menace of serious punishments, like fines, imprisonments, etc.” 
and who wished to compel the secular authorities “straight away, without 
delay, to carry into effect the verdict of the ecclesiastical authorities” (p. 628), 

226 (p. 519.) On the whole subject, see the illuminating remarks of Sohm: 
pp. 542-633. Here also the right explanation for this development out of the 
renunciation of the supernatural idealism, from Sohm's personal point of 
view an effect of lack of faith for which he makes Melancthon especially 
responsible, cf. 612 . — As Sohm shows, Luther always protested against this 
development ; but the passages quoted by Sohm reveal rather a protest of a 
theological and Scriptural nature against decisions of a juridical and Canon 
law nature than a conflict between the voluntary order of love and a legal 
order of compulsion; for Luther is ready to hand over sinners in life and 
doctrine to the secular arm for further secular penalties. This means that the 
twofold order is differentiated more in theory than in anything else : actually 
in practice it all amounts to a legal and compulsory attitude even in matters 



852 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

of Christian doctrine and discipline. The latter were found to be necessary and 
the formal decisions of Luther were practically ineffective. It could not be 
helped, p. 6ig : “The desire for a legal order was here stronger than faith in 
the rule of Christ and the power of the Word. Men desired a Church-order 
as an aid for the Word. Very well, it came, but it came in order to appoint the 
territorial prince as the lord also of the Church.’ * — For the way in which it 
came, see K . Muller: Anf tinge tier Konsistorialverfassung , Hist. £., 302 , pp. 1-30 . 

238 (p- 521 .) In this I have expressed my own attitude, as briefly as possible, 
to Sohm's famous thesis. It contains the important sociological viewpoint that 
every kind of Church-order is the law of the Church, and as thaf which is 
appointed to protect great supernatural things it is itself drawn into this 
supernatural order, and in so doing it receives qualities which make it quite 
incommensurable for the precise and actual jurists. Further, within this 
law there is the inconsistency that it binds and hampers the quite individual 
religious life by formal and purely objective standards. Only this is a con- 
tradiction which does not belong to the fact of a law in the Church, but to the 
conception of the Church as an institution which protects by strict rules an 
objective treasure of revelation. The ideal conception of the Church as of an 
institution which can be freely developed and ruled by the Word is a Utopia 
of faith. Historically the question is whether Luther purely and exclusively 
sanctioned this Utopia of faith as Sohm believes, and whether the introduc- 
tion of a Divine Law in reality can only be laid to the account of Melanc- 
thon, the politicians and the consistories, or, in other words, whether 
Luther (who had retained so many mediaeval Catholic elements of the con- 
ception of the Church, especially that of the objective doctrine which can 
alone give salvation and of the united Christian Society) at this point really 
went so far as to exclude all Divine Law from the Church and every kind of 
Divinely based rule for securing pure doctrine and the ordering of morals. 
The answer depends on the interpretation of Luther’s doctrine of the office 
of the ministry. Sohm interprets the Lutheran conception of the ministry 
( p . 473) quite simply from the point of view of the primitive Christian charis- 
matic idea and overestimates Luther’s own expressions about the charismatic 
character of the ministry,/?. 474 : “The heart of the doctrine of Luther . . . that 
the pastor exercises his office ‘only on account of the congregation’, only in the 
name of ‘the Church*. His ministry, from the spiritual point of view, he can 
only have from God through the gift which God has given him, but the exercise 
of the ministry is only possible to him, not legally, but solely because he is 
permitted by the congregation ( !).” Luther, however, alongside of this super- 
natural charismatic conception of the ministry also undoubtedly had the 
supernatural legal conception which represented the ministry of the pure 
Word as the truth of Scripture and formed the official expression of the com- 
munity ordained by God, which is bound to the assumption of an orderly 
calling excluding all disorder and fanaticism. The latter, in the prevailing 
point of view, is rightly regarded as the central point of a spiritual law since 
existence and a proper calling de jure are required for it, and the exercise of the 
Scriptural understanding of the congregation is bound up with these official 
interpreters of the Word; it is only the manner of the calling which is left 
free to human custom. The above presentation of this subject is based upon 
this latter conception. 

187 (P* 5 22 -) For these externa disciplina , which the Government is bound to 
exercise as custos utriusque tabulae from the point of view of the State, and as 
membrum praecipuum ecclesiae from the point of view of the Church, see the words 



PROTESTANTISM 


853 

of Melancthon quoted by Sohm : “Magistratus est custos primae et secundae 
tabulae legis, quod ad externam disciplinam attinet, hoc est prohibere externa 
scelera et punire sontes debet et proponere bona exempla. . . . Etsi enim 
magistratus non mutat corda nec habet ministerium spiritus, tamen habet 
suum officium externae disciplinae conservandae etiam in iis, quae ad primam 
tabulam pertinent (that is, in questions of worship and orthodoxy in doc- 
trine). . . . Cum quaeras, quae sint officia magistratuum, tibi pingito magis- 
tratum cui de collo pendeant tabulae duae legis Moysi. Horum custos esse 
debet politicus gubernator, quoad externam disciplinam attinet. Nam haec 
sunt summae leges, ex quibus ceterae honestae leges omnes tamquam ex 
fontibus derivantur.” For the way in which these externa disciplina for the 
maintenance of a Christian external order are to be used by the secular 
officials, see the Visitations Instruction of 1527, Sohm,p. 6oy\ “Officials, jurymen, 
town councillors, noble judges, also ought to punish matters which are not 
to be borne among Christians . . . like the following: frivolous swearing 
and using the Name of God in vain, item gluttony, drunkenness, gaming, 
idleness, item treating matters of faith flippantly or contemptuously in wine- 
or beer- or drink-houses, or quarrelling about them (thus a system of denuncia- 
tion, which, according to Wappler's reports of law proceedings actually became 
very dangerous to many Anabaptists), adultery and fornication, disobedience 
of children to their parents, and especially when these attack their parents 
with words, or with their hands, item if the children get engaged without 
their parents’ will or knowledge.” Absence from Church, disturbances in 
Church, and, of course, false doctrine, are all punishable offences. The punish- 
ments which are preferable are imprisonment rather than fines, which are 
considered “self-interested”. Later on, the consistories exercise the same 
discipline in their own name (p. 615) with fines, imprisonments, and corporal 
punishment, also with the great ban which is the result of the civil boycott, 
“ suspensio ab officio exclusion from the council, denial of the right to exercise 
his trade or his livelihood”. People even thought of building a special con- 
sistorial prison. These things only show how everything was dominated by the 
idea of the uniform Christian Society. Luther also desires all these things, only 
not at the disposal of the spiritual authority, but of the secular authority as 
such, which he justifies by the fiction that all these crimes also have a civil 
aspect which the State ought to punish as a contravention of its own order ! 
Calvinism, on the contrary, places all these matters under the control of the 
ecclesiastical court of discipline itself, which has the power to inflict very 
effective “purely spiritual” punishments, and thus, through the Church, by 
spiritual means, it establishes a social order which Lutheranism handed over 
to the civil government, and which, in the mixed consistories, came under the 
standpoint of the interests of the State entirely, and for that reason it did not 
develop a religious and ethical influence at all. 

288 (P* 522.) Gerhard in Schmidt: Dogmatik , p. 452: “Status sive ordines in 
ecclesia a Deo instituti numerantur tres, videlicet ecclesiasticus, politicus et 
oeconomicus, quos etiam hierarchias appellare consueverunt. Oeconomicus 
ordo inservit generis humani multiplicationi, politicus ejusdem defensioni, 
ecclesiasticus ad salutem aeternam promotioni. Oec. ordo oppositus est a Deo 
vagis libidinibus, polit. tyrannidi et latronciniis ; eccles. haeresibus ac doctrinae 
corruptelis.” These divisions are very ancient, see XXVIII , p . 624 ; also Bohmer: 
Luther, p. 220; in a Bishop Gerhard of Cambrai, 1036 ( Luthardt : Comp.,p . 26/), 
and then again in Stephen of Prague and Nicholas of Clemanges, K&hler: 
Staatslehre der Vorreformatoren (Jahrbb.f. deutsche Theologie , XX, p. 95). Also in 



854 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Wimpfeling , 1501 , see Roscher: Nationalokonomik , p. 37. In the last resort that 
really is the Platonic classification of classes in his politeia. The theory goes 
right through the whole ethic and dogmatics of Lutheranism, and has again 
been taken up by the ethic of modern confessional Lutheranism, whereby it is 
admitted that they owe to Pietism a broadening beyond the narrow conception 
of callings into the “general Christian humanity, for example, of home and 
foreign missions” ; see Luthardt: Compendium der Ethik, pp. 267-263. 

339 (p. 523.) For this idea of the Corpus Christianum , see specially the excellent 
treatment of the subject by Rieker ; similarly Sohm , p. 340 : “We only gain the 
right standpoint for the complete understanding of the question with which we 
are concerned when we get rid of all our present-day ideas about Church and 
State and transport ourselves into the spirit of the Church politics of the 
sixteenth century, which were still very much determined by the Middle Ages. 
The conceptions of Church and State in the present sense are still unknown, 
the fundamental conception is that of Christendom. In Christendom God has 
appointed ‘two swords*: the spiritual and the secular. It is the duty of both 
to govern Christendom, but with different aims and therefore with a different 
authority, the one with spiritual authority and the other with secular authority. 
The nature of these ‘two swords’, and therefore of their mutual relationship in 
authority, had to be determined. This is what Luther did. His doctrine of the 
division between the two forms of government represents solely the reformed 
doctrine of the Middle Ages of the ‘two swords*. Clearly it does not regard 
the question according to the relation between two organizations, but solely 
the question of the relation between two authorities . . . , which both belong 
to a great organism of Christendom.” Because the whole civilization of Luther- 
anism is based upon this, I have described this in the Kultur der Gegenwart, 
4 , as a certainly very penetrating transformation of mediaeval civilization. 
Bohmer , p. 121 , however, gives it as his opinion that this is “simply an assertion 
and, indeed, an assertion which excludes absolutely a clear insight into the 
nature of Protestantism as well as of Catholicism” ! 

am (P- 5 a 3-) For the ethic of Lutheranism, cf. Troeltsch : Joh . Gerhard und 
Melancthon; Honnicke: Studien zur altprot. Ethik , 1302 (also my review, G. G. A ., 
1902, pp. 577-583); Hupfeld: Ethik Joh. Ger hards, 1908 (also my Review, Th. L., 
/909) ; also the Geschichten der christlichen Ethik , by Gass and Luthardt; Th. £iegler 
remains, here also, on the fringe of the subject. Instructive presentation of the 
modern Lutheran ethic, but quite steeped in the Lutheran spirit, Gottschick: 
Ethik, 1907; Luthardt: Compendium der Ethiky 1896 , rich in quotations from the 
orthodox ethic; Hofmann: Theolog. Ethik, 1878, an excellent even though 
modernized description of the spirit of the Lutheran ethic. Both the latter are 
visibly full of the spirit of the triumph of this ethic in Church and State after 
the interim period of the Enlightenment, and they give some idea of the 
instinctive connection between the modern Conservative party and the spirit 
of the Lutheran ethic. A magnificent analysis of the Lutheran ethic in relation 
to the Calvinistic ethic is given by Schneckenburger , cf. Darstellung des Lutherischen 
und Reformierten Lehrbegriffes, 1855 . — We must always remember in every 
presentation of the Protestant ethic the Lutheran special dogma of the exposition 
of the Sermon on the Mount, according to which this only rules the spirit of 
Christians towards Christians without legally binding them to their concrete 
examples, and, above all, assumes alongside of this exhortation to a spiritual 
outlook at the same time the civil and legal official and vocational ethic as a 
legal order instituted by God. That is a fundamental Scriptural dogma as 
important as the doctrine of justification by faith, and it stands over against 



PROTESTANTISM 


855 

the Catholic dogma that the Sermon on the Mount contains the evangelical 
counsels of a one-sided perfection ethic alongside of the ethic of the world for 
the special class of the monks, as well as against the sect-dogma that the whole 
of Christian Society ought to obey these rules, and therefore as a religious group 
ought to withdraw from the State and from the world. This is a fundamental 
dogma of exegesis of Lutheranism contrasted with Catholics and Baptists. 
Hence also the characteristic historic construction of the Lutherans according 
to which the post-apostolic and primitive Church ethic under pagan influences 
again became uncertain about the right understanding of the Sermon on the 
Mount ( Hofmann, p, 294). In reality, the Protestant dogma of the Sermon on 
the Mount*was not yet present and could not be present. It only became possible 
through the mediaeval development over which the relative opposition must 
not lead us astray. 

240 (p. 524.) For further proofs, see Buddeus: Isagoge historico-theologica ad 
theologiam universam , Lpz ., i72o > //, 4: “De theologia morali simulque de 
theologia mystica itemque jurisprudentia divina et prudentia turn Christiana 
turn pastorali.” Even this title shows the variety of the contents; the retro- 
spective survey of the history of the Lutheran ethic (pp. 692-672) emphasizes it 
expressly and lan^cnts that there is no systematic treatment of the subject, 
although Luther and Melancthon were supposed to have renewed all the 
subject-matter of ethics. To that then comes in addition the “theologia con- 
scientiaria”, or casuistry ( p . 616), about whose connection with the Lutheran 
practice of confession (which had to differentiate between the sins which led 
to loss of grace and those which did not lead to it) Hupfeld makes a very 
instructive contribution to the subject. Also on this side there is an analogy 
with the Catholic ethic: the ecclesiastical ethic can only hold together the 
heterogeneous elements which it contains by means of casuistry and the 
confessional in spite of its Protestant autonomy and emphasis upon inwardness. 
Something similar is revealed by the Calvinistic system of Church discipline. 
The difference lies merely in the absence of the legal binding nature of the 
verdict ; see the statement by Gass , //, /, p. 197, on Balduin: Tractatus toti rei 
publicae utilis sive de casibus conscientiae , 1628. 1 here give the outline of the material 
according to B. (1) The real philosophical ethic in the Aristotelian sense is 
occupied with questions of the virtues, temperaments, etc., all of which is 
absorbed into the Christian central virtue of love ; see Luthardt: Compendium , 
122-169 . (2) The other part of ethics is the doctrine of Natural Law: “Altera 
philosophiae practicae pars seu jurisprudentia naturalis de officiis hominum 
legibusque divinis, quibus ilia diriguntur, praecipit.” For the second section 
the main authority is Cicero, while Aristotle, it is true, “ad vitae civilis usum 
unice accommodatus est”, but “prudentiae potius quam obligationis legumque 
divinorum habuit rationem” ( p . 308). The Church Fathers combine this 
Natural Law with revelation, the Schoolmen mingled Aristotle, the jus civile 
and the jus canonicum in a confused way. Melancthon, Benedict Winkler, and 
others then restored the right relationship. Finally, Fal. Alberti , in his Com- 
pendium juris naturae orthodoxae theologiae conformatum , whom the jurists Dav. 
Menius and Veit Lud. v. Seckendorf followed, deduced the Natural Law 
from the Primitive State, only in so doing they did not lay sufficient emphasis 
upon the special conditions and modifications produced by the Fall. In any 
case, it is “praestantissima philosophiae practicae pars, quae vel maxime vitae 
civilis negotiis inservire debet (p . 344 )”. (3) The third part of ethics is the 
real Politica, the doctrine of the effectuation of civil welfare in all classes and 
callings: “eo magis ilia tractatio est necessaria, quo amplius ejus est usus, 



856 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

siquidem non tantum prudentiae civilis et aulicae, sed et christianae et 
theologicae et ecclesiasticae principia et fundamenta ex ea petenda sunt” 
(P- 3 J 7 )‘ Here also there is a large literature which only in more recent times 
as “politica sive prudentia civilis” has become clearly defined in relation to 
the doctrine of the universal Law of Nature, which in earlier days was to a 
great extent mingled together with it. The primitive form of this “Prudentia 
civilis” is the Mosaic Law, “omnes enim istae leges aequitati naturali sunt 
consentaneae” ( p . 4/p) ; then the Wisdom literature of the Old Testament which 
had “prudentiam non minus quam ad doctrinam moralem seu vitam recte 
instituendam spectant” ( p . 320). The results have been put together by the 
well-known theologian Dannhauer, in a Politica biblica. Further, Aristotle has to 
be considered ; it is, however, felt that he is not quite sufficient to meet the 
requirements of the present day ; after that there follow notes on more recent 
literature on politics and State administration, among whom Bodin and 
Machiavelli, who exaggerates the rights of princes, must not be overlooked. 
To this belongs also political economy whose connection with the Christian 
class state and the Natural Law is shown by Roscher: Geschichte der Nationaloko - 
nomik. Buddeus names above all Seckendorff’s Christian State: “de omnium 
ordinum emendatione secundum indolem disciplinae Chrfetinae praecipit” 
( p . 721). (4) Above these three or four sections of practical theology there then 
rises the real theologia moralis , the doctrine of the motus spirituales y or the theologia 
moralis mystica , whereby this mysticism is only permissible if it is pure, that is, 
if it is based upon faith in the Atonement and faith in the Bible : “Per theologiam 
mysticam, puram scilicet, nihil aliud intelligi quam ipsam theologiam moralem 
stricte sic dictam quemlibet potest docere collatio. Mysticam namque theologiam 
ita nonnulli definire solent, quod sit divina et arcana de Deo rebusque divinis 
sapientia, qua mens hominis regeniti illuminetur, voluntas virtutibus divinis 
instructa ab inquinamentis peccatorum purgetur, ut ilia cum Deo arctissime 
uniatur. Id vero est, quorsum et theologia moralis tendit” ( p . 672). The books 
by Alberti , Dannhauer , and others I have unfortunately been unable to read. 

242 (p.529.) Cf. on this point K. Kohler: Luther und die Juris ten, 1873; E. Branden- 
burg: M. L.s Anschauung vom Staate und der Gesellschaft , igor {Schriften d. Vereins 
f. Ref-Gesch., 70); G. Muller: Luthers Stellung zum Rechte ( Schriften des evang. 
Bundes, 43-44), igo6 ; E. Ehrhardt: La nature du droit naturel chez Luther , F^tschrift 
der Pariser Fakultat fur Montauban; Cardauns: Lehre vom Wider standsrecht im Luther - 
turn und Calvinismus, Bonner Diss., 1903. — Bluntschli: Gesch . d. allgemeinen Staats - 
rechtes und der Politik , 1864 , pp. 46-60 , does not penetrate deeply enough into the 
subject; he makes certain criticisms which to some extent are in touch with 
modern liberal criticism. Bergbohm: Jurisprudenz und Rechtsphilosophie, 1892, 
a radical criticism of all Natural Law from a purely legal Positivistic standpoint 
has neither knowledge nor understanding of the ecclesiastical Natural Law, 
and speaks especially of the Natural Law of the Reformers (p. 139) with complete 
ignorance of the subject. Hinrichs: Geschichte der Rechts und Staatsprinzipien seit der 
Ref I, 1848, gives little about Luther, more about Melanchton and orthodoxy. 

248 (p. 529.) Here is the radical difference from Occam’s Natural Law, 
Ehrhardt , 304. Cf., for example, the “exhortation to peace in reply to the 
Twelve Articles of the peasants” : “So there is the Natural Law which governs 
the whole world, that no one may be his own judge nor revenge himself” 
(B. A., IV, 1, p. 319). “Can ye not think that if your demand were right each 
man would judge the other, and there would be no longer any authority or 
government, order or law in the world, but simply murder and the shedding 
of blood . . . ? Now it is said of the common Divine and Natural Law that 



PROTESTANTISM 


857 

even the heathen, the Turks and the Jews, must keep it, if order and peace in 
the world is to remain” (p. 321). “You are going beyond God, and taking 
away from the government its authority and its rights, and indeed all that 
it has. For of what use is the government if it has lost its authority? .... In 
authority consists all its wealth and all its life” {p. 320). Still more clearly 
in the pamphlet Ob Kriegsleute auch in seligem Stand sein konnen , 1326. So also 
in the modern Lutheran ethic, cf. von Hofmann : “As a member of the State the 
Christian is obliged, by means of that which the legal order offers, to maintain 
his own rights against their abuse by the official ruler. When this is out of the 
question, then only one of two things is morally possible, either to endure 
compulsion or to exchange this State for another” (p. 278, see also p. 273 ). 

248 (P* 53 2 *) Figgis: From Gerson to Grotius , pp. 62-107 , places Luther with 
Machiavelli. Buddeus: Isagoge , 323 , sees in Lutheranism the right mean between 
followers of Machiavelli and the Monarchomachi (opponents of monarchy) : 
“quorum illi imperantibus plus quam decet coneedunt, hi plus quam decet 
adimunt”. He also finds in Bodin relative truths ; the related elements in the 
view of Hobbes on the contrary seem to have been nowhere recognized ; only 
Pufendorf, who in many respects had a Lutheran way of thinking (see Bluntschli , 
p. 130 f; Lezius: mToleranzbegrijf Lockes und Pufendorf s , igoo , pp. 38 and 68), has 
noticed this; see Bluntschli , 121 . — These ideas of Lutheran Natural Law are 
those which lie entirely at the basis of the legal philosophy of F. J. Stahl, and 
in Stahl they experience their first comprehensive and otherwise very able 
philosophical basis; cf. the instructive analysis of Stahl in E. Kaufmann: Studien 
zur Staatslehre des monarchischen Prinzips, Hallenser Diss ., igo6. The connection 
with Luther is carried out right into details : the Government and authority 
a power that has been absolutely given and set over individuals ( p . 79) ; the 
social institutions, the family, property, the State, based in the Divine Will and 
not in immanental necessity, but appointed with the Creation and with Nature 
working themselves out along their own naturally reasonable laws {p. 82) ; 
law is ethical even in its transformation into an external compulsory authority 
which has been effected by the Fall ( p . 83 ) ; the State and Society limited to 
the working out of the purposes of well-being and order within the world for 
which authority and order is necessary, in that, however, it is quite independent 
and no£ influenced by revelation ( p . gf) ; the source of natural Reason is 
equally the source of the Divine power and appointment ( p . 94). All those 
statements are purely Lutheran; it is the Natural Law “of irrationalism”, as 
Kaufmann rightly sets it over against the Natural Law of Rationalism ; only 
Kaufmann in a quite erroneous conception of Luther as a representative of 
modern autonomous individualism has not recognized this connection {p. gg). 
The special factor in time and in history for Stahl is solely the intensification 
of the “irrational Natural Law” exactly towards the legitimist monarchy for 
which Luther felt no necessity. Princes or magistrates were all the same to 
him. — It is from this point of view that we can understand right down to the 
present day the politics of Conservatives who combine a policy of dominion 
with all the consequences of the thought of power with a Christian piety 
which is restricted to the inward life of the spirit and temper, and who maintain 
an ethical connection between the two separate spheres only by means of 
the theory of the patriarchal relationship of authority and respect, which 
should subsist between those who rule and those who are ruled. Cf. the demand 
of Stahl quoted by Kaufmann ( p . g6) : “Thou ought not to break this con- 
nection without reason (with the authority that has come into existence 
historically), thou must have reverence for that which God has either ordained 



858 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

or permitted to take place ; thou shalt not merely obey the Government where 
such exists but thou shalt yield faithfulness and affection to the dynasty 
which is rooted in history.* * Otherwise the existence alongside of each other 
of a policy of force, which includes all kinds of harshness, of a system of power 
which has to be established legally, and of a love ethic which believes in 
Providence, the result of sin, in which then all that is left over is to protect as 
far as possible the positive law and authority and a compromise in which the 
love ethic keeps the abstract doctrinaire spirit in the background. — Also in 
Bismarck the striking phenomenon of his policy of force, and his Christian 
piety which existed alongside of each other, can only be understood if one 
understands the ideas of that Lutheran and Stahl principle of the '‘Natural 
Law of irrationalism” alongside of a Christian piety which was entirely 
untouched by it; in the Calvinistic and sectarian Cromwell, and also in 
Gladstone and Lincoln, a position of this kind would have been quite impossible. 
For this separation between an external policy of force and an inward piety of 
feeling Bismarck liked to appeal to Luther; see Lenz: Bismarcks Religion ( Ausgew . 
Vortrage und Aufsatze, deutsche Bucher ei Nr. 18), Art. Bismarck in Religion in 
Geschichte und Gegenwart; Meinecke: B. s. Eintritt in den christlich-germanischen 
Kreis H. £., 1902; 0 . Baumgarten , B. s. Stellung zu Religion t snd Kirche, 1900; 
now, above all, E. Marcks: Bismarck , I, 1910. The impression of Bismarck’s 
political thought upon German Christian piety has been extraordinary even 
down to the present day ; but the glorification of force which has been rendered 
necessary by sin, with the withdrawal of the Christian ethic more to private 
relationships, is not only a peculiarity of the Prussian religion of the present 
day, even though it is only here that it has gained an enthusiastic acceptance 
as something quite natural which was alien to Luther’s ideas and for other 
reasons also to those of Bismarck. 

247 (p. 532.) Cf. the expression of opinion in the Kreuzzeitung on the 
aristocratic selection-theories of the well-known evolutionist sociologist 
Otto Ammon : “The weakness of the doctrine of the Blue and Red democracies 
cannot be represented more strikingly than in this book” ; they are results 
“against which even from a strictly conservative standpoint there is nothing 
to be said” ; see Stillich : Die politischen Parteien in Deutschland , /, Die Konservativen , 
p . 32; appeal of the Kreuzztitung to Machiavelli’s theory of Power, p. 5# v Or see 
the statement in the Conservative election programme of 1849: “The Con- 
servative candidate must be a political man. He must know that force in the 
life of a State is an eternally effective factor, and that it (although in itself 
unreasonable) may always be used if it produces that which is reasonable, 
as is proved by its being a fundamental condition of the life of the State” 
(Stillich, p. 218). 

250 (p. 534.) Cf. the section in Stillich: Die Rechtsauffassung der Konservativen , 
pp. 161-178. The inequality of law according to differences of class and the 
justice which takes account of the conditions of the time in contrast to the 
abstract equality before the law (p. 166). A mad example of Kadi justice is the 
verdict of the Duke Charles of Burgundy in von weltl. Obrigkeit , IV, 1, p. 272, 
to which Luther appeals: “A knight who engages the affections of the wife 
of his enemy and promises her that he will spare the life of her husband, and 
then, in spite of that, kills his enemy, is condemned to take the woman to 
wife, and then after the bridal night he is unexpectedly beheaded, and all his 
goods are given to the lady. See how such a judgment is freely due to reason, 
and goes so far beyond the law of all books that everyone must acknowledge its 
justice and find in his own heart that it is right.” 



PROTESTANTISM 


659 

251 (p* 535*) For the foundation of institutions in God and the meaning of 
this foundation, see Ehrhardt , p. 303. It is always meant indirectly. How this 
is understood is shown by the fact that Luther held that the Holy Roman 
Empire was appointed, that is, founded, by God, although Luther held that 
the translatio imperii by the Pope was a piece of trickery; W. Kohler: Luthers 
Schrift an den Adel , 1895, p. 242. “Starting from the idea of the absolute and 
unlimited arbitrariness of God . . . Luther recognizes in the Pope’s action a 
Divine intention, he places the Pope’s action under the guidance of God, 
seeing in the Pope the mechanical instrument of the Divine and Almighty 
Will.” Thus Professor Suchsland explains the Conservative theories of authority 
in the State, in morality, in law, in marriage, absolutely from the strictly 
scientific standpoint, that is, on the presupposition of the principle of selection; 
the theory of a “Divine appointment” is then held to be merely the transcendent 
dogmatic element of faith which is only something additional ( Stillich , p. 33). 

262 (P* 535-) On this point cf. Corpus Ref., XXI u. XVI; also Kohler: Luther 
und die Juristen , pp. 100-103; Troeltsch: Gerhard und Melancthon; Ellinger: Melanc- 
thon, 1902 , pp. 583-383; here his tendency to the aristocracy of the towns, just 
as it was with Erasmus; very good rendering in Hdnel: Mel., der Jurist (£./. 
Rechtsgeschichte, hg. v. Rudorjf, VIII, 1869). The following passage is relevant: 
“His standpoint is that of Scholasticism, in spite of his aversion to it, and that 
which in all his writings distinguishes him from the Scholastic writers is neither 
a greater precision in the definition of ideas nor a more independent and free 
method, neither new and fruitful ideas, nor even merely a deeper utilization 
of Aristotle, but solely the popularization of the subject-matter, the attempt 
to bring the philosophic way of thinking nearer to life, and naturally, above all, 
the altered view of the relation between Church and State” {p. 263). Only the 
doctrine of non-resistance must still be emphasized, as H. himself says in 
another place: “Behind the political ideas there are independent and peculiar 
conceptions and principles, as, for instance, especially, that man is created 
for Society, and that in Society conditions of authority and submission obtain 
which must be recognized and logically developed. But they are conceptions 
and principles which are Divinely implanted. It is this which makes the State 
a Divine institution. . . . The existing State and the existing law are Divine 
even when they are oppressive and stifle freedom ; even a Divinely appointed 
and unbelieving ruler must be respected in his rights as a scourge of God. 
Every self-willed and thoughtless alteration in the constitution and in the 
laws must be rejected; even departures from Reason must be tolerated, so 
long as they do not go wholly against Nature and then spoil it” (p. 260). Then, 
how under the influence of the problems which faced the Schmalkald League, 
Melancthon and Luther recognized the right of resistance, and incidentally 
adopted the Rationalistic individualistic conception of the Law of Nature, 
is shown by Cardauns, pp. 14-19 ; here, incidentally, are the preparatory stages 
of Calvin’s doctrine. Unfortunately, Cardauns does not show how these doctrines 
disappeared from Lutheranism ; their disappearance was probably connected 
with the general “Fundamentalist-Lutheran” reaction, and the reactionary 
propaganda which emanated from Saxony, through which, then, the forces 
which made for reform and progress were driven into Calvinism. In later 
Lutheranism the problem of resistance centres chiefly round the problem of 
the relation between the territorial lords and the Imperial power, in which a 
strictly Imperial and Conservative party stood in opposition to a Calvinistically 
influenced party, which was much freer and which centred in Jena; see Stintzing: 
Geschichte der deutschen Rechtswissenschaft , II, 1884, pp. 40-54. — The gradual 



860 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

decline of the liberal conception of Natural Law in the School of Melancthon, 
see v. Kaltenborn: Vorldufer des Hugo Grotius , 1848. 

862a (P- 537*) Cf. Cardauns , p . 13: at the beginning Melancthon follows the 
opinions of Luther; then, however, he shows “in opposition to Luther from the 
beginning, not only under the influence of external happenings”, his preference 
for class control of the ruling power. Cardauns points out his preference for 
Ph. de Commyncs (for the latter, ibid.,p. 30, and Baudrillart : Bodin , 1833, pp. 10- 
15), also echoes of the Erasmian doctrine of the State, Cardauns , pp. 31 ff. — 
For the connection between his hatred of the non-Sacramentarians and his 
aversion to a republic, see von Schubert: Bundnis und Bekenntnis , 1323-30, 1308, 
p. 3; M. s. Schule v. Hinrichs , 1 . 

* 58 (P- 537*) Cf. Stintzing: Geschichte der deutschen Rechtswissenschaft , 1 , 1880. Very 
characteristic here is the deduction of the jurist Konrad Lagus (pp. 302ff.) : 
distinction between the jus naturale primaevum and the jus naturale secundarium , 
the latter “granted to man by the grace of God against his corrupt nature”. 
“The law which flows from that the Romans call jus gentium because it is 
observed among all peoples. It is also called jus divinum. The Calvinists are 
wrong when they restrict this term to the standard laid down in the Gospel. 
For there are many leges vere divinae which are expressed neither in the Gospel 
nor in the Mosaic Law. The jus divinum is everything which corresponds to the 
Will of Christ and which purely human Reason requires for the protection of 
the existence of human society. This jus naturale has several degrees which are 
given in the Decalogue (by the distinction between the First and the Second 
Table). Its commandments — and, it is true, both those of the First and 
of the Second Table — can be inferred from human nature and Reason. Only, 
since the impulses of the sinful nature of man are so powerful that he often acts 
against the judicium naturale , it is not sufficient to leave obedience simply to his 
good-will. That is why it became necessary to invent other legum carceres in 
order to force men by public authority to obedience. These reflections lead to 
the positive law jus civile , “quod publica necessitate exigente civium suffragio ( !) 
in aliqua re publica constituitur”. In Kling, I, 307, we find the same con- 
clusions and the same way of treating the conceptions jus naturale primaevum 
and jus naturale secundarium as technical conceptions. It means the same thing 
that I have distinguished all through this book as the difference between the 
“absolute” and “relative” Natural Law. It is just the same in the standard 
jurist, Joh. Oldendorp, /, p. 371 : the jus naturale secundarium is said to be gathered 
up in the Decalogue as a means against sin ; thence it was taken over into the 
Roman Twelve Tables which the Romans are supposed to have learned from 
the Greeks, and the Greeks from the Hebrews. It is only with the aid of 
these examples that we see clearly into the meaning of the thought of early 
Lutheranism. 

854 (P- 538-) For the details, see in Stintzing , II; the doctrines of the theologians 
of the seventeenth century, in Schmidt: Ev.-Luth. Dogmatik, 433 ff.; Hollaz: 
“Causa efficiens principalis magistratus est Deus triunus, qui certis personis 
officium magistratus committit vel immediate (Exod. iff. 10; Num. xxvii. 18; 
1 Sam. ix. 15) vel mediate (John xix. 1 1) . . . Hodie ad officium magistratus 
personae habiles moderante Deo legitime perveniunt vel per electionem vel 
per successionem vel per justam occupationem.” J. Gerhard: “Magistratum 
potestate aliqua instructum esse pater ex Rom. xiii. 1. . . . Potestas ilia magis- 
tratus non est absoluta, illimitata et indeterminata, sed ad leges et normam 
superioris alicujus potestatis restricta. Cum enim potestatem suam a Deo 
magistratus accepcrit, ideo Deum superiorem recognoscere et illius voluntati 



PROTESTANTISM 


86 1 

ac legibus in usu hujus potestatis scse conformare tenetur. . • . Quando ergo 
politici absolutam potestatem [that is, Bodin’s doctrine] summo magistratui 
tribuunt, id non est accipiendum simpliciter nec respectu superioris sc. Dei, 
sed duiiitaxat respectu inferiorum magistratuum [this is in direct opposition 
to the main doctrine of Calvinism] . . . Propter peccatum protoplastorum 
non solum spiritualibus et aeternis futurac vitae bonis, sed etiam corporalibus 
et externis hujus vitae commodis genus humanum excidit. Sed Deus ex miranda 
et nunquam satis praedicanda benignitate propter filii intercessionem non 
ilia solum sed etiam haec restituit ac reparavit ac media illis conservandis 
ordinavit. . . . Per magistratum politicum Deus conscrvat pacem et tran- 
quillitatem externam, administrat justitiam civilem, defendit facultates, 
famam et corpora.” All this takes place through the Natural Law of Reason, 
only the later doctrine emphasizes mainly the Divine appointment of the 
existing order; upon this a jurisprudence which works up the empirical law 
material then bases itself, without caring very much about the theoretically 
asserted deduction from the Natural Law and Reason. — The doctrine of the 
jurists is summarized by Reinking : “The fundamental idea of his political 
convictions is the (mediated) Divine appointment of all authorities. He who 
attacks it breaks feith and is disobedient, and must expect to be punished by 
God, even when in extreme cases the resistance can be excused, i.e. when it is 
exercised against a prince who by despising the fundamental laws and by legal 
violence has become a ‘tyrant* (here, too, this is a relic of Natural Law 
Rationalist individualism!). To him the best of all forms of governments 
seems to be that of monarchy, because it is the most ancient and the most 
natural order, which most easily preserves peace, and which most nearly 
resembles the Divine government of the world’* ( Stintzing , II, igy). In matters 
affecting the law of the Empire, R. takes the Imperial standpoint ; the Empire 
is the fourth world monarchy of the Book of Daniel, which will last for ever. 
Authorities are the Roman law, and the law of feudalism, and the mediaeval 
jurists. “i?.’s work is interwoven with every fibre in the traditions of the Middle 
Ages so far as his decided Protestantism has not freed him** ( p . igg). The 
opposing modern school of Arumaus and Limaeus, which was influenced by 
the Netherlands and by Calvinism, seems (according to Stintzing* s illustrations) 
to have had modern ideas only in reference to the Imperial law. The analogous 
development in Catholic Absolutism (not, however, among the juridical 
philosophers), see Kaufmann , pp. i6ff. , and in Bossuet's Politique Tirie de V Venture, 
iyog; in English Absolutism similar conclusions in Filmer's Patriarcha , 1680. 
The Law of Nature only became suspect to orthodox Lutherans after the 
Natural Law of Grotius had emancipated it from theology ; see Stintzing , //, isg; 
over against that Reinking writes a Biblische Polizei , d. i. gewisse aus heiliger 
gottlicher Schrift zusammengebrachte, auf die drei Hauptstdnde , als geist lie hen, weltlichen, 
hduslichen , gerichtete Axiomata, Frankfurt , 1653; the large number of editions proves 
that the book found deserved acceptance {Stintzing, II, soyjff Similar in 
spirit is Seckendorff’s Deutscher Furstenstaat, 1655, and Christenstaat, 1685. — For the 
relation of Grotius and Pufendorf to these ecclesiastical schools of thought, see 
Bluntschli und Hinrichs, for Masius, see Bluntschli, p. 184. 

* 65 (p* 539*) On this cf. Roscher: Geschichte der Nationalokonomik in Deutschland, 
i8y4 . In spite of the opinion that the Reformation really constituted a renewal 
of economic thought as well, R. recognizes its purely Scholastic character 
(in this respect) in his description of both the main representatives of the 
Lutheran doctrine of Society; Melchior von Ossa (died 1557) and L. von Secken- 
dorff (died 1692): “Our friend Ossa stands likewise with one foot in the 



862 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 


theological period of political economy, and with the other in the juridical 
period. Besides the Bible, the Church Fathers, and Aristotle he quotes chiefly 
from the Corpora Juris ”, p . 7/5. That the latter is not in opposition to the 
Christian Natural Law has already been shown, and is also proved by the title of 
the main section of the work by Ossa: “ Von Gottseliger , weisslichen , vernunftigen und 
rechtmassigen Regierung und Institution ”. Here the identification of the Bible, 
Reason, and law are distinctly expressed. The description of von Seckendorff 
is similar: “That theological, or at least religious, colour of the science of the 
State and political economy, which the Reformation had not only retained 
from the Scholastic period, but had also considerably warmed and deepened, 
was quickly disappearing among S.'s contemporaries” {p. 240). On the 
development from the first to the second, see p. 252: the Prince becomes 
from a patrimonial lord a new head of the State; in spite of all the piety 
of the time, political science and the system of political economy “became, 
to a great extent, emancipated from the whole admixture of theology and 
jurisprudence”; only then did political science and political economy go 
beyond aphorisms and become systematic sciences. For the way in which the 
Church was hampered, and for the use of Scriptural examples for doctrines 
of Reason, even among authors of a modern outlook, see’the remarks on 
Obrecht , p. 152. The main interest was concerned with the preservation of the 
system of the division of classes, which was also served by the ordinances about 
dress, and to some extent by the laws about luxury (pp. ug , 727 , 727 ff. 247) ; 
it has been instituted by God like the State itself, to whose conception it 
belongs. The second main interest is the increase of the power of the territorial 
lord, who, however, remains bound in the patriarchal manner to Natural 
and Divine Law, and may not rule in the Machiavellian fashion {pp. io6 t 
7 2gff. y 204). — For the theologians the whole is a concern of the authorities, 
who in so doing have to behave according to the Natural Law and the Divine 
Law, as the appointed organ for the working out of that which was suitable ; 
thus Hutter: “Praecipua officia magistratus politici sunt: (1) curam gerere 
utriusque tabulae decalogi, quod ad externam disciplinam attinet, (2) ferre 
leges de negotiis civilibus et oeconomicis consentaneas juri divino et naturali ; 
(3) sedulo providere, ut leges promulgatae veniant in executionem ; (4) delin- 
quentibus pro qualitate delicti poenas irrogare, obedientes fovere et p~aemiis 
afficere”; or Hollaz' “Magistratus civilis est ordinatus ad bonum publicum 
idque quadruplex : ( 1 ) ecclesiasticum, cum reges nutritii ecclesiae et episcopi 
extra templum; (2) civile, dum civium commoda tuetur et hostes externos 
finibus patriae propulsat; (3) morale, quatenus honestas praescribit leges, 
quibus subditi in officio continentur, ut vitam tranquillam agant in pietate et 
honestate (1 Tim. ii. 2); (4) naturale, quo imperantes prospiciant subditis 
de commeatu et aliis necessariis instar Pharaonis (Gen. xli. 34)”. Schmidt: 
Dogmatiky 460. For the special nature of the content of the economic Natural 
Law, see further below. For the relation between the growing modern political 
economy and its individualistic rationalistic hedonistic character to that of 
the ecclesiastical Law of Nature, see Oncken: Geschichte der Nationaldkonomie y 
/, 7,902. 

,## (p* 542.) This fundamental theory finds its classic expression in Luther’s 
Greater Catechism : it is the duty of the individual to submit to the existing 
institutions as in the “media per creaturas bona percipiendi”. For “creaturae 
tantum manus sunt, canales, media et organa, quorum opera et adminiculo 
Deus omnia largitur hominibus. . . . Quam ob rem et haec edia [namely, 
parents, authorities, and the general relationships between one man and 



PROTESTANTISM 


863 

another] . . . non sunt respuenda neque temeraria praesumtione aliae rationes 
et viae investigandae, quam Deiis praecipit”. Thus parents, governments, and 
Christian fellow-men have received their task from God in their post which 
has been given them by Nature, “ut omnis generis officia nobis ostendant et 
exhibeant adeo, ut haec non ab illis, sed per illos a Deo peculiariter accipiamus”. 
(Symb. Bd. ed. Muller, p. 390). The most important commandment among those 
which relate to human relationships, that is, of the Second Table, is the fourth : 
“thou shalt honour thy father and thy mother” ( p . 403). At first this position 
of the family is described in its immediate significance, but as the highest 
ideal of sociological relations: “Hunc parentum statum et ordinem Deus 
praeciptfe hoc ornavit elogio ante omnes, qui sub ipso sunt, status et ordines, 
ut non simpliciter praecipiat parentes esse amandos, sed honorandos. . . . 
Est enim honor res amore multis modis sublimior, utpote quae non tantum 
amorem in se complectatur, verum etiam singularem quandam modestiam, 
humilitatem et reverentiam, quae cuiquam quasi majestati hie occultae 
habenda sit” ( p . 406). But this fundamental theory covers all kinds of authority, 
and since differences of authority, owing to the inequality among men, are 
everywhere present, it finally covers all relationships in general: “In hujus 
praecepti explaaatione neque illud praetereundum est, quod ad multiplicem 
obedientiam superiorum attinet, nempe eorum, qui versantur in imperio et 
rei publicae procurationem sustinent. Si quidem e parentum potestate omnes 
aliae propagantur et manant.” Thus there follow the relations to authorities, 
to which, of course, the local authorities and the lords of the manor belong ; 
then teachers of all kinds, and the pastors, then the neighbours, and finally 
employers of labour and servants, “ita, ut omnes, quotquot domini appellatione 
censentur, vice parentum sint ab iisdemque potestatem ac vim regnandi 
accipiant. Unde quoque secundum Scripturam omnes dicuntur patres, utpote 
qui in sua gubernatione officium patris obire ergaque subditos patris animum 
inducere debeant. Quemadmodum et olim apud Romanos et alios plerosque 
populos heros herasque patres et matresfamilias nominabant. Ita quoque suos 
magistratus et principes dixerunt patres patriae, nobis Christianis in dedecus 
et ignominiam” (p. 412/.). This implies the duty of care for others on the 
part of parents and masters : “Neque enim Dei voluntas est, ut aut perditi 
nebulopes aut enormes tyranni hujus officii procurationem obeant . . ., sed 
cogitent potius, quod et ipsi Deo obedientiam debeant, ut officium suae fidei 
delegatum ipsis curae sit ac sollicitudini utque liberos, familiam et subditos 
suos non tantum nutriant et corporalibus alimentis provideant, sed omnium 
maxime ad laudem et gloriam Dei propagandam educant” ( p . 417). Certainly 
it is generally true : “erga fratres, sorores et proximum in genere nihil amplius 
(Deus) praecipit quam amore prosequendos esse” (/>. 106) ; after that, however, 
follows the statement that it is a much higher thing to honour than to love, and 
in the general graded character of all conditions (coram Deo omnes quidem 
pares sumus, sed nos inter nos hoc dispari et ordinato discrimine non possumus 
non discrepare, 406) love everywhere is mingled with elements of authority 
and subordination, and everywhere it is replaced by grateful humility or a 
paternal authority.— Just as classically formulated is this fundamental theory 
with its religious basis within the modern Lutheran ethic by von Hofmann : 
“Our assistance to the world is conservative. The humility of our love to the 
world excludes all arbitrary action” (pp. 136 ff .) ; see also Stillich , p. 89: “The 
preparation for the social organization of Society desired by the Conservatives 
is that of the family. The latter”, says the venerable leader of the Saxon 
Conservatives, Freiherr v. Friesen , “purposes the harmonious co-operation of all 



864 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

the individual members in a definite whole, whereas the bureaucratic (that is, 
the modern) State, in the principle of equality, destroys that which was 
originally equal, for its own special purpose, and the individual atoms which 
it thus gains it forces violently into its own scheme.* * Even down to the present 
day these are the fundamental sociological features of the world-outlook among 
the Conservatives, so far as their policy is a policy of a world-outlook at all. 
It is, however, also clear that this view is closely connected with an anti- 
individualistic immobilized general situation in politics and economics, and 
that an urban mobile individualistic and capitalistic civilization would need 
different ethical and religious convictions. That the difficulties of the Lutheran 
Catechism lie in ethics still more than in dogma every pastor knows who 
works in great cities and among working-class communities. It represents a 
fundamental theory of sociological questions which cannot be carried out in 
our modern city civilization. On this point cf. Traub: Ethik und Kapitalismus a , 
*907- 

268 (p* 547 *) 0 ° this point see J. Kostlin: Luthers Theologie 2 , i88j , p. 482 : 
“Luther defines marriage as ‘conjunctio unius maris et unius feminae insepara- 
bilis, non tantum juris naturae as the Canonists express it : sed ctiam voluntatis 
ct voluptatis, ut ita dicam, divinae*. Its purpose or its cau\a Jinalis he sees in 
the procreation of children, in the procreatio sobolis . Before the Fall it had 
already been instituted as a means of providing the Church and the State 
with useful members. ‘Thus marriage and the household are not merely 
fons et origo generis humani , but at the same time they ought to serve as paratio 
ecclesiae and become fons rei publicae .* After the Fall it also serves the purpose 
as a remedy against lust and a check to its sinful outbreaks. Indeed, he now 
describes this as primus finis , whereas otherwise the original purpose remains 
finis magis principalis. Thus in his mind that desire still retains its sinful character, 
but ‘approbatio et beneplacitum Dei tegit miseram turpitudinem libidinis et 
removet iram Dei imminentem illi concupiscentiaeV* — The inner nature of 
marriage itself Luther explains very beautifully in the Greater Catechism, in 
the exposition of the Sixth Commandment, particularly at the end, where he 
is dealing with the subject of “chastity” within marriage : “Ubi enim volumus 
conjugali castitati locum esse, ibi necessum est ante omnia, ut vir et mulier 
in amore Concordes conversentur, ut alter alterum ex animo mutua c^uandam 
benevolentia et fide complectatur. Quod si praesto fuerit, ipsa quoque castitas 
sua sponte sine mandato consequetur” ( Muller , 426). In addition, cf. Wald. 
Kawerau: Die Ref. und die Ehe , 1892 ( V . f Ref.-Gesch ., Nr. 39); Marianne Weber: 
Ehefrau und Mutter y pp. 282-289; here it is rightly pointed out that “the new 
ideal of womanhood which lays the chief stress upon the moral qualities of the 
house-mother, on love and loyalty, on the fear of God and trusting God, on 
reliability and honesty** ( Kawerau , 7/), has been strongly influenced by the 
ideals of the Book of Ecclesiasticus ; further, cf. Rade: Stellung des Christentums zum 
Geschlechtsleben ( Rel . Volksbb ., V 7/8) , 1910; a collection of the most important 
passages in W. Walter: Fur Luther wider Rom y 1906. For the view of the matter 
as it affects economics and the theory of population, see Roscher: Geschichte der 
Nationalokonomik, pp. 57-59. For concupiscence, see Braun: Luthers Lehre von der 
Konkupisztnz . This, however, is not simply a relic of the Catholic and monastic 
system ; the thought lies much more in the system, as we shall see in similar 
ideas on the State and work. In the dry definitions of the later Lutheran Schol- 
astic thinkers ( Schmidt , Dogmatik , 461-465) , this feature disappears, but only 
behind the positive character of the command. Luther’s “relics of Catholicism” 
are connected with the early Christian opposition between the world and 



PROTESTANTISM 


865 

salvation, and they concern essential problems of Christian thought, as indeed 
the problem of sex relations undoubtedly is. — For Luther’s pessimism about 
actual conditions, see G. Kat : “Quoniam vero apud nos adeo foeda et nefanda 
omnium vitiorum et scortationum lerna cernitur, hoc praeceptum quoque 
ad versus omnia impudicitiae genera et species constitutum est. . . . Tantum 
ergo hoc praeceptuma nobis exigit, ut quisque turn pro se vitam castam agat, 
turn proximo quoque in hoc obinenda et tuenda sit auxilio” ( Muller , 423 ). — 
Rode , p, 5/, says : “The transference of the chief emphasis to the inmost centre 
of personality and the proclamation of Christian freedom which sprang out 
of that was bound to have as a result a complete change of judgment about 
the external processes of the life of sex. And we can only regard it as a relic 
of Augustinian and Catholic tradition that still under the influence of Luther’s 
example in the Protestant Church the universality of human sin was attributed 
to the sex origin of each individual.” This deduction, which is certainly possible 
from the logical point of view, from the principle of Christian freedom, was, 
however, not made by Luther. The life of sex and erotic love are precisely not 
gifts of God with their own beauty to be freely used and shaped, but they are 
simply a tribute paid to Nature, which the Christian can and ought to make 
a means for the exercise of the love of one’s neighbour. Naturally, the pre- 
suppositions which determine our point of view, namely, the biological con- 
ception of “lust” and the poetic glorification of eroticism, do not exist for 
Luther ; with him, rather, the predominant idea is the doctrine of lust as a 
result of the Fall. 

269 (P- 548.) On this point cf. Kostlin: Theologie Luthers , //, 485-490 , 553-564; 
J. Kostlin: Staat , Recht und Kirche und die ev. Ethik , Stud. u. Kritt., 1877; Branden- 
burg: Lds Anschauungen von Staat und Gesellschaft ; Lenz : Luthers Lehre von der 
Obrigkeit ( Preuss . Jahrbb., 75, 1894); Jdger: Politische Ideen L.’s und ihr Einfluss 
auf die innere Entwickelung Deutschlands ( Preuss . Jahrbb ., 1903); K. Kdhler: Luther 
und die Juristen. Lenz pays too little attention to the connection with the mediaeval 
world of thought, and connects the modern State too directly with Luther’s 
ideas ; Brandenburg rightly emphasizes the former, but undervalues the positive 
value of Reason and the Divine appointment of the State, which certainly only 
comes out in Luther later on. Gottfried Arnold: Unparteyische Kirchen- und Ketzer - 
historic, 1700, II, 11 and 12 , 18-28 , represents Luther’s politics with an emphasis 
on the features of detachment from the world; the newest is Karl Muller: Kirche , 
Gemeinde, und weltliche Obrigkeit nach Luther , Christl. Welt , 1910; the question of 
the State is, however, scarcely mentioned in this book. 

260 (p* 55 1 *) Cf. the tractate Ob Kriegsleute auch in seligem Stand sein konnen , 
1526 , and Vom Krieg wider die Tiirken , 1529. Here again the Old Testament 
has to be drawn in so as to justify a not really Christian idea. Later, of course, 
Luther thought less harshly, and perhaps also less logically, about these things ; 
see Cardauns , pp. 1-17. But upon the whole the particularism and the rejection 
of a policy of intervention is amain feature of genuine Lutheranism, as the works 
of Schubert which have been mentioned show. On problems of war and 
treaties, see above all Hortleder: Handlungen und Ausschreiben von Rechtmdssigkeit 
des deutschen Krieges, Gotha , 1617 und 1618 , where the material is collected, 
especially II; see here the discussion by Ratzenberger , who argues that Melanc- 
thon, Jonas, Bugenhagen, Menius, etc., had fallen away from Luther’s pure 
doctrine of resistance (p. 39 ), also Theolog. Jahresbericht , XXVIII , p. 460 , on 
Schweizer: Der Donaufeldzug von 1546. 

161 (p. 552.) Lenz gives it as his opinion: “In this double relationship of a 
Christian government in its negative function of preserving peace, maintaining 
vol. n. DD 



866 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 


law, and furthering material interests, and in its positive duty to secure peace, 
I believe, lies the solution of the much discussed problem, and of the harmony 
which is lacking in the life and doctrine of the Reformer. . . . Two kingdoms, 
both founded by God, are spread throughout the world, the creature and the 
Gospel, indivisible in every Christian, and yet theoretically to be kept separate 
like soul and body, idea and appearance; but the faith remains in an ideal 
freed from all the burdens of earth in the Kingdom of God” ( pp . 435ff-)> This 
is a distinctly modernized solution of the problem ; in reality, Luther firmly 
maintains the old solution of Scholasticism, the solution with the aid of con- 
ceptions of Natural Law and the Gospel, only transplanted from the mediaeval 
idea of an ascent from Nature to Grace, to the new sphere in which both are 
within each other. Otherwise Luther himself appeals to Augustine : “Thus I 
have written about the secular authority as glorious and useful as no teacher 
has done since the time of the Apostles, excepting possibly St. Augustine” 
( Krieg wider die Tiirken , B. A ., IV, i,p. 441). In his writings about the Peasants* 
Revolt and the war he teaches the dualistic morality of the use of law, force, 
and authority on the one hand, and of the suffering and sacrificial ethic of 
love of the Sermon on the Mount on the other hand, in an often absolutely 
amazingly harsh distinction; see, for example,/?/;. 322 ff . : “What do you think 
that Christ would say to it that you bear His Name and call yourselves a 
Christian body when you are so far away from that, when, indeed, you do 
and teach so abominably against His law that you are not even worthy of 
being called Turks or heathen, but much worse, since you violently oppose both 
Divine and Natural Law which is observed among all the heathen (by rebellion 
and the encouragement of a Christian form of communism) . . . Further, we 
will now speak of the Christian and evangelical law, which does not bind the 
heathen like the former law, for as you boast and like to hear that you are 
called Christians and also wish to be regarded as such, so you must also endure 
that I hold up to you your law. Give ear now, beloved Christians, and listen 
to your Christian law. Thus speaks Christ (Matt. v. 39) : ‘Resist not evil, 
but he who impels thee to go with him one mile go with him two, and who 
takes thy cloke let him take thy coat also and he who strikes thee upon the one 
cheek, offer him also the other. . . .’ Indeed, Christ says (Matt. v. 44) that we 
ought to wish good to those who do us evil, and pray for our persecutors and 
love our enemies and do good to those who injure us. These are our Christian 
rights, dear friends. ... A child, indeed, would understand from these sayings 
that it is a Christian law not to resist evil, not to take to the sword, not to 
defend oneself, not to revenge oneself, but to deliver up one’s body and one’s 
possessions, and let anyone take it who will. We indeed have enough in our 
Lord Himself who will not leave us as He has promised. Suffering, suffering 
cross, cross is the Christian’s law and there is no other.” Or,/;. 363 : “There are 
two kingdoms : the one is the Kingdom of God, the other the kingdom of the 
world (in this instance he does not mean the realm of evil, but of the natural 
creation of Reason). . . . God’s Kingdom is a kingdom of grace and mercy and 
not a kingdom of wrath or of punishment. For it means nothing but forgiveness 
and protection, loving and serving, doing good, having peace and joy, etc. 
But the kingdom of this world is a kingdom of wrath. In this kingdom there is 
nothing but punishment and resistance, judgment and condemnation in order 
to force the evil and to protect the good. Therefore also this kingdom possesses 
and wields the sword. . . . The texts which speak of mercy belong to the 
Kingdom of God and to Christians, they do not apply to the secular law. 
For a Christian must not only be merciful, but he must also suffer all manner of 



PROTESTANTISM 


867 

evil, etc. But the kingdom of this world, which is simply the servant of the 
Divine wrath over evil men and the precursor of hell and of eternal death, 
and it must not be merciful but severe, etc. . . . ; it looks upon the evil men 
that it may punish them and hold them in check and in peace for the protection 
and the deliverance of the good.” This, indeed, is something other than the 
relation between the idea and the appearance. 

262 (p* 553-) pessimism is strongly emphasized by Brandenburg : “Thus 
at the beginning at least he had an ideal floating about in the air of a Christian 
society which should be governed by an authority informed with the Christian 
spirit. This authority, however, was not to be subordinate to the spiritual 
authority and directed by it ; otherwise its actions would be forced and value- 
less; but while it possessed an equal right externally it was to be combined 
with the spiritual authority in the same Christian spirit. . . . This thought runs 
right through Luther’s Address to the Nobility of the German Nation . But the dream 
soon faded, and when he awoke Luther found himself alone with a few 
like-minded souls among the heathen, and he gained the conviction that this 
was how it would remain. Henceforward he had no more interest in trying to 
picture how a Christian Society might be created and ought to be, for, he 
thought, it indeed will never come to pass; the few Christians scattered 
throughout the world will never be able to form a closely knit community. 
The world as it is cannot be governed with Christian love according to the 
Gospel ( p . 9). . . . Therefore Luther says: ‘If thou sufferest violence and 
injustice, thou must say that is the government of this world. If thou wilt 
live in the world, that is what thou must expect. Thou wilt never succeed in 
bringing about that it should happen otherwise. If thou wilt live among the 
wolves, then thou must howl with them. Here in this world we are serving in 
an inn where the Devil is master, and the world is the landlady, and all kinds 
of evil passions are the servants ; and these all are the enemies and opposers of 
the Gospel. Thus if thy money is stolen or thou art injured in thy honour, that 
is just what thou hast to expect in this house. 5 Nowhere do I find the essential 
element in Luther’s outlook on the world so clearly expressed as in this illustra- 
tion. The monk wishes to forsake the service of the devilish landlord by flight, 
the struggling Church desires to tear the rule out of the hands of the innkeeper 
by external means of authority and gain control of the domestics; at first 
Luther hoped to be able to convert the inhabitants and fill them with the 
Christian spirit ; now, however, he has given up this hope, but in spite of that 
he wants to stay in the terrible house. For he is not there of his own will, but 
because he has been placed there by his God. Therefore he desires to do his 
duty here, to let himself be beaten and ill-treated if it pleases the evil master 
and his servants to do this, but he will not stir from the spot till his Lord calls 
him away, and every good hour which he enjoys he will rejoice in as a special 
grace” ( pp . 5^.). Brandenburg , in my opinion, lays too much stress upon these 
passages — at least alongside of them there are others in which the Christian 
order of life in public and private morality seems to be something possible 
and desirable, upon which, indeed, his ethical text-book, the Greater Catechism, 
is constructed. In my opinion the really characteristic element is rather his 
alternation between that despairing pessimism and the triumph that the 
genuinely evangelical order has at last become a reality. The principles, on 
the other hand, in which Lenz ( p . 440) describes the continued influence of 
Lutheran ideas as the “vital mark of our people” (“in them is rooted the right 
of our sword, its might, and our obedience. With forceful power they fetter 
everyone to the public will, and in freedom millions serve them without 



868 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 


difference of creed. They are interwoven with every public office, with our 
customs of marriage and family life, with our ideals of war ( !) and all our ( !) 
work of peace. Upon this foundation our whole classical literature ( !) has 
grown up, and these ideas still dominate large sections of our art ( !) ; only 
through them has genuine tolerance and free research ( !) become possible**), 
are only very partially of Lutheran origin. A continued influence of the 
Lutheran idea of the State and of Society in reality only takes place in the 
Weltanschauung of the Conservative party, and, above all, in its standard- 
bearer Stahly who, however, found himself obliged to incorporate Calvinistic 
and Independent individualism into the newly formed Lutheran i4ea of the 
State ; cf. Stahl: Der christliche Staat. 

803 (p- 554*) Gf. L. von Seckendorff: Teutscher Furstenstaat, 5 , 1687 (at first i6$6)y 
especially c. /, 5 and 8 of the third section. The author, however, confesses in 
the Foreword : “I have often been obliged to put the Regula instead of that 
which in reality I ought to find, but which I found nowhere, or very little.** — 
Especially characteristic of the spirit of the whole is pp. 194$.'. “The main 
aim of all this is the healthful preservation of the police, or of the whole 
Government, in its august power and greatness, and the ultimate aim is the 
glory of God.’* In Christian States, however, the task is not /tie rely that of the 
maintenance of authority, the prevention of crime, and the preservation of 
peace, but also the moral furtherance of the subjects, “a constant approximation 
and exercise, which among the ancient pagan peoples of Greece and Rome 
was sought in many kinds of instruction from learned philosophers and poets. 
But in a Christian State the Government can and must go still further in this 
matter”. It must cultivate right sentiments and dispositions, and since this 
cannot be brought about by compulsion and by the law, the discipline of the 
Church, the home, and the school must also be used for this purpose. “Not- 
withstanding this, however, there are certain matters in the administration of 
a country which concern every person in it ; these are dealt with by the Govern- 
ment, since they also can bring harm and vexation to others in the same land 
if they are not wisely regulated. As, for instance, a seemly outward celebra- 
tion of Sundays and festivals, the avoidance of shameful drunkenness, and 
where, after a certain time of day, one must stop tippling and treating. Further, 
a regular calling and activity and the avoidance of idleness . . ., fo* which 
purpose also an excellent method is the provision of a house of correction for 
those naughty persons, for the improvement of their life and for the relief 
of the minds of other people. The preservation of a seemly order and precedence 
between the various classes and subjects, according to their honour, their 
position, and their office, in all events and gatherings, both in clothing and in 
other outward things . . ., in order that confusion, misunderstanding, and 
vexation may be prevented.” This conservatism, however, is only to serve the 
cause of peace and order, but it is not to exclude all idea of progress (p. 5/5). 
“The Government is bent on introducing into the country more and more 
what will be useful and will serve the way of peace and understanding, by all 
kinds of friendly methods, and granting of immunities, it desires to show that 
it desires to encourage progress and advancement in many ways.” — Joh . 
Gerhard , in his Loci (ed. Cotta , 1775)9 vols . XIII and XIV , develops the Natural 
Law and Christian ideas of the State in great breadth and detail, with, however, 
the lack of vision, which considers it quite possible to realize the ideal of a 
Christian society with a Christian spirit of the government, pure Church 
doctrine and the humble obedience of the subjects: “Utraque potestas ad 
ecclesiae collectionem conservationem ac propagationem itemque ad Dei 



PROTESTANTISM 


869 

gloriam ordinata est. Mutuas cnim sibi tradunt operas. . . . Sine ecclesiastico 
ministerio commode quidem, at non pie ; sine politica potestate pie quidem, 
sed non commode vivi potest. (XIII , 225) ! The “Magistratus sunt Dii terrestres” 
(XIV , 305) ! This lack of vision is also reflected in the ideal of the Primitive 
State, which in development without the Fall would have been, in spite of 
that, a “subjectio”, but only a “subjectio filialis” instead of a “subjectio 
servilis” (p. 240 ). On treaties: “Foedera ipsa urgente rei publicae necessitate 
cum infidelibus et diversae religionis hominibus instituta non possunt absolute 
et simpliciter improbari ; cavendum interim, ne adhaereat fiducia in humanum 
auxilium ac diflidentia erga Deum neve defensio ecclesiae, quae est solius 
dei opus? foederibus illis transscribatur” (XIV, 14). Support of oppressed 
co-religionists in foreign countries only allowed as diplomatic (XIV, 72). All 
that is said about the Sermon on the Mount is that it is parabolic in character 
and must not be taken quite literally, and of the law it says simply : “Observa 
etiam quod magistratus dicatur constitutus subditis in bonum, nimirum ut 
bonum publicum promoveat justitiam administrando, justos defendendo, 
sontes puniendo. Quare cum hoc bono et dono divinitus concesso utimur, 
hoc est cum officium magistratus imploramus, recte omnino facimus” (XIV, 133 ). 
As in the Churqji, the Church law has been introduced as the Divine law, 
and is in general no longer a problem, so also for the State and for Society, 
law and might have ceased to be a problem, they are a bonum divinitus con - 
cessum (p. 137 ). The comprehensive polemic against the Anabaptists is a 
thorough transformation of the Sermon on the Mount, in the light of other 
passages of Scripture, which is continually being renewed ; the spirit of the 
whole is that of the most extreme Philistine theological politics. 

264 (P- 554 *) On this point cf. Roscher: Geschichte der Nalionalokonomik and 
Aug. Oncken: Geschichte der Nationalokonomie , I, 1302; and also the well-known 
treatises by Schmoller: Z ur Geschichte der Nationalokonomischen Ansichten in 
Deutschland wdhrend der Reformationsperiode, Z-f ■ d. gesamte Staatswissenschaft, i860, 
pp. 461-716; Wiskemann: Darstellung der in Deutschland z. Z- der Reform, herrschenden 
Nationalok. Ansichten (Jablonowskische Preisschrift, 1861); also Uhlhorn: Geschichte 
der christlichen Liebestatigkeit , III , 1830; Uhlhorn: Katholizismus und Prot. gegeniiber 
der sozialen Frage 2 , 1887; see Eck in the detailed introduction to Luther's Von 
Kaufhandlung und Wucher, Bd. IV, 1, pp. 434-513; K. Kohler: Luther und die 
Juristen,pp. 1 11-124; Bbhmer: Luther im Licht der neueren Forschung,pp. 130-133; 

Brandenburg: Luthers Stellung zu Staat und Gesellschaft; Frank G. Ward, presentation 
and estimate of Luther’s views of the State and its economic tasks ; Conrad's 
Abhh., XXI, 1838; finally, my own presentation of the subject in Kultur der 
Gegenwart, pp. 544-552 . — For the general economic setting in which the 
position of the Reformers moved, see Lamprecht: Deutsche Geschichte, V and 
VI; Schmoller: Das Merkantilsystem in seiner historischen Bedeutung (Umrisse 
und Untersuchungen, 1830, pp. 1-60), the numerous researches of G. von Below, 
especially the Untergang der mittelalterlichen Stadtwirtschaft (Jahrb.fiir Nationalok. 
und Statistik , 1301 ) and Territorium und Stadt , 1300 ; examples of the economic 
situation in the towns in Bothe: Frankfurter Patriziervermogen im 16. Jahrh ., 
Archiv fur Kultur geschichte, Beiheft 2, 1308; for rural and provincial conditions, 
see Schauenburg, 100 Jahre Oldenburgischer Kirchengeschichte , V, 1308. For the 
seventeenth century, see compilations in Handtke: Deutsche Kultur im 
des 30 j . Kriegs , 1306, see Below: Die Frage des Riickgangs der wirtsch. Verhaltnisse 
vor dem 30 j . Krieg (Vierteljahrsschrift fur Soz •- und Wirtschafts geschichte, 1303, 
pp. 160-167). At the present day we must take it for granted that the great 
economic and social upheavals of the sixteenth century arose independently 



870 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

of the religious movement, and that in them Lutheranism at first adopted an 
essentially reactionary attitude, whereas the casuistical ethic of Catholicism 
was in a position to make compromises with them. 

a6# (p* 555*) On the “traditionalist” character of the Lutheran doctrine of 
property, see Max Weber: Geist des Kapitalismus , Archiv . XX, pp. 44-50 ; on the 
ethical objection to competition which is evident, particularly in Luther’s 
doctrine of prices, Schmoller, 451 ff. Luther himself says (Kaufhandlung, BA, 
p . 527) : “We ought to be satisfied with a very moderate standard of living . . . 
not day and night try to reach something higher.” Oncken calls this the 
“ascetic” conception of industry in contrast to the “hedonistic” conception 
which entered in with Adam Smith {pp. 152, 149). In the question of usury 
Melanchthon is more inclined to compromise than Luther, and the later 
orthodox Lutherans did not perpetuate Luther’s severe attitude towards 
usury, Neumann: Geschichte des Wuchers; that, however, does not mean a new 
principle, but only the modification which we notice everywhere of Luther’s 
ethical radicalism. 

272 (P* 557*) This non-feudal character is also a marked feature of the medi- 
aeval economic ethic ; on the relation of both elements in the mediaeval town and 
in the Canon Law, see Oncken , I, 125 , who is excellent on t^iis point; Oncken 
describes it as the system of the “gebundene Geldwirtschaft”, which is opposed 
to the later “ungebundene” capitalistic economy of the towns. The Reformers 
only opposed the latter kind. Only so were they in a position to prefer the 
Roman law, which is quite opposed to the feudal constitution and favours 
both an economy based on money and the principate of the territorial lord. 
The modern tendency of the Reformers consists essentially in handing over 
economic matters to the territorial lords, who are obliged and entitled to 
increase possessions and industry for the good of the whole; cf. Schauenburg: 
s. Theol. Jahresbericht , 436. Thus with the blessing of Lutheranism and without 
ecclesiastical control they entered the path of mercantilism as well as that of 
an absolutist social policy. Otherwise already Scholasticism had empowered 
the territorial lords to gather treasure, and thus they were exempt from civic 
morality ( Oncken , I, p. 128 ). 

278 (P- 55^0 Cf. the highly characteristic passages in Kaufhandlung, BA. 
IV, 1, pp. 523-527, on the four ways in which we ought to behave in a Qhristian 
way in business: firstly, that we ought to allow ourselves willingly to be 
exploited if the Government does not prevent it ; secondly, that we ought to 
give to those in need freely ; thirdly, that we ought to lend without receiving 
it back again. Then only comes the fourth way, that we buy and sell goods 
for goods or goods for money as a measure of value and a method of preserving 
value; for the latter end, however, the fixing of the pretium justum by the 
Government is necessary. Yet still more plain is the much-quoted letter to the 
people of Dantzig in the year 1525, in which he says that the taking of interest 
is forbidden by the Gospel, but then continues : “But the Gospel is a spiritual 
law by which one cannot govern, but about which each man must decide for 
himself whether he will observe it or whether he will leave it alone. And one 
may and ought to force no one to it, any more than to faith ; for here it is 
not the sword but the Spirit of God which must teach and govern. Therefore 
the spiritual rule of the Gospels must be separated from the external secular 
rule and the two must not be mixed with each other. . . . The Gospel teaches, 
indeed, that one is to have no care for possessions at all, but whoever forces 
me he takes from me that which is mine.” Thus according to human law he 
would sanction at least a limited and officially fixed interest of 5 per cent. 



PROTESTANTISM 


871 

(Oncken, I, p. 144 ). This, again, is the well-known dualistic ethic of Luther on 
account of which Luther’s attitude on the question of interest has often been 
called hesitating and uncertain; that, however, is not so inwardly and in 
itself in the Christian demand it is not so ; it only becomes so when the serious 
effort to realize it in practice is given up and when a secular use is recognized 
in addition. 

274 (p- 55^0 Thus Luther is ready to tolerate the sins which inevitably belong 
to the desire for gain which characterizes the system of trade which is allowed : 
“Therefore thou shalt not burden thy conscience with that, but thou must 
bring it to God as another sin which cannot be overcome to which we are all 
prone ; oJmmend it thus to God with the paternoster and leave it to Him, for 
necessity and the kind of work drives thee into this failing, not knavery and 
envy, for I am speaking here of good-hearted and God-fearing people who do 
not wish to do wrong. Just as the duty of marriage is not carried out without 
sin, and still on account of necessity God winks at it because there is nothing 
else to be done” (BA., IV, i,pp.gigff). It is exactly the same with the toleration 
of the compulsory character of the State as the “kingdom of wrath”. 

276 (p. 560.) On this contrast see Schmoller, g6g, ggi, 6g2, and yig ; on a motive 
of Socialism present among the Reformers, and only restricted in favour of the 
situation conditioned by original sin, see Schmoller, 708 ff. ; on the religious and 
ethical motives for the regulations in defence of the poor and the debtors 
(as in the Canon Law), see Schmoller, 323 and ggi. The Socialistic element, 
which — on a religious basis, and with the presupposition of sin and inequality — 
the canonistic Lutheran doctrine contains, is also emphasized by Oncken, p. 135 ; 
there also note the connection between the physiocratic doctrine and this 
“natural economic ethic”. 

281 (p. 561.) For the social organization in Luther’s view which quite 
corresponds to the mediaeval idea, see Brandenburg, p. 11; Schmoller , pp. 473, 
483-487, 688. How natural Luther found the guild organization is shown by 
the anecdote in his Table Talk, according to which Luther claimed that 
among the tailors there ought to be special groupings for making breeches, 
jerkins, or coats, in order that the work might be better ( Schmoller , p. 487). 
There is a wealth of material for the social history of Lutheranism in Drews: 
“Einfltts^der Gesellschaftlichen Zustande auf das kirchliche Leben y * (Z f. Theol. und 
Kirche, igo6), and “Der ev. Geistliche in der deutschen Vergangenheit” , 1303. To a 
great extent the theory continues the barren scholastic threefold division ; the 
third estate is never constructed in its constituent parts, the urban and agrarian, 
and then further in their mutual organization ; above all, the fourth estate of 
servants, day-labourers, serfs, and slaves never appears in a category by itself. 
As a rule the theologians deal with the status economicus as a domestic economy 
in which the servants are included and which as far as possible they regard 
as a self-contained household ; cf. the meagre statements in Schmidt: Ev.-Luth. 
Dogmatik,p. 462 ; here the only distinctions that are made are the societas paterna, 
that is, the smaller family group, and the societas herilis, that is the legitima 
dominorum et servorum conjunctio divinitus instituta ob mutuam utilitatem, and for 
all further detail people are commended to the study of the Decalogue. The 
real social theory and policy is left in the hands of the authorities, of the princely 
police, and of the financiers ; the theological ethic emphasizes only the general 
principle of patriarchalism. — A book which Gottfried Arnold often quotes and 
uses, called Spiegel aller Stdnde, by J. Cuno, I was unable to obtain. 

282 (p. 561 .) On this point Luther exclaims against the demand of the peasants 
that serfdom ought to be abolished (BA. IV, i,pp . 334 ff -) : “There ought to be 



872 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

no serfs because Christ has set us all free. What then is that? This means 
Christian freedom would be quite carnal — did not Abraham and other 
patriarchs and prophets also have bondmen? Read St. Paul and what he 
teaches about the servants who in his time were all slaves! Therefore, this 
article is clean against the Gospel and sheer robbery, for every man who con- 
siders his body thus his own has stolen it from his master. For a serf can, 
indeed, be a Christian and have Christian freedom, just as a prisoner or a sick 
man is a Christian and still is not free. This article wishes to make all men 
equal and make the spiritual Kingdom of Christ into a secular external 
kingdom which is impossible. For a secular kingdom cannot exist without 
personal inequality where some are free and some are bound, some are lords 
and others are subjects.” In another passage he exhorts even the Christian 
prisoners of war who have been enslaved by the Turks to endure their state of 
slavery patiently: “Thou must think that thou hast lost thy freedom, without 
which thou thyself canst do nothing apart from the will and knowledge of 
thy master without sin and disobedience. For in so doing thou dost rob and 
steal thy body from thy master, which he has bought or otherwise gained that 
it henceforward is not thine but his possession like a cow or any of his other 
goods” ! ! BA . IV, /, p. tfg. Thus the fresh expansion of serfdom in the agri- 
cultural districts and estates on the eastern side of the Elbe from the time of 
the sixteenth century was entirely unhindered by Lutheranism (see Gothein: 
Agrargeschichte in Religion in Geschichte und Gegenwart , I, p. 2807). A legal stabiliza- 
tion of human rights did not take place at least in Germany until the time of 
the Enlightenment, and until the present day it is only from this point of view 
that this is possible. 

883 (p- 561 •) F, J. Stahl: Der christliche Staat, p. 8, the patriarchal fundamental 
theory; p. 77, the opposition of the modern principle. The continuance, or, 
rather, the reawakening by the Restoration of these tendencies in modern 
Conservatism, is described in a most interesting manner with a large number of 
extracts from the Conservative Press by Stillich: Die politischen Parteien in Deutsch- 
land, /. Stillich, however, sees in this only an expression of the Conservative 
class struggle, and overlooks the connection between this class struggle and the 
reawakening of the pure ideological motives of Lutheranism, through which 
alone it can be carried on in the name and with the energies of a .popular 
outlook on the world ; see p. 55 for the class, or as we say to-day in order to 
distinguish it from the mechanical individualistic principle, the organic 
conception of Society of the Conservatives ; see likewise pp. 8y and 2ig ; p. 143 
for the economic traditionalism which is bound up with that. 

188 (p. 562.) Cf. the presentation of this political economy by Roscher and 
especially by Oncken , 1, 226-236 : “Political economy as a specific form of the 
mercantilistic literature of Germany bears on the one hand a populationist 
character, and on the other a character of the science of State finance. In a 
‘productive* town and country population, and in a flourishing ‘aerarium*, the 
wealth of the land consists. One must also say in praise of the political econo- 
mists that they have honestly and eagerly tried to cope with the tasks which 
have faced them: it cannot be denied, however, that when at that time the 
wealth of a sovereign prince was measured by the number of his subjects, this 
mostly happened in the sense in which in our own day a landowner is esteemed 
according to the number of his cattle.** Noteworthy is the similarity of the 
Catholic and the Protestant branch of this political economy in its theological 
ethical presuppositions and its practical political results. Only the Protestant 
tendency is represented in more fullness and variety (p. 232 ). Oncken calls 



PROTESTANTISM 


873 

attention rightly to the “semi-Socialist character” and the tendency to the 
“middle class” (/>. 22 g), but he does not sufficiently emphasize the connection 
with the religious ethic. It is everywhere quite plain that the emphasis on 
peace, order, the exclusion of competition, the stabilizing or new regulation 
of the class-organization, proceed from the standpoint of the ethic of love, 
which is opposed to the free struggle for existence. The “free couise of com- 
merce” is “evil and foolishness” (p. 231). The whole exclusiveness and the 
lack of individual initiative are both due to religious motives as well as based 
on circumstances without its being possible to describe the religious theory as 
simply a reflection of the actual circumstances. It is a reaction behind the lay 
culture or civilization of the town of the later Middle Ages which is based on the 
one hand on the actual political and social development of conditions of power 
and economics, but on the other hand also on the reactionary religious theory 
of Luther about economic and social questions which is quite independent of 
the former. That the formation of greater States, with a unity of administration 
which follows with this from another point of view is progress, or the pre- 
supposition of progress, is a matter of course ; only that kind of idea is not 
consciously intended by Lutheranism, whether of the theological or of the 
juridical political 4 cind. 

289 (p- 567.) Cf. Uhlhorn , III , 315-414 . One of the chief defects in this other- 
wise excellent book is that it does not recognize and emphasize the return to 
the principle of charity as such, and therefore it does not discern the real 
reasons for this return. They lie in the failure of the early Lutheran patri- 
archalism, which believed that in the cosmos of “callings” all were cared for, 
and only provided the Kasten for exceptional cases. It is of the essence of 
the new period of Protestant philanthropy since Pietism arose that it no longer 
depends upon the organization of the State, nor upon the official activity of 
the Church, but that it organizes its charity freely from the laity and from the 
local congregations. Instead of that, in order to explain this new period Uhlhorn 
suggests that it is due to the influence of the philanthropy of the Enlightenment, 
which decidedly had very little part in it. Further, Uhlhorn rightly lays a 
great deal of emphasis upon the influence of Calvinism and of Catholicism ; 
also the fact that the opposition of the official Lutheran Church is a sign that 
it regards these returns to Calvinistic and Catholic lay activity as something 
new and strange. That in reality the Catholic principle of charity was being 
approached in this activity is shown by the way in which Fliedner and Wichern 
appeal to the institutions of the Primitive Church, as well as by some involuntary 
expressions of Uhlhorn : “There is a danger of falling into a very widespread 
habit of almsgiving all the more because the various associations have little 
or no connection with each other, and the applicant has only a very external 
link with the association. . . . But the most serious result would be if those 
people were right who say that the number of charitable associations which at 
present exist is a symptom that the historic groups, the State and the Church, 
are breaking up as in the Roman Empire and towards the close of the Middle 
Ages” ( p . 412). The similarity of these associations with the Catholic Religious 
Orders is often noted and carefully denied. 

890 (P* 588.) Cf. Uhlhorn , ///, 347 ff -364, and especially Wernle: J. H. Wichern , 
igo8. In the Commission of the Central Committee for Home Missions, Wernle 
summarizes the content of Wichern’s Memorial of 1849: “Within the sphere 
of the State the Home Mission ought to fight against the revolutionary spirit, 
and also care for the welfare of the prisoners and of discharged criminals. 
In the ecclesiastical sphere it is her main task to give to every baptized Christian 



874 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

the full opportunity of hearing the pure Word of God ; this means that Bible 
Societies, Bible Study Groups, special Missions, etc., must be instituted. 
In the general sphere of morals it must oppose prostitution, drunkenness, and 
bad literature, and finally in the social sphere it must do all that is possible to 
maintain and to save family life ; it must care for the poor and the sick ; it must 
organize Christian Workmen’s Unions over against the Communist organiza- 
tions ; it must take special care of manual labourers who are in great need and 
of apprentices for whom colonies on the land should be created” ( p . 38). For 
the reasons of failure he says rightly: “The methods of saving almost all 
proceed from a very marked lack of understanding of the true intellectual, 
political, and social distress of the modern day ; they accept the old Christianity 
of authority and the old political and social order as apparently sanctioned by 
Divine authority, and, therefore, as something which is quite natural. . . . 
Above all, they are unable to place over against the modern emancipation 
movement any great positive aim in which the deeper longings of the recent 
time might be able to find itself” ( p . 33). Further, however, ecclesiastical 
Lutheranism did not accept these proposals, which already seemed to it to be 
too revolutionary. “It is the tragic element in the life of Wichern that all his 
enthusiasm and his energy of love broke in vain on the «rock of this rigid 
Lutheran tradition. In addition to Lutheran ecclesiasticism, the greatest 
hindrance . . . was the political reaction, and especially in the fact that it 
sanctioned the Home Mission” ( p . 48). In vain Wichern tried to avoid this 
political disintegration (p. 43). 

201 (p. 568.) Cf. Gdhre: Evangelisch-soziale Bewegung, 1836. It is interesting to 
note how in Rud. Todt and his central association, Lutheranism, completely 
overwhelmed by the knowledge of the new situation becomes quite bewildered, 
believes that it ought to evolve a new social theory to meet the new conditions, 
and composes this theory under the influences of Socialism and the Sermon 
on the Mount. Yet even Todt’s State Socialism retained strongly patriarchal 
conservative features. Stocker’s work developed this latter dual tendency still 
farther, and finally sacrificed the social reform tendencies to middle-class 
patriarchal High Church ideas; Gdhre , ioj. The Kirchlich-Soziale Konferenz, 
which inherited Stocker’s ideas, went farther in this direction. The Protestant 
Workmen’s Unions also display the same dualistic point of view ; Gdhri, pp. 116 
and 1 S3. The cause of that, however, is not merely political, but also the after- 
effect of the old tradition of Lutheran ethics. 

222 (p. 568.) So, for example, the earlier Hanoverian Church leader, Uhlhorn: 
Kath. und Prot. Appealing to the tradition of Lutheranism, and in decided 
opposition to the changes in the Lutheran spirit introduced by Stdcker, he 
wishes to see the Church solely occupied with the preaching of the Word and 
he lays down as the social service of the Church : ( 1 ) the re-emphasis on the 
dignity of labour in which the modern work in factories can be ennobled in a 
Christian manner, just as slavery was ennobled in the Early Church; (2) the 
proclamation to the masters of a patriarchalism which recognizes the infinite 
value of every Christian soul ; (3) Sunday observance, the building of churches, 
the institution of new parishes ; (4) the creation of smaller and more living 
congregations ; (5) bringing under the control of the Church the very varied 
philanthropy which flourished in very different forms, sometimes Pietistic and 
sometimes almost Catholic, and the making of this charity into a definite task 
of parochial Poor Relief. Otherwise, however, the Church ought solely to place 
the Word of God upon the lampstand, so that “Christian” statesmen, jurists, 
political economists, members of parliament, manufacturers, bankers, and 



PROTESTANTISM 


875 

workmen “then freely, according to their special insight, can effect social 
reform’*. To the Church itself, this is not commanded : “The Church is only 
concerned with that pertaining to spiritual possessions, righteousness, peace, 
and the Holy Ghost, and these possessions need to be gained whatever the 
external conditions of man may be” ( p . 44). This, however, presupposes that 
those Christian statesmen, etc., will find also a social order which will corre- 
spond with the Christian ideal of Lutheranism, and that that which they 
discover will neither disturb nor alter Lutheran dogma and ethics! — Less 
unconcerned in this respect is Nathusius: Die Mitarbeit der Kirche an der Losung der 
Sozialen Frage z , 1904 ; he therefore desires a High Church intensification of the 
independence and power of the Church, and he gives the “Christian” states- 
men, etc., some hints upon what assumptions they ought to base their thought 
and their action. 

293 (p- 568.) Cf. Wenck: Gesch. d. Nationalsozialen, 1905. Naumann completed 
the process of development from charity to Christian social reform, and from 
this to a social formation based purely upon general political and economic 
causes which cannot be effected by religious ideas directly, and in so doing 
he gave the religious element back again to its more limited sphere. This again 
leads him to the tradition of Lutheranism, but with the important alteration 
that he requires a general social development which is strongly opposed to the 
main ethical idea of Lutheranism ; this led naturally to a critical and dis- 
integrating reflex effect upon Lutheran dogma and its ethic, as his Brief e iiber 
Religion shows. On the other hand, he emphasizes increasingly the indirect 
importance of the religious element for the freedom and value of personality 
in contrast to the oppressive influence to be expected from a bureaucratic 
capitalism. 

204 (p- 568.) Cf. the Reports of the Ev.-soz. Kongress since 1890, especially the 
address by P. Drews at the last Congress in 1909; otherwise, Gohre , 199-162. 
Since Stocker left the Congress and the Conservatives became increasingly 
reluctant to identify themselves with this movement, the Congress has become 
more and more a place for the discussion of all the important leading questions 
of the Lutheran ethic, both practical and theoretical ; this is also proved by the 
fact that it is now under the chairmanship of the leader of progressive Protestant 
theology, Adolf Harnack. The development of thought, which can be traced 
in the Reports, of a free Protestantism, gradually turning its attention to ethics 
rather than to dogma, is extremely instructive and attractive, but we are here 
concerned merely with the first beginnings of a new statement of the problems, 
behind which the scientific ethic of modern Protestantism only marches very 
reluctantly, and which with its earnestness actually affects very small groups. 
But at the present day, where do we find a really penetrating social ethic at all? 

295 (P- 589*) Gf. on this point Elisabeth v. Richthofen: Ueber die historischen 
Wandlungen in der Stellung der autoritdren Parteien zur Arbeiterschutzgesetzgebung und 
die Motive dieser Wandlungen, Heidelberger Diss . , 1901, p. J2: “The hostility between 
industry and agriculture, which at first (that is, among the adherents of the 
Christian Social party) seemed to lead to the support of the working classes 
against their ‘capitalistic exploiters’, has finally culminated, as the result of 
the need for labour, in an aversion to the introduction of measures for the 
improvement of the situation among industrial workers. . . . The Conservatives 
have renounced all initiative in social politics, and have withdrawn to the 
standpoint of a purely agrarian representation of interests. Traditional views 
and social relationships united them with men of that type who wish to 
maintain, as far as they possibly can, a patriarchal, dominating system of 



876 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

labour which alone corresponds to the principle of authority for which they 
stand.” Cf. also Stillich, especially the chapter Die Gesellschaflsauffassung der 
Konservativen. Always there is behind all this a certain sense of the value of the 
ethical principles of obedience and of authority, on the basis of the theoretical 
statement of the essential inequality of mankind which is not merely dictated by 
class interest, but which is connected with all the fundamental Christian and 
Lutheran tenets ; see the passages in Stillich , pp. 164-167. Further, it is every- 
where the peculiarity of the Lutheran Natural Law, to emphasize in Nature 
the inequalities and hindrances which oppose an ideal social order from which 
it derives ethical values of obedience and of care for others, instead of wishing 
to overcome and remove them in a direct and reforming way throdgh ethical 
idealism; certainly a very serious ethical question from the consideration of 
which we ought not to allow ourselves to be diverted by class- war exploitations 
of the principle. The problem of equality forms in reality one of the most 
obscure and difficult points in the modern social doctrines of a liberal and 
Socialistic nature. 

297 (P* 57°-) The Protestant idea of the “calling” is exalted in this way in 
the influential works of Ritschl: Geschich. d. Pietismus , and Uhlhorn: Geschich. d. 
christlichen Liebestdtigkeit , and Uhlhorn: Prot. und Kath. The critical voices of the 
sixteenth and seventeenth centuries which summon Lutheranism back to 
opposition to the world are here represented as Catholic ascetic, and, what is 
identical in both, as sectarian reactions which then were completed in Pietism. 
This, however, is a misinterpretation of the dualistic elements in Luther’s own 
doctrine. — That both regard the “permeation of civilization” essentially in the 
Conservative anti-modern sense is shown by Uhlhorn: Prot . und Kath., where he 
gives the advice that the question of Labour should be handled as Paul handled 
the problem of slavery (p. 46), and Ritschl , who in his Gotlinger Jubildumsrede 
(Drei akademische Reden , 1887), taught that Liberalism, social democracy, and 
the Catholic doctrine of Society had arisen out of the same root of individualistic 
Rationalism, while he claimed for Lutheranism an historic anti-Rationalist 
basing of Society upon power and force, somewhat in the sense of Heinrich 
von Treitschke, and thus explained the filling of the relationships of life which 
have thus been created with trust in God and loyalty to one’s “calling” for 
the anti-mediaeval modern civilization; this leads, then, to insight ^nto “the 
Conservative task of the State understood in the light of history” (p. 61). The 
intention is similar when in the book by Loo/s: L.'s Stellung, Luther is represented 
as the victor over the mediaeval world and the founder of the modern world ; 
the “modern world” of Loofs is possibly Prussian free Conservative or National 
Liberal of the Right. 

890a (P- 57 1 -) RitschVs Jubildumsrede has a right feeling for this special 
character of the Lutheran Natural Law contrasted with that of Catholi- 
cism and Calvinism. Rightly there also the Catholic, Liberal, Socialist (and 
Calvinist) idea is connected with Greek Rationalism, even though otherwise 
the account of the history of the Christian social doctrines is far from clear. 
We must, however, note that Greek speculation had already foreshadowed that 
difference, and had taught alongside of the Rationalist-individualistic Natural 
Law also that anti-Rationalistic positivist Natural Law; cf. Hirzel: Ndpog 
Aypapog Abhh . d. Sachs. Ak., 1900 ; also Karst: Entstehung der Vertragstheorie , 
Z- f wiss. Politik , 1909, pp. 524-928. 

800 (p. 571.) For its general influence on civilization, see Arnold Berger: 
Die Kulturaufgaben der Reformation , und desselben Luther. For the dual tendency of 
these effects, see the opinions of the good Protestant historian, H. Baumgarten , 



PROTESTANTISM 


877 

in his famous self-criticism of Liberalism ( Preuss . Jahrbb ., 1866) : “Luther’s 
almost exclusive emphasis upon the inward side of religion caused this aspect 
to predominate in our character for centuries. . . , Our Lutheran princes, too, 
had a policy, and one which was quite new and had never been seen before . . . 
the policy of moral scruples, of paternal conscientiousness, of sterling excel- 
lence in small things and impotence in large questions, of great industry in 
a narrow circle, and stupid laziness when great matters were afoot. It was a 
policy of this kind which established and encouraged the solid bourgeoisie of 
our towns, the comfortable prosperity of our villages, the success of our schools 
and universities, the conscientious industry of our officials, the seriousness of 
our science, the purity of our family life ; it has created, or at least developed, 
everything of which we may be proud, everything which makes foi happiness 
and prosperity in our domestic, private, and economic life. It has, however, 
also created that Kleinstaaterei which honours a man only as the father of 
a family, but which has no use for him as a man and a citizen, that wretched 
Philistinism which keeps our nation in bonds, that terrible habit of cherishing 
the most daring fantasies and then of sinking to the ground in despair before 
the slightest difficulty. This spirit has sucked the energy and virility out of the 
life of the State, 5 nd has turned it, properly speaking, into a sort of Kinder- 
garten, which has preserved us from all the dangers of this wicked world, but 
also from all its greatness” ( p . 456). Baumgarten then goes on to say that this 
Lutheran “inwardness” also caused the cosmopolitanism and lack of national 
spirit present in our classical literature and philosophy. And it is a fact that 
all this is connected with the specifically Christian side of Luther, but the 
question has also another aspect. Bismarck, too, whom Baumgarten admired 
for his greatness, but to whom he was opposed in other ways, also appealed 
to Lutheranism. But the Lutheranism to which he appeals is certainly not 
the definite Christian element in Luther, but his irrational conception of the 
Natural Law of power and authority, which for two hundred years certainly 
only served to support the claims of the existing authority, but which with the 
rise of Prussia were brought out afresh by Stahl as arguments against Liberalism 
and the Revolution and developed in a brilliant way; since then, in its con- 
nection with the Christian idea of sin and of inequality (in the non-religious 
sphere), «it has served the interests of a highly realistic policy of might and 
authority which allows the Christian, as an official member of the institutions 
determined by sin, to develop all the consequences of the naturalistic idea of 
power and authority. It is thus, namely, that H. v. Treitschke has represented 
Lutheranism. In so doing, however, as with Bismarck and other Conservatives 
of the modern day, the idea of power has frequently become an end in itself, 
the duty of the State to care for the Christian character of Society has been 
placed in the background, and the co-operation of the policy of power with 
the religious end of life has been left in a general way to Providence, who has 
made humanity what it is at any rate ; cf. Lenz: Bismarcks Religion. German 
social legislation, therefore, is no longer the result of a conception of the State 
which is Christian in principle, but it is an incidental use of Christian ideas for 
political ends in which that which had been separated fortunately is once 
more united. 

808 (p* 573-) On this point, see Haendtke: Deutsche Kultur im des 30 j. 

Krieges, p. 70: “It is beyond doubt that at that time from the economic point 
of view Germany was still very much hampered by mediaeval views ; for in 
what other land would it then have been possible (1684-5) to forbid, for 
example, the ribbon-loom which was so important, as took place at Nurnberg 



878 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

at the request of the lace-makers, or as happened at Frankfort-on-the-Maine ; 
in 1666 permission was refused to set up a weaving-loom such as had already 
been Seen in 1665 at the Frankfort Fair. . . .” Also in other places it was 
unthinkable that the question of machinery was made “ ‘une affaire de con- 
science* by the ‘premier confesseur et predicateur de L*Electeur de Saxe*.** 
We ought to place alongside of that the often-quoted sentence of Uhlhorn 
that the machine is in itself Protestant ! — Laveleye : Prot, u. Kath. u . deren Bezie • 
hungen zur Freiheit und Wohlfahrt der Volker, deutsch 1875, deals with Protestantism 
in general, it is true, but in point of fact it refers always only to Calvinism. 
The only points which apply to Lutheranism are the reference to the increased 
intellectualism of a doctrinal and book religion. In this realm of thought there 
is need for some much more exact research. 

807 (p. 575.) In reference to the great European “Restoration** (of the early 
part of the nineteenth century), its world of thought, and its social history, 
there is no really satisfactory work, which represents its difference from the 
modern world. Church histories in particular, which should have a good deal 
to say on this question, are totally inadequate. Either they glorify the reawaken- 
ing of faith, which to them is something quite natural contrasted with the sin 
and evil of the modern world, or they complain of the destruction of the 
beginnings of reform which they regard as the result of reactionary politics 
and selfishness. A deeper understanding of the subject is found in the brilliant 
book by Meinecke: Weltbiirgertum und Nationalstaat , igo8 , which deals with a 
different subject. This writer does justice not only to the Liberal school of 
thought (which is usually the only one to which attention is paid), but he traces 
the connection from “Stein to Friedrich Wilhelm IV, that is, the Romantic- 
Conservative branch of the idea of a national state** ( p . ig). Here also we come 
upon the reawakening of the irrational positivist Natural Law in Burke , 126 ff., 
in Adam Muller , 128 , K. L. v. Haller , 212 /., and the religious interpretation of 
the Law of Nature as the natural reason guided by God in the process of 
development ( 21 1 ), the maintenance of this idea of development alongside of 
anti-revolutionary conditions which morally are required, and which belong 
to the Christian-patriarchal-aristocratic forms of life ( 217 ), contact with the 
ideas of Darwin without giving up the religious interpretation ( 212), the 
focusing of this Christian-realistic policy, in opposition to the revolutionary 
doctrinaire policy in a Christian universal policy, a new Catholicism ( 221 ), 
the entrance of these ideas into Pietist Lutheran circles and the reawakening 
of the old Lutheran sociology, combined with a compromise with the modern 
idea of a national State, and with increased emphasis upon monarchist 
Legitimist ideas (226-232), the complicated blend of these ideas (243-231), 
Bismarck’s development out of these theories (300-313). All this, however, is 
regarded too much from the “Romantic” point of view, whereas in reality 
Romanticism merely formed a bridge to the old ecclesiastical-sociological 
ideas, and after that the Christian and ecclesiastical sociology plays its part 
alongside of the nationalistic and philosophical-cosmopolitan theories, and 
after the victory of Bismarck-Nationalism it is to-day again endeavouring, in 
quite an unromantic way, in connection with certain definite interests, to 
dominate the situation. The fact that this Romanticism looked first of all 
towards Catholicism was because it alone offered the two elements of authority 
and internationalism which seemed necessary in order to counteract the 
influence of the Enlightenment, whereas the Lutheran churches with their 
“advanced** theology, and their dependence on the State, were at first of no 
use for this purpose. Since in this respect they have gained their own organized 



PROTESTANTISM 879 

independence, they, and not Catholicism, which contains within it strongly 
Liberal elements, are the real home of Conservatism. 

808 (p* 577-) Htindeshagen , in his Beitrdgen zur Kirchenverfassungsgeschichte und 
Kirchenpolitiky 1864. , has shown for the first time that the essential difference in 
Calvinism is to be sought in this sphere ; in this book the writer counsels his 
colleagues in Church history to make the basis of their research into the question 
of the conception of the Church “the visible empirical social group formed by 
the churches and their laws of life and growth which are still too little known” 
instead of dogmatic speculative research ( IX ) ; that is, he is summoning them 
to treat Church history from the sociological point of view. “Not merely in 
Geneva, but wherever Calvinism extended it found great social crises already 
in existence, and it intervened as a stimulating but also a purifying element 
which, while it caused ferment, also produced order out of chaos. For Calvinism 
the sphere of conflict is never merely religious or ecclesiastical in the purely 
religious sense ; the Roman Catholic faith never opposes it simply as such, but 
everywhere definitely combined with dynastic interests and principles of 
government. Thus it was in the nature of the situation that Calvin and his 
co-workers like Zwingli had to take into account not merely individuals but 
smaller and great^* nationalities. Thus for Calvin also the Gospel is not merely 
an energy which saves all the individuals who believe in it, it is not merely a 
comfort for individual burdened consciences, not merely the overcoming of 
errors which are dangerous to the soul, but it is at the same time the means of 
healing all public and universal ills, the element of purification and renewal 
for larger social groups and the foundation-stone upon which this work of 
renewal must be based” ( pp . 294 ff.). This passage gives very apt expression to 
the difference between Calvinism and Lutheranism. — The recognition of the 
fact that in this special form Calvinism also contains an element of considerable 
approximation to the tendencies of the modern world (once again in contrast 
with Lutheranism) relates this book to more modern researches: Gierke's 
Althusius ; Jellinek: Die Erklarung der Menschen- und Biirgerrechte 2 , 1904; and the 
treatise by Max Weber on the Geist des Kapitalismus und die prot. Ethik , Archiv 
XX und XXL The following works also follow the same line : Rieker: Grundsatze 
ref. Kirchenverfassung , and Figgis: From Gerson to Grotius, igoy; v. Schulze-Gavemitz * 
Britischer Imperialisms und englischer Freihandel 3 1906 , and my presentation in 
Kultur der Gegenwart , IV 7 - 3 Protestantisches Christentum und Kirche. In this matter 
also, however, Hundeshagen has already been before us: “ Ueber den Einfluss des 
Calvinismus auf die Ideen von Staat und Staatsbiirgerlicher Freiheit” , 1840, also 
Baudrillart: Bodin et son temps , 1899 . — The primary reason for the growth of 
Calvinism in France and the Netherlands (in addition to that of geographical 
proximity) seems to have been its independent ecclesiastical Church formation 
and its more decided opposition to Catholicism. Cf. K. Muller: Preuss. Jfahrb., 

1 903 , and Rachfahl: Wilh. v . Oranien und der Niederlandische Auf stand, /, 1906, p. 149. 

809 (p* 577*) Cf. A. Kuyper: Reformation wider Revolution (German translation 
by Jdger 9 1904). This book is not only Kuyper’s government programme, but, 
consisting of lectures delivered at the University of Princeton, which is strictly 
Calvinistic, it constitutes a kind of collective creed of modern orthodox 
Calvinism. Otherwise in an absolutely unprecedented degree Neo-Calvinism 
is here read into the primitive Calvinism of Geneva. It is the book of a dogmatist 
and a politician, and as such it is extremely instructive ; as an historical work, 
however, it is very misleading. 

811 (P* 57®*) Cf. von Bezold : Staat und Gesellschaft des Ref-£eitalters (Kultur der 
Gegenwart y //, V, /), p, 81: “In many respects Calvin’s work is reactionary; 



880 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

he is especially sharply opposed to the Humanist artistic and natural science 
tendencies of his day. When, however, in spite of that Calvinism is here regarded 
as an actual ferment which caused the rise of modern Europe, this applies very 
largely to its propaganda and development outside Geneva.” The rest of this 
section will show how true this last observation is ; I would only add that the 
basis for this development was already present in primitive Calvinism. The 
earlier part of this quotation is only true within certain very definite limits. 
Cf. Arnold: Calvin , igog . 

31 a (P* 579 *) Cf. in general Kampschulte: J. C., seine Kirche und sein Staat , 
i86g-gg; Cornelius : Historische Arbeiten , i8gg; Doumergtie: John Calvin (7 vols.) ; 
Marcks: Coligny, I, 1892; Rieker : Grundsdtze Reformierter Kirchenverfassung , i8gg; 
and Sohm: Kirchenrecht } /; for Church history see in particular Karl Muller . 
The two works of Choisy are particularly important, La Thiocratie d GerUve , 
and L'ttat chrttien d Genlve aux temps de Blze ; an analysis from the point of view 
of ethics and of the history of dogma in the masterpieces of Schneckenburger and 
A. Ritschl , to which we must add Lobstein: Ethik Calvins , i8yy ; also Rachfahl: 
Oranien, I, /, igo6; I, 2, igoy ; II, igo8. The results of the researches of the 
Jubilee year, 1909, are given by W. Kohler in Th. J. B. for 1910. The following 
works ought also to be noted: the Calvinreden of the Siebeck^Verlag, the Calvin - 
studien of the Elberfeld group , published by Bohatek , and Calvin and the Reformation, 
four studies by Doumergue, Lang , Bavinck, and Warfield', finally, C. F. Arnold: 
Calvinrede. — In the research of the present day the relations between early 
Calvinism and Martin Buccr and Strassburg emerge very clearly ; this aspect 
of the subject is treated by Lang in his Evangelienkommentar, igoo , and also by 
W. Kohler: Gott. Gel. Anzeigen, igo2 ; Anrich: Die Strassburger Reformation , Ch. W. 
jgoj; von Schubert: Calvinreden, p. 141. Of Calvin’s own writings the chief are 
the Institutes and his Letters. — For histories of dogma, see Loofs and Seeberg. — 
Above all, there is a great deal of useful material in G'obel: Geschichte des christ- 
lichen Lebens in der rheinisch-westf dlischen Kirche, I, i84g; II, 1852; III, i860 ; this 
book deals especially with the analogies between Calvinism and Pietism and 
the sect-type of which there were many illustrations in the development of 
Calvinism in the Netherlands and on the Lower Rhine. This valuable, although 
somewhat unctuous book, first shows the matter in a true light, whereas 
RitschVs Gesch. d. Pietismus treats the Calvinism of Calvin simply as an imitation 
of Luther and a reaction towards Catholicism. Such a statement is only in- 
telligible in the light ofRitschl’s curious doctrine that the sect-type is Catholic, 
and therefore that any approach to the sect-type means Catholicism and 
“mediaeval reaction”. This doctrine makes it impossible to understand the 
matter ; rather, together with the Baptists, Calvinism ought to be described as 
radical Protestantism and “ Biblizismus ” (that is, a Church in which the Bible 
occupies a central position), whereas Lutheranism remains closer to Catholic 
conservatism and its institutional spirit. This has been shown in the previous 
section, and is of the highest importance for the understanding of the special 
nature of the social teaching of Calvinism compared with which Catholicism 
and Lutheranism are relatively closer to each other, and in spite of all differences 
they move within one common type. Schneckenburger, I, 6, remarks very truly : 
“First of all Lutheranism after Catholicism is the direct continuation of Latin 
Christianity, a spiritualized transformation of the same, and an actual reform 
which is connected with its historical development. In the Calvinistic church 
development the aim is not so much a mere reform and spiritual continuation 
of historic Latin Christianity as a phenomenon which in principle is a new 
formation of Christianity directly formulated from the Scriptures according 



PROTESTANTISM 


88 1 


to its original standard form.” This is confirmed by the undeniably greater 
dislike of Catholic and Old Catholic thinkers (among the latter Kampschulte 
and Moritz Ritter) for Calvinism than for Lutheranism. Quite similarly also 
Ranke expresses himself in one famous passage about the Augsburg Confession. — 
A survey of recent literature on Calvinism is given by Knodt: Bedeutung Calvins 
und des Calvinismus fur die prot. Welt im Lichte der neueren und neuesten Forschung, igio. 

813 (P* 581 .) Cf. the beginning of Book IV in Calvin's Institutes . Here the Church 
is regarded as the treasury of grace independent of the individual: “Quia 
ruditas nostra et segnities externis subsidiis indigent, quibus fides in nobis et 
gignatur et augescat et suos faciat progressus usque ad metam, ea quoque 
(Deus) acfdidit, quo infirmitati nostra consuleret ; atque ut augescat Evangelii 
praedicatio, thesaurum hunc ad ecclesiam deposuit. Pastores instituit ac 
doctores, quorum ore suos doceret Eph. iv. 1 1 . Eos autoritate instruxit. Imprimis 
sacramenta instituit, quae nos experimento sentimus plus quam utilia esse 
adjumenta ad fovendam et confirmandam fidem. Nam quia ergastulo carnis 
nostrae inclusi ad gradum evangelicum nondum pervenimus, Deus se ad 
captum nostrum acomodans pro admirabili sua providentia modum prae- 
scripsit, quo procul disjuncti ad eum accederemus” (Inst. IV, /, /). — “Quia 
nunc de ecclesia'visibili disserere propositum est, discamus vel uno matris 
elogio, quam utilis sit nobis ejus cognitio, immo necessaria: quando non alius 
est in vitam ingressus, nisi nos ipsa concipiat in utero, nisi pariat, nisi nos alat 
suis uberibus, denique sub custodia et gubernatione nos tueatur, donee excuti 
carne mortali similes erimus angelis. Neque enim patitur nostra infirmitas a 
schola nos dimitti, donee toto vitae cursu discipuli fuerimus. Adde, quod extra 
ejus gremium nulla est speranda peccatorum remissio nec ulla sal us” (IV, 1, 4). 
An individual is born into this Church as you inherit an entail ; cf. Contre les 
Anabaptistes, Corpus Reformatorum, 33, p. 322 : “Ainsi l’homme qui n’a este receu 
en l’alliance de Dieu des son enfance, est comme estranger k l’Eglise, iusques 
k ce que par la doctrine de salut il soit anient k foy et repentance. Mais alors 
sa semence est aussi quant et quant faict domestique de l’Eglise. Et pour ceste 
cause les petitz enfants des fiddles sont baptises en vertu de cette alliance, qui 
est faicte avec leurs p£res, en leur noms et k leurs profits.” The spiritual nature 
of the sacraments which Calvinism teaches thus changes nothing in the con- 
ception .ef the Church. Infant Baptism should take place in the presence of 
the congregation, but it is always a witness to the child’s birthright in the 
Church which it already possesses ; cf. Brief e, II, 34, 38, 243 , 423. In the Sacra- 
ment of the Lord’s Supper, moreover, Calvin has retained the idea of objective 
wonderful spiritual food, even though solely spiritual, in the interest of the 
idea of the Church, and, therefore, he regarded himself as a Lutheran. Although 
he lays stress on the exercise of discipline and makes the demand for a worthy 
reception of the Sacrament the centre of his idea of a holy community, he 
expressly guards against all separatist and sectarian consequences. Where the 
Word and the Sacrament are, there for him is the Church, as for Luther, and 
since it is impossible to know the inner state of each individual, no separation 
between believers and unbelievers is allowed. C.R., 33, p. 68: “Car la majesty 
de la parolle de Dieu et de ses sacrements nous doit estre en telle reputation, 
que partout ou nous la voyons nous soyons certains que \k il y a Eglise, nonob- 
stant les macules et les vices qui pourront estre en la vie commune des hommes.” 
The power of excluding individuals from communion, which is to be exercised 
by the Church, is good, but it is always only a method of punishment and 
education used by the Church, never a separation of the pure and holy from 
the Church of the pure doctrine and the pure Word, however much sin she 

VOL. U. EE 



882 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 


may contain : “Je laisse k dire qu’encore pos£ lc cas quc nous nc deussions 
avoir aucune consideration que des hommes et de leur mcurs (this is supposed 
to be a false assumption of the Baptists), nous pourrions estre souvent abusez en 
reiettant une compagnie et ne la daignant estimer Eglise k cause des imper- 
fections qui y seraient. Car il se pourrait faire tout les coups, que nous ferons 
iniure k beaucoups de sainczt personnages, dont le nombre est cache entre les 
meschants comme le bon grain dessoubs la pouille.” These are almost literally 
all the characteristics of the idea of the Church contrasted with that of the 
sect which I have previously noted (II, g ) . Cf. also the completely Lutheran 
formulas for the Church conception, Brief e, I, 6, 57, 76, 271; II, 158, 4og : 
“I know very well, thank God, that the true efficacy of the Sacrament does not 
depend upon the worthiness of him who dispenses it.” Further, the strongest 
emphasis is laid upon the ministry called and established in an orderly manner, 
without which there can be no congregation and no Church ; the ministry is 
regarded as the vessel which carries the wonderful power of the Church, which 
is independent of the personal worthiness of each individual minister ; Brief e, 7 , 
p . 266; II, 18, 47, 52; cf. 272, 357 : Laymen can never be considered suitable for 
any office; also “the elders” are not purely lay, for they are ordained in the 
same way as a minister ( Choisy , 356). From this there naturally results that so 
far as the influence of the State authority extends, only the true religion may 
predominate: Brief e , I, pp. g, 311, 344, 445 f; II , pp . 117, 200. The circuitous 
route which Luther followed in order to reach this view was not necessary for 
Calvin, after events had spoken clearly. Toleration is granted only to the 
Truth, and this toleration must predominate. The most characteristic expres- 
sion of this absolute assurance of possessing the sole Truth is Calvin’s remark 
about the “false martyrs” (the Anabaptists), although Calvin himself at the 
same time describes martyrdom as the highest witness to the Truth ; see C. R ., 
p. 33 : “Et mesme c’est ce qui discerne les martyrs de Dieu de ceux du Diable 
que de mourir pour iuste cause. Pourtant tout ainsi que c’est une Constance 
louable que de souffrir la mort, si mestier est, pour le tesmoignage de la 
v£rit£ : aussi c’est obstination enrag^e que de souffrir pour mauvaise querelle. 
Tellement que celuy qui en souffre le plus, est d’autant plus k vituperer.” 
This is a spirit of self-assurance which entirely takes away the breath of the 
modern man, but it constitutes the heart of the Church conception and of 
the dominion of the Church, the heart of the greatness of those men. Cf. also 
Calvin’s self-estimate, Briefe, I, 431 : “So far as I am concerned, my masters, 
I am quite certain in my conscience that that which I have taught and written 
did not arise out of my own head, but that I have received it from God, and 
I must stand firmly by it if I am not to be a traitor to the Truth.” He writes 
in the same vein to the Council (I, 444 and II, 67). At the same time the 
spiritual nature and inwardness of the Church is preserved, as by Luther, 
through the statement that the Church does not force men to believe, but that 
the State only compels people to lead an externally Christian life and to use 
the means of grace in the interest of society; faith is a miraculous gift 
of God and conquers only through the inner power of the Word. — The rest 
of this section will show that the Church, together with the State, must and 
will also accept and dominate civilization in general ; further, Calvin expresses 
everywhere in his views on the Anabaptists that this previous statement is the 
logical result of the conception of the Church, C. R-,33,p. g2 : “Touchant de la 
fin ou ilz pretendent, ie n’en diray que deux motz: qu’ilz (the Baptists) se 
monstrent en cela ennemis de Dieu et du genre humain. Car c’est faire la 
guerre k Dieu de vouloir mettre en vitupere ce qu’il honors (that is, in the 



PROTESTANTISM 


883 

Old Testament and through the actual course of history) ; de vouloir fouler 
aux piedz cc qu’il a exalte. Et on ne saurait mieux machiner la ruine du monde 
et introduire partout qu’en taschant d’abolir le gouvernement civil.” The 
emphasis on this objective institutional character of the Church increases with 
the various editions of the Institutes, Kostlin: Ueber Cs. Inst. (Stud. u. Krit . , 
j866) i p. 481 ; Rieker tends to emphasize the “fellowship” element in the 
Church conception more strongly than the “institutional” (p. 71) ; he considers 
that “the latter threatens to absorb the former in course of time”. This, 
however, only took place in Independency which precisely on that account 
cannot claim pure descent from the thought of Calvinism ; so long as Rieker 
abides by the Calvinistic idea pure and simple, he himself must also lay a 
great deal of emphasis on the institutional element and the agreement with 
Luther (pp. 75, 81 ff.> 8y). The “combination between predestination and a 
sectarian individualism” is nowhere completed by Calvin since predestination 
is always connected with the “vehicle” of its outworking in the Word and the 
Sacrament. In Calvin also, as in Luther, we find the doctrine that the Church 
is present wherever the Word and the Sacrament are present even within 
Catholicism (Brief e, /, 332, 37 i f 437). The individualism of the doctrine of 
predestination is important enough, but it has nothing to do with a “fellowship” 
conception of the Church. — Moreover, to speak of an element of Natural Law 
in the Calvinist conception of the Church, as does Sohm , Kirchenrecht , p. 697 , 
seems to me a complete misunderstanding of the subject; this is always an 
interpretation of primitive Calvinism in terms of modern Calvinism. The 
historical problem lies precisely in this transformation, and in this section this 
subject will be dealt with very thoroughly. 

314 (P- 583*) That in this respect also Calvin at first simply follows Luther 
is shown perfectly plainly by the one fact of Luther’s treatise against Erasmus, 
De servo arbitrio (for the meaning and importance of this work, see the careful 
book by Zickendroht: Der Streit zwischen Erasmus und Luther , 1903). For the inde- 
pendent development of the doctrine of predestination, see Alex. Schweizer: 
Die Zentraldogmen der reform. Kirche , 1834-36. For the importance and the effect 
of this doctrine upon Calvin’s doctrinal system, and, above all, on his ethic 
about which there has been much controversy, see the various leading ideas 
in Hundeshagen , pp. 301-306. Yet there can be no doubt that for Calvin this 
doctrine was of central importance ; see Scheibe : Calvins Prddestinationslehre , 1897. 
Ritschl’s opinion that the doctrine of predestination was only an additional 
element in Calvin’s system which arose out of his strict obedience to the 
Scriptures, is a strange and curious idea which can only be explained from 
the point of view of his endeavour to turn Calvin into a mere imitator and 
disciple of Luther; see his Geschichtl. Studien zur christlichen Lehre von Gott ., Jbb. 
f. deutsche Theol., 1863 and 1868; from my own point of view the agreement 
with Scotism, which is here asserted, is only due to analogy and not to origin. 

315 (P* 583*) Lob stein , 82-86. Luther always looked upon suffering as essen- 
tially the result of sin and justified by it. The importance of distinguishing the 
gratia universalis from the grace of election which softens the doctrine of Original 
Sin, accepts the fact of Reason and culture, gives room to theZ,*# Naturae , and 
generally weakens the rigidly pessimistic and ascetic features ; see Bavinck in 
Calvin and the Reformation , and also Kuyper,pp. 110-118. This side of the question, 
which is usually overlooked, is very important for the problem of asceticism 
and its relation to civilization. 

818 (P* 585.) Cf. Hundeshagen , pp. 396 , 40 1, 447 , 448. On the intellectual 
nature of Calvinism, see Choisy; L'ftat chritien , p. 323, and Kuyper, 103-331; 



884 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

the latter with an admixture of very powerful apologetic, highly characteristic 
of the aims of modern Calvinism. Schneckenburger has some excellent passages 
on the intellectual character, self-consciousness, and calm assurance of 
Calvinism ; for the fact that this led to the acceptance of Western culture and 
of Humanism by Calvinism which, in spite of its predominant pessimism and 
asceticism, is much stronger than in Lutheranism, see Arnold: Calviwrede. The 
higher position of spiritual and intellectual culture in Calvinism is also very 
finely expressed in C. F. Meyer's Novelle iiber die Bartholomausnacht. 

819 (p- 587*) On the great emphasis on the Bible in Lutheranism and 
Calvinism, see Schneckenburger , 7, pp. 16, 20, 27; Otto Ritschl: Dogmengeschichte 
des Prot.y 1908 , 7, 53-192 . Gobel, 77, 7/4, 754, 547, results for worship &nd song; 
ii8j the form of worship, which is very simple and founded on the Bible, 
resembles that of the Waldensians and the Moravians ; 7, 326 , Laski’s view of 
the Bible “stands midway between the Lutherans with their lack of constitution 
and the separatist Anabaptists’*; 311, the same tendency in Calvin, who in so 
doing “also really attained the re-entrance of the separated Anabaptists which 
since then in Geneva and in the whole Calvinistic Church scarcely happened 
again (?), and then soon also they were tolerated in a way which never hap- 
pened in the Zwinglian (and Lutheran) churches**. This ainalogy with the 
Scriptural principles of the Baptists is very clearly recognized by A. Ritschl: 
Gesch. d. Pietismus> 7, 72. 

320 (p- 59°-) For the special character of Calvinistic individualism, see 
Schneckenburger and especially Max Weber: Archiv. XXI , pp. 5-14 , in which Weber 
rightly points out the very different meaning which the word “individualism** 
can be used to cover. It may mean the mediaeval freedom of movement and 
the variety of graduated relationships along with a relative equality in the 
spiritual content of life, or the modern consciousness and sense of difference 
with the greatest possible equality in the legal and social sphere, or Catholic 
mysticism and Catholic liberalism, or Lutheran happiness of justification, or 
the self-concentration and self-control of Calvinism. Calvinism is characterized 
not by an increased individualism, but by a particular kind of individualism ; 
see Weber , p. 12 , also cf. Rieker , p. 72, and Seeberg: Begriff der Kirche , 7, p. 123 , 
who, however, underestimate the connection between the effect of predestina- 
tion and the ecclesiastical means of grace, because they think that tjie later 
Independents and the sects were derived directly from Calvinistic individualism. 
This, however, in view of its Church conception, which it borrowed from 
Luther directly, is impossible. For Calvin the Church and predestination are 
in no way rival forces, and the conception of the Church is placed within the 
setting of predestination. From the ethical point of view, however, this 
individualism always has more touch with that of the sects. But although the 
legalistic spirit, the emphasis on the will, the derivation of fellowship from 
the association of individuals, brings Calvinism very near to the sects and 
increases the spirit of individualism, this sense of individualism is again 
removed by the conception of grace which gives rise to the doctrine of pre- 
destination. Schneckenburger has brilliantly opened up this subject, and shown 
the interplay of both these tendencies. He was also the first to notice the 
resemblance to the sect, 7, 26: “The external Church has almost only necessitas 
praecepti and it very nearly rejects them quite in the sectarian manner’* ; 50: “The 
far greater significance of the institutional character of the Church for the 
Lutherans** ; 157: “The Church does not make the believers what they are, 
but the believers make the Church what she is ; this is the principle expressed 
in a very outspoken way by Vinet, and is directly opposed to the Lutheran 



PROTESTANTISM 


885 

conception of the Mother Church’ * ; 167: “It was and is always the practical 
way of sect-formation through which certain inconsistencies in doctrine, and 
more frequently merely ascetic or disciplinary discords, are resolved.” Cf., 
however, also the reverse side of this question in the section on the Unio cum 
Christo , /, 133-143 , where the removal of these consequences by the doctrine 
of Predestination and of Grace is described. 

328 (p* 593*) On this point his work, Contre les Anabaptistes , C. R. 33, is very 
important. In this work Calvin treats the conservative branch of the Baptist 
movement on the whole very leniently, only blaming them in a condescending 
manner for their foolishness and lack of culture. He admits especially that so 
far as the* demand for a holy community and excommunication is concerned, 
there is a common standpoint which the Baptists also had gained from the 
Bible, and he only opposes their atomistic separatism, their tendency to regard 
solely the moral worth of the individual, and their subjectivism which overlooks 
the objectivity of grace and their hostility to culture. So far Calvin, in fact, 
accepts the early Lutheran group ideal ( W . Kohler: Christl. Welt, 1907, pp. 371- 
377), and he corresponds to the tendencies of a lay Christian Puritanism as it 
has been called by Barge. Only it should be emphasized very strongly that 
Calvin did not to reach that ideal of the holy community from the stand- 
point of lay Christianity and the priesthood of believers, but through setting 
up a supernatural Church-order based on the Scriptures, which is of Divine 
authority. He also removed the question of appointment to, and control of, 
the ministry from the congregation, handing it over to the general body of 
the pastors and to the Council, leaving to the congregation only the right of 
protest. The lay elders also were elected by the pastors and the Council, they 
were not chosen by the congregation, and they had a semi-clerical character ; 
see Choisy: L’tiat chrHien , p. 336. Attempts at a more far-reaching congregational 
democracy were suppressed by the pastors ( Choisy , 79, 149 , 133). Certainly the 
fundamental idea of Calvinism was the purity of the body of communicants, 
based upon Pauline teaching, only this purity was maintained on ecclesiastical, 
authoritative lines, not on those of a sectarian lay religion. On that account, 
because all exclusion was effected by the State-clerical institution of discipline 
and had civil consequences, the celebration of Holy Communion was always 
an act b*>th of the municipal community and of the Church at the same time 
{Choisy, 338) . Only thus did Geneva become the “Holy City”, the “New Jeru- 
salem”, as men liked to call it {Choisy, 430, 436). This, together with the different 
attitude towards culture, is the difference between primitive Calvinism and the 
New Jerusalem of the Baptists at Munster; in contrast with Luther it is the 
supernatural character of the Calvinistic Church-order which made possible 
the erection of a stable community and kept it in close touch with the Church- 
type, whereas Luther in the rejection of that “new law” in reality would have 
been at the mercy of congregational democracy and the sect-type, if he had 
followed his earlier plans out in detail, or if he could have done so. Only in 
France, when congregations were set up which were free from the State, did 
the congregations begin to elect the elders (. Briefe , II, 469) ; for the Palatinate 
Calvin had outlined a mixed system of election ( 413 ). The election of pastors, 
however, lay always in the hands of the pastors {II, 330). Further, democratic 
tendencies towards lay Christianity, the election of pastors and elders by the 
congregation, discussions on the sermon into which the congregation was 
drawn, which indeed closely resembled the Baptist communities, which 
became so important for the Netherlands and the Lower Rhine {Joh. a . Laski , 
see in Gobel, I, 318-331, 412). 



886 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OP THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

834 (p* 594*) The illustrations of this question are in Schneckenburger , Choisy , 
and Gobel. The purity of the body of communicants as the main point, 
Schneckenburger , 1 , 64 ff.; Gobel , II, 75; baptism as an obligation, Gobel, I, 122, 
J 75ff’j Schneckenburger, I, 254. The connection between these ideas of excom- 
munication, the purity of the body of communicants, and baptism, with the 
Baptist movement, and the tendency (which was also present in Calvinism) 
from this point of view to break down the ecclesiastical spirit altogether, is 
emphasized a good deal by Gobel, I, 88-99 : “Since for other and more impor- 
tant reasons this separation did not take place, because it was considered 
desirable to maintain itself as a Church and not to become a sect, there 
remained, therefore, in all the congregations a great deal, and in some every- 
thing to be done in order to reach even to some extent the high aim of a true 
congregation consisting only of believers.” I, in, scruples against Infant 
Baptism and the oath; 113, Labadism and Pietism only opposed because their 
effect is sectarian; 211, central significance of the home rather than of the 
congregation, because the former is more capable of being really Christianized. 

836 (p. 595.) On this spirit of legalism, see Schneckenburger , I, 109-131; 
Lobenstein, 51-37; Inst,, II, 7, 6-9; here the statement, II, 7, 12: “Tertius usus 
legis, qui est praecipuus et in proprium legis finem propius spectat, erga 
fideles locum habet, in quorum cordibus jam viget et regnat dei Spiritus.” 
The law does not serve chiefly to make sin known as in Lutheranism, but it 
regulates the behaviour of the individual who has been born again ; therefore, 
in the Calvinistic Catechisms law does not precede but follows faith. This has 
nothing to do with Catholicism, for obedience springs out of faith, but with 
the strictness of a holy community ; it is combined with predestination through 
the idea of perseverance and the doctrine (which Calvin himself rejected) of 
the signs of the state of grace. On this point, in addition to Schneckenburger , see 
Gobel, II, 137, 145, 206, 215. The only analogy is the legalism of the Baptists, 
whose moralism, however, is set aside by Calvinism by tracing everything back 
to predestination. 

837 (p. 596.) On this point see the brilliant sections in Schneckenburger on the 
mystical indwelling ( 1 , 182-255). Christ as Lord and Law-giver (I, 126); the 
Lord in Whom the Church is planted (I, 136). Of course, I do not mean that 
we are here confronted with an historical influence of the Baptists, blit simply 
with the consequence of an idea which Calvinism held in common with the 
Baptists. The same consequences, the same effects. At the same time the 
difference which arises out of the rest of the assumptions on both sides is quite 
clear. It is, however, remarkable that so far as I know no one has pointed out 
this resemblance before. Choisy , certainly, points frequently to the Christo- 
cratic conception which distinguishes Calvinism from Lutheranism. 

838 (p. 597.) On the Covenant idea, see Schneckenburger, I, 159; Gobel , I, 385 , 
already Olevian in Heppe , 205-240. That this is the root of Calvinist Free 
Church development is shown by Gobel, 401; 418, the Church on the 
Lower Rhine ; 423, a voluntary Church based on personal confession of faith 
and personal obligations; 443, the resemblance of this idea of the Church 
to that of the sect fully recognized. In consequence of this, the idea of the 
germ of the Church existing within the Church ; Gobel, II, 71, closed and open 
communities ; II, 415, two congregations in each parish. Gdbel emphasizes in 
this the transition to Pietism just as Coccejus, with his Covenant theology, 
did more for Pietism than Voet with his organization of Conventicles in which 
Coccejus did not share. Coccejus has done more to break up the idea of the 
Church inwardly and spiritually through the idea of the Covenant than the 



PROTESTANTISM 887 

orthodox Voet, who only wished to help Church discipline through his 
Conventicles. 

8#0 (P* 59 ®*) Gf. Choisy : La Thiocratie. Here and in Sckneckenburger genuine 
ecclesiastical Calvinism is described ; in Choisy that of the Genevans and of 
Calvinism; in Sckneckenburger that of orthodoxy. Gobel , however, whose sym- 
pathies were Calvinistic and Pietist, points out everywhere the connections 
with Pietism, which were in harmony with his own sympathies, for which 
reason also he often detects resemblances between primitive Calvinism and 
the sect-type. For this reason his book is very instructive, whereas otherwise, 
even in Sckneckenburger , the legal and ascetic features of Calvinism are often 
attributed to Catholicism. It is, however, true that Sckneckenburger likes to 
make his subject more intelligible by using illustrations from Methodism, 
Quakerism, Pietism, and Puritanism. — For the ecclesiastical nature of 
Calvinism which remained in spite of all this, see Choisy , p . 262 : “Calvin does 
not admit that man is free ; he excludes this idea from his theological, and 
from his social system. The Kingdom of God is not offered to man to be freely 
accepted ; it is established by persuasion, no doubt, but also by the repression 
of all rebellion by constraint. Calvin does not admit that the glory of God 
consists in offering His Sovereign Will to the will of man, who accepts it 
freely or who denies it, who obeys or who resists it, who gives himself or refuses 
to do so. For him the glory of God is maintained when man bows down before 
His law in an attitude of submission whether free or forced. Sins against God 
and His Word are considered violations of the law.” This applies equally to the 
elect and the reprobate. Here is the main difference between Calvinism 
proper and every form of Free Church and Pietistic modification or accentua- 
tion of Calvinism, and also of all forms of sectarianism. — The connection 
which still exists between both, in spite of all that, is also recognized by Luthardt: 
Gesch. der christl. Ethik , II: “However vigorously Calvin tries to disclaim any 
connection with the Anabaptists, the connection with that twofold way of 
thinking (spiritual mysticism and the legalistic holy community) cannot be 
denied. And although at the beginning perhaps it was unconscious, it was later 
quite consciously expressed and made to count.” The matter is still more 
clearly recognized by Ritschl: Geschichte des Pietismus , /, 61-98, in which also 
the different attitude of Lutheranism towards excommunication and Church 
discipline is made very clear. Cf. /, pp. 7 and 96 . RitschPs argument that this 
resemblance to the sect-type is due to its French revolutionary, equalitarian 
popular character, is certainly more characteristic of the Prussian conservative 
Ritschl than it is of Calvin. The Lutheran Ritschl, who exalts so highly the 
Lutherans because they regard the Church in an objective sense, cannot even 
imagine that such things are simply Christian, that is, that they represent an 
indestructible element of primitive Christian thought. Further, in Calvin there 
is no question of “equality”. 

881 (p. 601.) For Calvin’s ideal of heroism and its conscious connection with 
Platonism (probably also and still more with Stoicism), see the section in the 
book mentioned below by Beyerhaus , pp. 153-155 . Calvin’s Humanism is cer- 
tainly coloured by the ethic of Stoicism, much more deeply than Melancthon’s 
merely Scholastic Humanism. He is the most Humanist of the Reformers; 
see Arnold , pp. // ff. Cf. also the analysis of the commentary on Seneca's De 
Clementia in Beyerhaus , 1-25. In his ethic it seems possible to discern the effect 
of Humanism and of juristic thought to the same extent in which one discerns 
in Luther’s ethic the influence of monasticism. 

888 (p. 602.) In Calvin there is no distinction as there is in Luther between 



888 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

personal and official morality. Calvin has, it is true, Luther’s formulas; cf. 
Contre les Anabaptistes , CR. 55, p . 77 : “Or il est vray qu’en particular l’usage 
du glaive ne doit estre permis a nul pour faire resistence au mal. Car les armes 
des Chrestiens sont prieres et mansuetude, pour posseder leurs vies en patience 
et vaincre le mal en bien faisant selon la doctrine de PEvangile Luc. 21, 19. 
Rom. 12, 21. L’office de chacun de nous est de souffrir patiemment si on nous 
fait quelque outrage plus tot qui d’user de force et violence. Mais de condamner 
le glaive publique, lequel Dieu a ordonne pour nostre protection, c’est un 
blaspheme contre Dieu mesme.” There is a similar passage in Lobstein,p . 121. 
But the opposition between the legal order and its spirit of punishment and 
authority, its connection with the struggle for existence against the purely 
voluntary order of love, has been quite lost. The legal order is solely a useful 
member appointed by God in the upbuilding of rational society as already in 
the Old Testament. This comes out most plainly and in an almost identical 
manner in the Calvinist exposition of the Sermon on the Mount, whose results 
are gathered up in the work Contre les Anabaptistes , C.R. , 35, in the Institutio, 
IV, 20, 17-22, and in the exposition of the Decalogue, II, 8. The Sermon on the 
Mount is to be understood in the light of the Old Testament as an expression 
of the unchangeableness of God ; Christ has added nothing,to it and altered 
nothing, but since He has not opposed the social and legal order of the Old 
Testament He has confirmed it ; all that He did oppose were the misinterpreta- 
tions of the Pharisees. Therefore even the harsh laws against adultery belong 
to the law of Christ. Inst. ,11, 8, 26: “Christo non est institutum legem aut laxare 
aut restringere, sed ad veram ac germanicam intelligentiam reducere, quae 
falsis Scribarum et Pharisaeorum commentis valde depravata fuerant.” Thus 
from this point of view the oath, law, tyranny, war, and possessions are 
regarded as permitted by the Sermon on the Mount. Also the practical interests 
of Society require an exposition of this kind ; cf. Beza’s opinion about the death 
penalty for double adultery ( Choisy , p. 185) : “Et ce d’autant que pour punir 
ce crime capitalement, il faut avoir esgard non seulement k l’impudicite, mais 
aussi et principalement k l’interest de la society humaine, laquelle ne peut 
subsister si la distinction des families, heritages et successions n’cst conserve, 
ce qui rend ce crime naturellement capital, comme expose tres bien Mr. Calvin 
sur l’histoire de Juda, Genes. 28, 24.” The story of the woman taken in adultery 
is interpreted in a different sense. Thus Calvin sees in the Sermon on the 
Mount simply the use of civil ordinances and law without personal hatred and 
passion for the objective end of the securing of the law and of the protection 
of Society (Inst. IV, 20, 18, and R. 35, p. 44). Calvin knows that even that is 
difficult and rarely happens. This is all undoubtedly practical and sensible, 
but the whole feeling is quite different from that of Luther’s ethic. The reason 
for the different conception lies in this that the ethic of Calvin does not have 
its central point in the free outpouring of love, but in purity of conscience and 
in heroism and self-denial for the setting up of the Christian community. 
Love in the meaning of Luther is not its fundamental conception ; hence it feels 
no opposition between love and law and force, see Choisy: La Thiocratie, p. 258. 
On this point Calvin himself speaks very plainly. The sum-total of ethics is to 
him (Brief e, II, 100), “that we are strong in hope and in endurance, that we are 
self-restrained and sober in the avoidance of worldly lusts, that we give great 
pains to control the passions of the flesh, that the endeavour after righteousness 
and piety live in us strongly, that we are earnest and eager in prayer, that the 
thought of eternal life should draw us upwards.” Of Moses he says, charac- 
teristically (II, 221 ) : “Whence he gained his strength, namely, because he * 



PROTESTANTISM 


889 

became firm, through gazing upon God.” The Theologia Germanica , which 
Luther prized so highly, Calvin rejects “as a prating of the devil, which has 
been made by his cunning in order to confound the simplicity of the Gospel” 
(//, 258). — In a very special way he expresses himself on the subject of love in 
writing to Renata of Ferrara (II, 470 ff.) in order to defend hatred of evil; 
Renata especially did not wish to see her brother-in-law, the murdered Duke 
of Guise, insulted, and Calvin writes as follows: “To my observation, that 
David teaches us by his example to hate our enemies (Ps. xxxi. 7, and clxi. 3), 
you say that that was at the time when under the rigid law it was still per- 
mitted to hate one’s enemy. Now, madam, an exposition of that kind could 
overthrow* the whole of Scripture, and therefore we must avoid it like deadly 
poison. For we see that David exceeded the very best men that we could find 
to-day. ... If, however, he says that he cherishes a deadly hatred of the 
reprobate, so doubtless he is boasting of his right pure ardour, which is quite 
in order if the following three conditions are fulfilled : ( 1) that we do not draw 
ourselves and our own personal interest into the matter; (2) that we act with 
wisdom and foresight and do not judge lightly; (3) that we are restrained and 
do not go beyond that to which we are called. You can read more on this 
subject in several passages of my exposition of the Psalms. Precisely on that 
account even has the Holy Ghost given David to us as a kind of patron saint 
that we should follow his example. It is, indeed, actually told us that in his 
zeal he was a type or a foreshadowing of our Lord Jesus Christ ; see Ps. lxix. 10, 
and John ii. 17. Do we then want to exceed Him who is the source of all sym- 
pathy and mercy in gentleness and kindness? If we do, woe to us ! Let us make 
an end of all explanations: we then will be content that St. Paul applies 
particularly this exhortation to all believers that the zeal for the house of God 
shall eat them up (Ps. lxix. 10 and Rom. xv. 3). . . . The method (against a 
false conception of love) is this : to hate evil, but not to think simply of indi- 
viduals, but to leave each to his own judge.” — This is an example of the positive 
and impersonal character of the Calvinist ethic. To this also belongs the 
exposition of the renunciation of revenge in Hoornbeck, quoted by Weber , 
XXI, p. 13 : “Denique doc magis ulciscimur, quo proximum, inultum nobis, 
tradimus ultori Deo. Quo quis plus se ulciscitur, eo minus id pro ipso agit 
Deus !”A similar example on p. 32. Here we are worlds apart from Lutheranism. 
Characteristic also is the passage which Beyerhaus quotes from C.R. , 57, 143 : 
“Car en cela monstrerez . . . vous que vous estes vrais zelateurs du service de 
Dieu, quand vous tuerez vos propres fibres, et que rien ne sera espargn£ : que 
l’ordre de nature sera mis sous le pied, pour monstrer que Dieu domine par 
dessus tout, et qu’il a son degr6 souverain.” For Luther the natural order of 
love (in its perfection in the Primitive State) was identical with the Divine 
Law of morality ; Calvin, however, under some circumstances makes a distinc- 
tion between the Natural Law of love and the positive Divine Law of the 
unconditional glorification of the sovereignty of God. This leads also this 
ethic back to the fundamental difference in the conception of God. — In any 
case this is a quite different spirit from that of the Lutheran ethic and also 
from that of the New Testament. Calvin finds Scriptural justification for it in 
the Old Testament, which, therefore, for this purpose he reads into the New 
Testament. His fundamental idea is the fulfilment of the eternal unchangeable 
law through the grace of election in the new Israel which is formed by Christ. 
Choisy emphasizes this fully everywhere. I would only add that without this 
Calvin’s practical work would have been quite impossible, just as impossible 
as that of Luther actually became. From the point of view of the New Testa- 



890 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

ment it is impossible to effect any direct change in the world. The whole 
of this previous inquiry has shown us this and Calvin’s use of the Old Testament, 
for all that is practically important, is only a further proof of this statement. 
Even to-day we have the same interpretation in, for example, Rauschenbusch: 
Christianity and the Social Crisis , 1904 ; in which the writer argues that the teaching 
of Jesus was drawn from the Old Testament prophets and His Kingdom of 
God from the prophetic ideal of Society, and he describes the Church as 
apostate because she has fallen a prey to the mystical individualism of the 
Greek spirit ! For all political and social matters Calvin appeals, in fact, to the 
Old Testament ; see Rieker , /, 234, 343, 393, 403. Cf. Choisy: L'itat chritien , 156 ff. 

833 (p. 602.) This emphasis on Christian Socialism above all® in Choisy: 
La Theocratic, 244 and 278. Only here does Christianity become consciously and 
systematically social after it had followed a very devious or fanatical course of 
development among the Anabaptists and the sects. Cf. above, pp . 82 and 423 . 
Also at this point we see more clearly the resemblance between Calvinism and 
the sect-movement as well as its limits. Calvinism understands Christian 
Socialism as a life-unity of Church and State ( Choisy , 230-234) and modifies 
the over-idealistic standards of the sect to practical common sense. That is 
why Calvinism and Calvinism alone has been successful c in a far-reaching 
education of peoples. Choisy , 203: “The Protestant peoples are there in order 
to show that the ecclesiastical and social work of Calvin, his colossal effort 
to realize upon earth the social ideal of the Kingdom of God, have not been 
in vain.” This primitive Calvinistic Christian Socialism differs from modern 
Christian Socialism by its predominantly ethical and ideological character, 
whereas the Christian Socialism of the present day is based upon the economic 
historical and technological foundation of modern social theory. At that time 
such things were scarcely thought of at all because circumstances did not make 
it necessary. Calvinism, however, even then was concerned with the question 
of the material economic substructure of the ethical life, and it knew the 
value of statistics. Of this more anon. — On this Christian social feature down 
to the present day there are admirable observations in Karl Hartmann: Englische 
Frommigkeit , eine Studie , 1910 ( Beilage zum Jahresbericht des prot. Gymnasiums zu 
Strassburg). This work contains a great deal of illuminating material about 
Calvinism and the sects, and everywhere it confirms the point of view which 
is here presented. 

836 (p. 604.) A number of examples in Kampschulte and Choisy. Unfortunately 
Schneckenburger gives no analysis of this. Like so many other thinkers, in this 
legalism he only sees the rigorism of a spirit which approaches dependence on 
“works”. He lays stress upon the fear of exaltation of creatures, on the rational 
and methodical systematic nature of Calvinist behaviour; and the relation to 
the future happiness with the constant tension of aiming at a goal in the future 
life which contrasts strongly with Lutheranism and its sense of security in the 
present life and its happy faith. Only he makes no attempt to understand these 
ideas in connection with Christian asceticism and its history. Also in Luthardt: 
Geschichte der christlichen Ethik this does not happen. The theologians in their 
treatment of ethics almost always discuss simply problems of form, that is, 
of the basis or sanction, and the source of energy or of religious power, but not 
the content or the aim of morality. This aim, however, in an ethic which over 
against the world which is lost and corrupt by Original Sin and wishes to 
secure the happiness of heaven, is ascetic. And at this point the Calvinistic 
ethic, contrasted with the Lutheran, is much more dualistic, more systematically 
directed towards the other life and the depreciation of this life, without. 



PROTESTANTISM 8 9 t 

however, taking away the value of this life altogether, but in order to use it. 
Ritschl , in his acute way, has described Calvinistic asceticism as “a clear 
approximation to the monastic withdrawal from the world” ( Geschichte des 
Pietismus , /, 76) ; it is the attitude of “Franciscan Tertiaries”. “So far as the 
Christian ideal of life of Calvinism is anti-Catholic, this is due to Luther’s 
influence; so far as it departs from Luther’s conception it goes back again 
into line with the Franciscan ideal of life.” P. 78 : “Ascetic holiness, namely, 
strict rejection of all worldly recreation and of all games.” The derivation 
and description of the ideas of this Calvinist “asceticism” arc, however, quite 
inadequate in this book; indeed, it is almost comic ( p . 76). A penetrating 
conceptuaf analysis has only been given by Max Weber ; see especially Archiv . 
XXI , 73. Gobel gives a mass of examples and analyses the subject less clearly: 
/, 444-448 , resolutions of Synods ; here ( p . 447) the asceticism of the “calling” ; 
“a Christian shall use the time which he still has to live in a serious manner 
(that means without pleasures), faithfully fulfil his ‘calling’, and otherwise in 
his leisure time he ought to fill the time with God-fearing conversations, 
taking great care to avoid books of fables and to read aloud from the Holy 
Scriptures and other hallowed treatises”; II, 72, self-description of the 
Calvinistic members of the Church as “Christians”, while all the others are 
called “children of the world” ; II, 47, further resolutions of the Synods against 
pleasures, even against those which the Government has instituted and expects 
to be used; II, 103: “the Calvinists are distinguished by an earnest piety and 
a strict morality, by a careful observance of the First Table of the Law, by 
great honesty and sobriety, especially in relation to public pleasures (dances, 
Church consecrations, shooting festivals, banquets, theatres), and through the 
frugality and order, industry and honesty which is connected with that way 
of living.” The characteristic element is everywhere unlimited industry with 
solely spiritual recreation, the cutting down of the sense-life to the unavoidable 
minimum, but without bodily injury or mortification, the purely utilitarian 
treatment of all secular things as mere means and the exclusion of all that is 
earthly from this aim, the methodical and systematic discipline and direction 
towards a final end in the other life. In all these things Lutheranism is much 
more lax, spontaneous, instinctive, and, above all, less logical. The attitude of 
Lutheraiysm in these things is, above all, one of absence of theory and lack 
of logic, just as its whole ethic with its repetition of justification is not directed 
towards a logical end, but towards the enjoyment of the salvation offered us in 
Christ in each experience. Schneckenburger has developed this latter point in a 
very striking way; see also my review of Hoennicke in GGA., 1902. It is true that 
Lutheranism knew sufficient about denial of the world; cf. these words of 
Luther quoted by Schneckenburger : “Weeping goes before works, and suffer- 
ing is a greater thing than all we do.” The question is, “Sese passibilem Deo 
praestare,” man must become clay in the hands of God who will mould him. 
Even where in the older books of doctrine good works are specified, he only 
knows “abnegatio sui, toleratio crucis” and “precatio” (/, 140) ; this passage 
shows at the same time the difference between Lutheranism and the active 
asceticism of Calvinism. The idea of “intramundane asceticism”, which is 
here used, is already found in G obel, III , 334 : “The Roman Catholic external 
renunciation of the world and external system of sanctification contrasted 
with the Evangelical inward overcoming of the world and joy and peace in 
believing.” This simply means the same thing expressed by Weber and myself 
as the opposition between an asceticism apart from or within the world, which, 
however, it is easier for a Pietist to understand and value than for a rigid 



892 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Churchman like Ritschl or even a Rationalist like Rachfahl. — Further, see 
the article entitled Askese ( geschichtlich ) by Heussi in Schiele's Lexikon , which 
follows my point of view. The article entiled Askese (ethisch), by Scheel at least 
instinctively distinguishes the two main tendencies which I discern of the 
metaphysical and the disciplinary kind of asceticism; otherwise he has not 
recognized sufficiently the special character of Christian asceticism; the 
asceticism of Buddhism, Neo-Platonism, of fanatical and ritual cults, is some- 
thing quite different. Christianity, when it found that the world was going to 
last and that it must renounce the idea of the miraculous coming of the 
Kingdom of God, was obliged necessarily to transfer the spirit of tension 
directed towards the other world to another part of its world of feeling. Thus 
its asceticism arose, but it was a Christian asceticism, and it is always important 
to distinguish clearly between its own nature and the various influences 
from outside which have affected it (from Neo-Platonism, paganism, etc.). 
Scheel , from his modern immanental standpoint, questions whether Pro- 
testantism is justified in retaining the conception of asceticism at all ; he says, 
however: “I have not been able to find a sure opinion about asceticism in 
general which would correspond with its fundamental religious and ethical 
convictions.’ * Certainly, and for good reasons. “Intramuiedane asceticism” 
is, indeed, from both points of view, Lutheran and Calvinistic, not so easy to 
justify, and yet in both confessions its main ideas are present. Here the resolute 
dualism of Catholicism is easier to justify. The inner complication of Pro- 
testantism, its position between Immanence and Transcendence, between a 
pessimism which regards the whole world as lost in sin and the acceptance of 
the world, emerges clearly particularly in its idea of asceticism. That is why 
it is so difficult to conceive this idea clearly. Where, however, within Protes- 
tantism asceticism is clearly emphasized and required, there appears the 
dangerous element which this important factor contains by reason of its 
indefinite character. The tendency of asceticism within Protestantism is 
always towards breaking away from the Church, whether in the sectarian or 
the mystical and idealist sense, since asceticism in Protestantism is not placed 
under the control of the Church or of a religious order, but it is an entirely 
voluntary matter or the personal duty of the individual. — The latter anti- 
authoritative effect of asceticism (Max Weber: Archiv. XXI , 65 ff . , 99), has been 
recognized pre-eminently by Ritschl . Thus actually in Calvinism it leads to 
Pietism, as Ritschl rightly discerns. Ritschl 1 s own conception of Lutheranism 
as a glorification and moulding of the world in one’s “calling”, made possible 
through trust in God and the happiness of justification, is certainly a highly 
modernized Lutheranism which allows the dualistic ascetic and pessimistic 
elements in trust in God, that is, in truth under the influence of modern ideas 
of Immanence, to disappear. That which he regards as the heart of Lutheran, 
and therefore of genuine, Christianity, namely, trust in God, which is based 
upon the ecclesiastical objective means of grace, and which makes possible both 
different degrees of active holiness and adaptation to the world in popular 
Christianity, docs not occupy in any sense a prominent place in the early 
sources, and also has only been brought to light by Ritschl as their unconscious 
presupposition, which was hidden behind doctrinaire ideas. 

887 (p. 608.) Rachfahl , in his attack upon Weber and myself ( Calvinismus und 
Kapitalismus , Internationale Wochenschrift, 1909) , has felt able, by appealing to 
some encyclopaedia articles, to treat the conception of “intramundane 
asceticism” in a very condescending manner. But he understands nothing at 
all of theological matters ; I believe that what I have written is sufficient in 



PROTESTANTISM 


893 

order to justify afresh the use of a conception which must have some kind of 
name and which modern Rationalists — theological and non-theological — do 
not understand at all. When Rachfahl appeals to Loofs: Luthers Stellmg, pp. 21 ff., 
Loofs is there only opposing the opinion that because such asceticism exists, 
Protestantism must be relegated to the Middle Ages, and is, therefore, of no 
further use for the modern man. This, however, is not my view in any sense, 
as Loofs himself knows, since he thinks that if I had had more opportunities 
I would have shown more understanding for asceticism. Loofs interprets what 
I have said about Luther’s connection with the Middle Ages as valuejudgments, 
which they are not meant to be at all. That Luther “got stuck” in the Middle 
Ages was fieither the expression I used nor is it my opinion. I emphasized 
only the difference compared with the modern world as it actually is; and 
there is no doubt that in its practice and its theory the modern world has very 
little room for asceticism. But in saying this I am not giving a value judgment 
upon asceticism in itself. The mediaeval world contained many elements which 
are still live issues at the present time, and the ascetic elements which the 
Reformers held in common with the mediaeval period contained permanent 
problems and vital interests which will certainly return once more, although 
in a completely different form. I would refer my readers to Jakob Burkhardt's 
Weltgeschichtliche Betrachtungen, one of the deepest and most thoughtful books of 
recent times. My difference with Loofs is related in reality to the question 
of the unity and extension of modern thought. I regard this as a much bigger 
question than Loofs does, and I consider that the situation of the Church is 
far more serious than he does ; see my article, Die Entstehung des modernen Geistes 
in Preuss. Jahrb., 1906. In the question of simple facts about the nature of 
Protestant asceticism on the contrary, I believe that I am, upon the whole, in 
agreement with Loofs. — Rachfahl , in his second statement ( JW., 1910) Nochmals 
Calvinismus und Kapitalismus, declares that he thinks it wise to withhold con- 
fidence in my statements about asceticism until they have been accepted by 
Loofs , Kawerau , Kattenbusch , Scheel, and Lang. To some extent these men are 
outstanding scholars, but at this particular point of the definition of Catholicism, 
Lutheranism, Calvinism, and the Baptist movement with the assistance of the 
conception of asceticism, they are all under the influence of the well-known 
ideas of Ifytschl, which, closely connected with theological confessional value 
judgments, have, in my opinion, a quite wrong orientation. Further, those 
scholars themselves would certainly dissociate themselves from RachfahVs 
banal observations about asceticism {pp. J28JJ.). 

838 (p. 609.) Cf. Inst., Ill , 7, 1-2; Lobstein, pp. 79 ff. f 86 , and especially 
108-112 : “If we are to live we must have the necessary means of life. Also we 
cannot avoid that which leads more to pleasure than is absolutely necessary. 
We ought to observe a spirit of true moderation which must be determined 
by the thought that life is a pilgrimage towards heaven.” “Our principle 
ought to be to use goods for the purpose for which God has created them. 
But He did not create them merely for necessity, but also in order to give 
pleasure. He has thought of the desire of the senses since He has created 
flowers and has given to gold and silver, ivory and marble, a beauty and a 
brilliance which makes these metals and stones more costly and valuable than 
others.” “Thus, then, the best and the safest path to pursue is to subordinate 
this present life to the eternal ; we ought to enjoy life as though we did not 
enjoy it ; we must learn to endure poverty patiently and wealth in moderation ; 
we must guard ourselves against turning those things which are the means of 
this life into hindrances for the eternal life. Secondly, we must beware against 



894 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

thinking too much of earthly goods ; this tendency shows itself both in the 
flight from poverty and lowliness as in honour and desire for gain. Thirdly, we 
must always remember that we have to give an account of our use of earthly 
goods. Finally, God wishes us in all the deeds of our life to regard our ‘calling* 
in order to judge our actions by this standard and to orientate our lives by it.** 
I give the following extract from a sermon in which science and art are treated 
according to these principles : “Quand un homme sera le plus exquis en science 
qu*on sauroit imaginer, si faut-il que nous apprenions de nous humilier, et 
que toute hautesse soit mise bas, que le savoir humain que Dieu nous aura 
donn6 pour lui servir, soit assujett6& sa parole.** It is the same with eloquence. 
“Vray est que tous les deux procedent de la pure bont6 de Dieu. Mdis si faut-il 
venir 1 k, que celui qui sera parvenu k la vraye clart6 celeste, die, Je suis tien, 
Seigneur ; et tout ce que tu m*as donn£, aussi vient de toy : que tu le revives 
dono sur tout : puisque tu m’as fait la grace de estre instruit par ta parole, fay 
que tout le reste rende l’honneur et l’hommage tel que il appartient k ceste 
science admirable, que j*ai apprinse en ton escole. . . . Dieu a ressuscite les 
sciences humaines qui sont propres et utiles k la conduite de nostre vie, et, 
en servant k nostre utility, peuvent aussi servir k sa gloire. . . . Nulle bonne 
science n’est repugnante k la crainte de Dieu ni k la doctrine qu*il nous donne 
pour nous mener en la vie eternelle, moyennant que nous ne mettions point 
la charrue devant les beufs ; c*est k dire que nous ayons ceste prudence de 
nous servir des artzs tout liberaux que mechaniques en passant par ce monde 
pour tendre tousiours au Royaume celeste.** Cf. also G. Lasch: Calvin und die 
Kunsl , Christliches Kunstblatt, igog , in which the differences between Calvin and 
Luther in this sphere come out very clearly. This also reveals their attitude 
towards the Renaissance. Only when we recognize this use of earthly means 
with reference to a heavenly purpose is it right to describe the meditatio futurae 
vitae as the central point of Calvin’s ethic ; see M. Schulze : Med . fut vitae im 
System Calvins , igoi. Further, Lobstein points out that in his struggles at 
Geneva Calvin’s practice was more austere than his theory. 

344 (p. 612.) Weber's treatise in reality does not aim merely at the derivation 
of the capitalist spirit from the Calvinistic idea of vocation, but at the explana- 
tion of the modern bourgeois way of life, within which the “capitalist spirit” 
is only one element. He is concerned in the main with the modern character- 
istics of the bourgeoisie, and not with the elements which modern capitalism 
has inherited from the ancient world and from the later Middle Ages. Rachfahl 
and Kurdt have not understood this in the least. For my part I would rate still 
higher the difference which Weber emphasizes between Calvin and Calvinism, 
which has played its part in the formation of the bourgeois way of life. I would 
like to emphasize as an explanation of the “bourgeois” spirit in this later 
Calvinism still more than Weber does the setting, the exclusion from the 
official world, from feudalism, and from the right to hold large estates. But there 
can be no doubt about the close connection between the “bourgeois spirit** 
and later and present-day Calvinism. This has been made possible particularly 
by the fact that Calvinism has reduced the Christian ethic from a spiritual 
and Utopian ethic of love to one of strict fear of God, industry, faithfulness in 
one’s calling, and honesty. The difference between this bourgeois ideal and 
the feudal aristocratic world which was much happier with the authority 
religions of Catholicism, Lutheranism, and Anglicanism, and whose morality 
was inwardly entirely free from the democratic spirit of humanity (but also 
from the really spiritual morality of love), is obvious; incidentally this is 
expressed quite frankly now and again. Likewise, however, also the difference 



PROTESTANTISM 


895 

from the morality of the ancients ; before me there lies a Jahrbuch fur die geistige 
Bewegung , 1911, published by disciples of Stefan Georges, with an article by 
Friedrich Gundolf on Wesen und Beziehung , in which the Protestant bourgeois ethic 
and its secularized inheritance appear as the curse from which only a free, 
autonomous development apart from any “calling”, but out of the unity of 
body and spirit, can help the situation. Here the inconsistency is rightly felt 
even though to me the argument seems practically hopeless. — On the question 
of the Huguenots, see Marcks ; on its gradual development in the bourgeois 
direction, see certain passages in Elster and Laveleye. Its peculiar character still 
needs to be specially investigated. Max Weber scarcely touches it, and 
Schneckenbt&ger not at all. It is, however, certainly more nearly related to the 
genuine spirit of Calvinism than the bourgeois world of the Netherlands, the 
Lower Rhine, England, and America. I do not know what the position is in 
Scotland, where the nobility in particular took a great part in the Reformation 
movement; in any case, however, very characteristically the nobility finally 
went back into Anglicanism. 

345 (p. 612.) Cf. Briefe , II, 267 : “More than two years ago, in a private 
conversation, John Knox asked me what was my view about the regiment of 
women. I answertd frankly that it was a departure from the original true 
order of nature, and on that account that it must be regarded as one of the 
penalties of the Fall, as, for instance, slavery.” Cf. also II, 13. — Further, with 
reference to marriage: in the pure state of nature marriage was without 
“libido”, but “accensa post lapsum libidine . . . illam ipsam conjugalem 
societatcm in necessitatis remedium esse ordinatam, ne in effrenem libidinem 
proruamus” (Inst., II, 8, 41). — The oath is a Divine appointment for the good 
of Society under the conditions of evil which have been brought in by sin 
(Contre les Anabaptistes , CR.,35, p. 98) ; likewise the power of the sword of princes 
and governments (ibid., 78).— Further statements about the relative Law of 
Nature, or, as it is here put (p. 84), about the “results of sin limited by the 
universality of grace”, see in Kuyper , pp. 73-76, where Calvin shows himself 
entirely as a supporter of the general teaching of the Church: “Through its 
profound conception of sin Calvinism has merely laid the essential foundations 
of the life of the State, and at the same time two things are impressed upon us : 
(1) that V£e ought to accept the life of the State and the Government as means 
of deliverance which are now absolutely necessary; (2) but also that we, in 
virtue of our natural instinct, ought always to be on our guard against the 
danger to our personal freedom which lies in the supreme authority of the 
State” (p. 74). The new element lies in the second point, whose significance 
will immediately be explained. There is a great deal of material (on the 
relative Natural Law, however, only as suggestions,/?/?. 131-133) in the ex- 
tremely careful and convincing work of G. Beyerhaus, Studien zur Staatsan- 
schauung Calvins (Neue Beitrdge herausgegeben von Bonwetsch und Seeberg, VII), 1910 . 
There are some passages also in the extremely superficial book by A. Lang: 
Die Reformation und das Naturrecht (Beitrdge zur For derung christlicher Theologie), 
1909, pp . 20-22. I cannot understand how in face of his own quotations Lang 
can say that Calvin found no place for Natural Law in his system. For Calvin 
this is simply a natural presupposition, and it permeates all his arguments 
wherever this idea was present. In the Institutes naturally this takes place least 
of all. Beyerhaus, p. 66, says very rightly : “If Lang had systematically studied 
Calvin’s Commentaries, especially, for instance, the explanation of the 
Decalogue, CR. 3 2, 261 ff. s as well as CR . 57, 554 ff. (also Beyerhaus, pp. 96 ff., 
and p . 137, nr. 4 b), he could scarcely have made the assertion that ‘the Natural 



8 g6 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Law plays no part in Calvin’s judgment of legal and social conditions’, and 
his whole verdict upon the meaning of the Lex Naturae for Calvin would have 
been essentially altered.” The fact is that Lang has no insight into the inner 
structure of the Christian Natural Law and its function for the idea of* a 
Christian civilization. Hence also the quite wrong assertions about Luther, 
who also is supposed to have seen nothing in Natural Law and the restriction 
of the understanding of Natural Law to Melancthon. So he comes to make 
the statement that the Natural Law is really contrary to the true view of 
Luther and of Calvin, only in haste “for lack of a conception of the State 
clearly formulated according to the fundamental ideas of Protestantism” (p.50 ), 
it was taken over out of mediaeval Catholic theories which arose in Catholicism 
“and therefore in error”, and were then adopted by Liberalism ! 

846 (p. 613.) This point of view is expressed in countless passages. The 
doctrine of law and the Decalogue is introduced with the statement : “Porro 
haec ipsa, quae ex duabus tabulis discenda sunt, quodam modo nobis dictat 
lex ilia interior, quam omnium cordibus inscriptam et quasi impressam superius 
dictum est. Proinde (quod turn hebetudini, turn contumaciae nostrae neces- 
sarium erat) Dominus Legem scriptam nobis posuit: quae et certius testifi- 
caretur, quod in lege naturali nimis obscurum erat, et mentrem memoriamque 
nostram excusso torpore vividius feriret” (Inst., II, 8, /). “Nihil est vulgatius, 
quam lege naturali hominem sufficienter ad rectam vitae normam institui. 
Nos autem expendamus, quorsum indita haec legis notitia hominibus fuerit ; 
turn protinus apparebit, quousque illos ad rationis veriratisque scopum 
deducat” (II, 2, 22), Cf. also Brief e, II, 140. The same idea occurs also in 
Gratian. The law is unchangeable and eternal for the future ; it was, however, 
also unchangeable before Moses (see the sermon of Lobstein,pp. 59-62), hence 
this unchangeableness of God means that there is no difference between the 
law of Moses and that of the Sermon on the Mount, which, therefore, likewise 
is a perfected form of the Natural Law (Contre les Anabaptistes, CR. 35, p. 95). 
In Beza the expression is “Loy divine, naturelle et universelle”, or “R£gle 
perpetuelle et infallible de toute justice”, or “Loy de Dieu et de nature”, 
absolutely the Terminus technicus for the Decalogue ( Choisy : Vitat ckritien , 
pp. 180 ff., 294, 296) ; the history of the Old Testament as an illustration of the 
Law of Nature in the interesting record of the Vintrable Compagnie ,in Choisy , 
pp. 179 ff. This is a further reason which justifies the use of the Old Testament. — 
Cf. also the section on ordre de nature and jus naturae in Beyerhaus (pp. 66-76), the 
Stoic extension of Natural Law into the animal world (pp. 148-152), and the 
analysis of the commentary on Seneca (pp. 3ff.). 

847 (p. 613.) The main passage in Inst., II, 8, 11. Pervading spirituality as 
the nature of the First Table (Inst., II, 8, 16) : “Praecedat oportet vera religio, 
qua in Deum viventem animi referantur, cujus cognitione imbuti ... in 
omnibus vitae actionibus tamquam in unicum scopum aspirent.” Otherwise 
the division into two parts belongs also to the Natural Law (Inst., II, 2, 24, and 
Inst., IV, 20, 9) : “Officium magistratus extendi ad utramque legis tabulam, 
si non doceret scriptura, ex profanis scriptoribus discendum esset : nullus enim 
de magistratuum officio disseruit, qui non exordium faceret a religione et 
divino cultu.” 

348 (p. 613.) Inst., IV, 20, 8: “Magna hujus dispensations ratio posita est 
in circumstantiis.” Here is the place of the “naturalis aequitas et officii ratio” 
(Inst., IV, 20, //). “Libertas singulis gentibus relicta est condendi quas sibi 
conducere providerint leges : quae tamen ad perpetuam illam caritatis regulam 
(that is, the Law of God and of Nature) exigantur, ut forma quidem varient, 



PROTESTANTISM 


897 

rationem habcant eandem. Nam barbaras et fcras leges . . . pro legibus 
habendas minime censeo” (Inst,, IV, so , 15). Further material in paragraph 16 . 
It is from this point of view that we can explain the positive peculiarities of the 
Jewish and Roman law, which we would consider impossible to combine 
( Choisy,pp . 184 and 514). Thus the historical development of states and of law, in 
spite of all differences, is something which has been indirectly effected by God 
through the natural causal nexus ; it is the ancient doctrine of God as the causa 
remota of states, of law, and of constitutions : “Perinde istud valet, non humana 
perversitate fieri, ut penes Reges et Praefectos alios sit in terris rerum omnium 
arbitrium, sed divina providentia et sancta ordinatione, cui sic visum est, res 
hominum moderari, quandoquidem illis adest ac etiam praeest in ferendis 
legibus et judiciorum aequitate exercenda” (Inst., IV, so, 4). “Quodsi non in 
unam dumtaxat civitatem oculum defigas, sed universum simul orbem 
circumspicias ac contempleris vel aspectum in longiora saltern regionum spatia 
diffundas, comperies profecto divina providentia illud non abs re comparatum, 
ut diversis politiis regiones variae administrentur ,, (Inst., IV, so, 8). The 
“institution of the government by God” is thus — apart from the supernatural 
history of Israel — as in Luther, always conceived as mediated by Providence 
and that means the natural causal nexus. It is the Stoic doctrine of Providence 
and of the cosmos of the political and social world (see Beyerhaus , pp. 3, 71, iog, 
6s, is?). Thus the apparent positive law goes back to Providence and the 
Law of Nature: “Solent plerique nimis scrupulose inquirere quo quisque jure 
adeptus sit imperium : atqui hoc solo contentos esse decet, quod videmus eos 
praesidere” (CR., 83, 344). In this the historical and Natural Law point of 
view is united. 

349 (p. 613.) Passive obedience to the point of suffering : Briefe, II, 14, 64 ; also 
Inst., IV, so, 1, and so, 35, especially so, 37: “Nunquam in animum nobis 
seditiosae illae cogitationes venient, tractandum esse pro meritis regem”, or 
“nihil refert, qua sit apud homines conditione, cujus gentis legibus vivas : 
quando in rebus istis minime situm est Ghristi regnum.” Greatest respect for 
the Government (Briefe, I, si 3; II, 80, iq8, sso, 367) , advantage of the Reforma- 
tion that it supports the Government more than the Papists (II, 134). Lobstein, 
104. Treatment of the masses in Luther’s style; Choisy , 330: “le peuple, qui 
est une beste farouche et dangereuse”, p. 33s: “une beste k plusieurs testes”. 
Frugality as an ideal of life (Inst., II, 8, 46). A main interest and favourite 
expression of Galvin is the cogere in ordinem (see Beyerhaus, p. 63 ) ; passive 
obedience and the exclusion of the mediaeval doctrine of popular sovereignty 
(p. 97) ; but also a gradual modification of this doctrine of passive obedience 
and increasing rationalism (pp. 133-139). In this there is reflected only the 
inner contradiction within his whole theology, which on the one hand recog- 
nizes to a great extent the rationalism of the Lex Naturae, and on the other hand 
asserts the irrational character of the Divine Will. Calvin can say on the one 
hand “ut voluntas ejus sit pro lege et pro ratione et pro summa justitiae 
regula” (Beyerhaus, 63, CR., 68, 683) ; on the other hand he is able to identify 
the law of revelation and the law of reason. Under the influence of the first 
idea all government seems to be simply appointed by God, and the whole 
duty of subjects seems to consist in the exercise of self-humiliation ; under the 
influence of the second idea the authorities are bound by the Law of Nature, 
and they are to be controlled by those who have called them to their office, 
even to the extent of the complete removal of the idea of sovereignty from the 
Government. This discord goes right through Calvin’s teaching ; as time went 
on, however, the conception of the State became more rational (Beyerhaus, p. 88). 

VOL. n. FF 



898 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

350 (p. 613.) A harsh expression of opinion about the State in the Augustinian 
and Lutheran sense (cf. above, pp . 566-568) we seek in vain. Everywhere and 
directly ? ffcis regarded as a Divine institution. It is “sancta Dei ordinatio et 
donum ex eorum genere, quae mundis munda esse possunt” ( Inst ., IV, so, 19). 
It belongs to the absolutely necessary means of human existence : “Sin ita est 
voluntas Dei, nos, dum ad veram pietatem adspiramus, peregrinari super 
terram, ejus vero peregrinationis usus talibus subsidiis indiget; qui ipsa ab 
homine tollunt, suam illi eripiunt humanitatem’* (IV, so, s). The State is 
only considered from the point of view of its positive rational service to the 
Church and Society. Here Calvin is speaking as a lawyer and a practical man, 
in contrast with Luther, who was a monk and an idealist. — With reference to 
property there are traces of certain specific Scholastic ideas. Cf. Beyerhaus, 76. 
They are, however, of little practical significance. The Institutio says, simply : 
“Sic enim cogitandum est, unicuique evenisse, quod possidet, non fortuita 
sorte, sed ex distributione summi rerum omnium Domini* * ; thus, property is 
regarded as a Divine institution, as well as the legal system which safeguards 
property (CR., 35, p. 87). In his discussions with the Anabaptists, where one 
might expect an explanation of primitive communism, he only says : “De ce 
qu’aucuns d’entre eux ont tenu touchant la communaut£ des biens, item 
qu’un homme peut avoir plusieurs femmes et mille autres absurdites : je me 
d6porte d*en toucher. Car eux mesmes, estant confuz en leur follies, s’en sont 
retire tout bellement pour la piupart” (CR., 35, p. 103 ). He considers the 
Baptists well-meaning fools who do not know the world, and are arrogant 
expounders of the Bible, who follow their popular fantasies. “Je demande & ces 
bons docteurs, que deviendra le monde !** (CR., 35, pp. 87 and 92) ; and if they 
think that among true Christians law and authority are unnecessary Calvin 
says simply: “e’est une resverie!” Practical life is impossible without the order 
of the State and of law, since there are so many unavoidable errors and obscuri- 
ties in life, even when there is nothing wrong. For the way in which the State 
(without sin) is supposed to have developed as a patriarchal world empire, 
cf. Kuyper, p. 73. The fact that Calvin saw no practical significance in the com- 
munism of the Primitive State is connected with his whole change of the point 
of view of the ethic of love into an ethic of the glorification of God, and it is 
of great significance for his rationalism of the formation of the State and of 
Society, although it is little noted. 

361 (p. 614.) The meaning of the First Table, Inst., II, 8 , 16: “Pura sit ergo 
conscientia vel ab occulissimis apostasiae cogitationibus, si religionem nostram 
Deo approbare libet. Siquidem integram et incorruptam divinitatis suae 
gloriam non externa modo confessione requirit, sed in oculis suis, qui abditis- 
simas cordium latebras intuentur.” The meaning of “spirituality**, II, 8, 6: 
“Paulus affirmans legem esse spiritualem significat non modo animae, mentis, 
voluntatis obsequium exigere, sed requirere angelicam puritatem, quae 
omnibus carnis sordibus abstersa nihil quam spiritum sapiat.’* This is a quite 
different meaning for “spirituality** than that in vogue among the Lutherans, 
for whom the antithesis is spirit and law, love and rights (see above, pp. 494, 
497 > 5 * 6 )- 

853 (p. 615.) Examples of this State Rationalism, which proceeds not from 
popular sovereignty but from the idea of the purpose of the State, and therefore 
finally involves the ethical, philosophical, Christian, and also the legal 
obligation of the Government to the solus publico and, further, the advocacy of 
the Church will be found in Beyerhaus, pp. 69, 95-97 , IS3-1S9. The essence of 
authority is to measure all by this standard — “ad Dei cultum tuendum et 



PROTESTANTISM 


899 

promovendum ct populi totius commodum et utilitatem procurandam (7*5)” ; 
all this is best guaranteed by a written constitution ( 123 ). This is something 
quite different from Luther’s conception of authority (see above, ppQ&i~532)* 

864 (p. 616.) There are examples of this subject in the very condensed 
twentieth chapter of Book IV; see especially the famous passage ( paragraph 31) 
in which Calvin declares that a moderately aristocratic republic is the State 
form which approximates most closely to the ideal of Natural Law. Hence 
Providence has endowed most States with such organs in the course of the 
historical process: “quales olim erant, qui Lacedaemoniis erant oppositi 
regibus Ephori aut Romanis consulibus Tribuni plebis aut Athenicnsium 
senatui demarchi, et qua etiam forte potestate, ut nunc res habent, funguntur 
in singulis regnis tres ordines, cum primarios conventus peragunt” ( e.g . the 
German estates of the Empire and the States General in France). Of these 
magistrats infbrieurs it is said : “illis ferocienti regium licentiae pro officio inter- 
cedere adeo non veto, ut, si regibus impotenter grassantibus et humili plebeculae 
insultantibus conniveant, eorum dissimulationem nefaria pcrfidia non carere 
affirmcm, quia populi libertatem, cujus se Dei ordinatione tutores positos 
norunt, fraudulenter produnt.” In this we see the compromise between Luther’s 
authoritarian way of thinking, which Calvin fully shares, with his rational 
ideal of Society which secures the claims of the individual. For the constant 
criticism of State and of Society in its aim and purpose which this produced, 
see Choisy, pp. 493 ff. ; Beyerhaus , pp. 108-130. — Kuyper also quotes some charac- 
teristic words of Calvin: “Haec maxime optabilis est libertas, non cogi ad 
parendum quibuslibet, qui per vim impositi fuerunt capitibus nostris, sed 
electiionem permitti, ut nemo dominetur, nisi qui probatus fuerit” ; and p. 77 : 
“Ye people to whom God has given liberty to elect your own rulers, see to it 
that ye do not use this favour unwisely by electing worthless persons and 
enemies of God to the highest posts of honour.” That is a rational Natural Law 
which must lead finally to laying on the Government the obligation of observing 
the laws in as nearly an ideal way as possible, as, indeed, Calvin co-operated 
in this sense in the endeavour to observe the political laws of Geneva. It is a 
germ of constitutionalism, as Kuyper , p. 89 , rightly points out and Beyerhaus 
confirms. 

366 (p. 617.) The examples for this are given in great detail in both Choisy’s 
books. It also permeates the whole tradition of the Calvinistic ethic in its varied 
and independent development. Even in the eighteenth century Lampe teaches 
in his ethic : “Finis, in quern ipse Deus mundum conservat, est ecclesiae con- 
servatio et electorum salus. Si salus singulorum est rei publicae finis, turn liquet, 
quod quo perfectior est salus, ad quam leges societatis civilis tendunt, eo 
perfectior sit ipsa rei publicae forma. Salus temporalis ct acterna ita sibi 
invicem sunt innexae, ut ilia absque hac inanis umbra sit.” Luthardt: 
Geschichte der Ethik , II, 219. Here also we must observe the spirit of utilitarian 
individualism. 

856 (p. 617.) The conception of a fundamental theory of this kind was 
expressly formulated by Calvin himself, since in his discussion of the Fifth 
Commandment he describes the sociological relation of the family with its 
authorities and the spiritualizing of authority as the fundamental common 
ratio which lies at the basis of all other social relationships : “Quoniam hoc 
de subjectione praeceptum cum humani ingenii pravitate valde pugnat 
(quod, ut est celsitudinis appetentia turgidum, aegre se subjici sustinet) ea, 
quae natura maxime amabilis atque minime invidiosa superioritas, in exemplar 
proposita est, quia facilius animos nostros emollire et inflectere ad submissionis 



900 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

consuetudinem poterat. Ad omnem enim legithnam subjectionem ab ea, quae 
facillima est toleratu, nos paullatim, assuefacit Dominus : quando est omnium 
cadem ratio. Siquidem quibus attribuit eminentiam, quatenus ad earn tuendam 
necesse est, suum cum illis nomen communicat. In unum ipsum ita conveniunt 
Patris, Dei ac Domini tituli, ut, quoties unum aliquem ex iis audimus, 
majestatis illius sensu animum nostrum feriri oportcat. . . . Quapropter 
ambiguum esse non debet, quia hie universalem regulam statuat Dominus: 
nempe prout quemque novimus esse nobis ejus ordinatione praefectum, ut 
ipsum reverentia, oboedientia, gratitudine et quibus possumus officiis prose- 
quamur. Nec interest, disquirere an indigni sint, quibus honor iste deferatur ; 
nam qualescunque sint tandem, non sine Dei Providentia hunc locum assequuti 
sunt” (Inst., II, VIII, 33). This looks as though it were the same as the patri- 
archalism of Lutheranism developed from the ideal of the family. Only the 
continuation shows that this is meant somewhat differently: “Sed istud etiam 
obiter annotandum, quod illis obedire nonnisi in Domino jubemur : neque id 
obscurum est ex jacto prius fundamento : praesident enim eo loco, in quern 
erexit eos Dominus. . . . Quae ergo submissio illis exbibetur, ad suscipiendum 
summum ilium Patrem grad us esse debet. Quare si in legis transgressionem 
nos instigant, merito turn non parentis loco nobis habendi runt, sed extranei, 
qui nos a veri patris obedientia subducere conantur. Sic de principibus, 
dominis et universo superiorum genere habendum. Indignum enim et absonum 
est, ut ad deprimendam Dei celsitudinem eorum eminentia polleat, quae, ut 
ab ilia pendet, ita in illam diducere nos debet” (Inst., II, VIII, 38). An all- 
round description of the nature of Society and of the relation of the individual 
members to each other, see Inst., II, VIII, 46 : ‘‘Honest gain without desire for 
riches; the support of all in the enjoyment of their rightful possessions and, 
as far as possible, avoidance of strife with deceitful and faithless men, even at 
the cost of one’s own loss; in cases of need the utmost readiness to help; 
correctness and strictness in keeping all legal obligations ; obedience to legal 
authority ; the obligation of all authorities to consider the welfare of those who 
are under their protection with a constant consciousness of their responsibility 
in the sight of God ; duties of the clergy in dogmatic and ethical instruction 
and good example ; trust and obedience of the people to the clergy ; mild but 
authoritative education of children, respect of youth for age; friendly and 
understanding counsel to youth by age; willing and cheerful obedience of 
servants for the sake of God; brotherly and considerate attitude of masters 
towards their servants ; each individual first occupied with the endeavour to 
fulfil his own duties ; finally, constant looking up to and sense of responsibility 
of all towards the Divine law-giver.” 

857 (p. 618.) This is the very important contribution of Ritschl to the 
understanding of Calvinism. From this point of view he has absolutely corrected 
the mystical individualism of Lutheranism and has tried to support Lutheran- 
ism by means of the Calvinistic idea of the Church ; this also is an example of 
the increasing importance of Calvinism at the present day ; cf. Rechtfertigung und 
Vtrsohnung*, I, pp. 203-216 : “In this Calvin has saved a principle which Luther 
in his original right feeling of the reciprocity of the idea of justification with 
life in the congregation of the faithful placed in contrast to the erroneous 
structure of the Roman Catholic Sacrament of Penance and its ecclesiastical 
system(?)” (p. 216). It would, however, be more true to refer this contrast to 
a certain mystical tendency of Luther which led him to treat the individual 
in isolation ; in his early years this was one of Luther’s predominating ideas ; 
as time went on, however, it receded into the background and the idea of the 



PROTESTANTISM 


901 

Church took its place, but the effects of the earlier ideas are still operative in 
Lutheranism as a whole. 

360 (p. 620.) The inequality continues in the other life, as Calvin argues 
from 1 Cor. xv. 41-42 (Brief e, II, 66). The higher position a man occupies 
the more is he bound to endure martyrdom (II, p. 277). Cf. also Troeltsch : 
P.raedestination , Ch. W., 1907. — There are also characteristic passages in Beyer - 
haus , 99 : “We ought to know ‘que d’autant plus qu’un homme sera eslev6 il 
est oblig6 aussi et k Dieu et k ceux sur lesquels il preside comme il n’y a nulle 
preeminence sans charge, voir sans servitude*. The sphere of these moral 
duties in which this ‘servitude honorable* ought to exercise itself is placed in 
the comprehensive conception of the common weal which corresponds to the 
eudaemonistic State theories of the Ancient World.’* P. 139: “This dominion 
of individual viri maximi, which he regards as the original form, is described 
in the following words : ‘mediocris status hominum, ut si qui aliis praessent, 
non tamen dominarentur, nec sibi regium imperium sumerent, sed dignitate 
aliqua contenti civilem in modum regerent alios et plus autoritatis haberent 
quam potentiae* ** ( CR.,51 , 159). Example, Noah. This situation which Calvin 
describes as vetustissimus mundi status on that account enjoys God’s special 
favour because it Corresponds to the demands of a moderata administratio , that is, 
on the side of the Government it preserves the aequalitas cum minoribus , on the 
side of the subjects a willing spirit (sponte magis eos reverabantur quam imperio 
coacti). This aristocratic form of government “was first broken through by 
the ambition of Nimrod : he is the archetype of the tyrant, his name hence- 
forward is a byword.” — This blend of aristocracy and masterfulness with the 
free initiative of each responsible individual is a permanent characteristic of 
the peoples which have been educated or influenced by Calvinism ; they are 
remote from the equalitarian Latin democracy of Rousseau’s school ; indeed, 
in this respect Rousseau was in no wise a disciple of Calvin, although people 
often tried to make him one. This is the reason why in England the Socialism 
of self-help co-operative societies and trade unions provided the first outlet for 
these ideas, and therefore genuine social democracy could only make headway 
with difficulty. In America also the slow progress of Socialism must also be due 
to this education in self-help. It is, however, true that even there this difference 
is being increasingly nullified by the effects of industrial capitalism of the 
present day, which are everywhere the same. — Kuyper considers this idea from 
all sides, and he sees in Calvinism the great modern principle of civilization. 
For the contrast between the American and the French Revolution, see this 
expression of Hamilton in Kuyper , p. 80: “The principles of the American and 
the French Revolution resemble each other about as much as the quiet Puritan 
house-mother resembles the adulterous wife in a scandalous French novel.” 
In the same book (p. 78) the contrast between the French and the English 
Revolution is thus expressed by Burke : “Our Revolution and that of France 
are just the reverse of each other in almost every particular and in the whole 
spirit of the transaction.” — Gladstone also says to Ruskin : “I am a firm believer 
in the aristocratic principle, the rule of the best. I am out and out inegalitarian. 

. . . How are you to get the rule of the best? Freedom is the answer” ( Morley , 
Gladstone's Life , II, 582). For Gladstone the highest virtues are self-command, 
self-control, respect for order, patience under suffering, confidence in the law, 
regard for superiors (II, 124). — Carlyle also in support of his ideal appeals to 
Puritanism and Calvinism ; see Baumgarten : Carlyle und Goethe , 1906: “The eternal 
right of the dignity of man, the aristocracy of the heroes and obedience, that is, 
submission to the better”, this is his sociological ideal. The idea of equality is 



90a THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

at home in the radical section of the Baptist movement, in the Stoic Natural 
Law, and in the modern Natural Law, but not in Calvinism. From those 
sources it certainly has penetrated into Calvinistic peoples, but it has never 
radically triumphed. In the book which I am about to mention by Hagermann: 
Erkldrungen der Menschen - und Biirgerrechte, on p. 77 it is said of Milton : “We read 
in Milton that all men are by nature born free. However, this freedom is a 
Protestant freedom; he calls it ‘a due liberty and proportioned equality, both 
human and Christian’, as we have seen in the American constitution to some 
extent men have not advanced beyond this demand for equality ...” In the 
same book ( p . 45), see remarks about the origin of American equality from the 
literature of the Enlightenment. Especially instructive in this respect is Held: 
Zwei Bucher zur soziden Geschichte Englands y 1881. Here the continuance of the 
Puritan conservative features within Liberalism is explicitly described, especially 
in Burke. Likewise everywhere here the connection is shown between the 
radical democratic theories and, in particular, the French equalitarian proposi- 
tions ( pp . 340-342 , 288-233 ) : “The spirit of Cromwell’s God-fearing regiments 
was still alive and active in the social struggles of the nineteenth century, and 
it was due to this fact that in spite of all passion and confusion the working- 
classes remained true to the State and its laws.” “Puritan vie\tfs which restrained 
the spirit of democracy by a strong Christian sense of duty lived on effectively 
among the Dissenters ; Hampden remained a more popular hero than Robe- 
spierre.” — The history of the problem of equality would be one of the most 
important contributions which could be made to the understanding of the 
development of European Society. It is, however, still entirely unwritten ; there 
are some suggestions in Lorenz von Stein: Soz . und Komrn.,pp. 3-128. 

361 (p. 621.) Cf. the presentation of the fundamental theory in Choisy: 
Udtat chritien , pp. 483 ff. : “Calvinism is animated by a great spirit of equality, 
of justice, and of social solidarity. The person and the activity of man being . . . 
immediately dependent on God and His Word, it follows that all men are 
equally obliged to obey God and are equal before His law. No one is capable of 
doing good apart from a gift of God, a communication of His Spirit. Since 
things are so, no man of himself has the right to dominate over others. Authority 
belongs to God alone, and there is no respect of persons before God. This 
fundamental equality before God and His Law results in the authority of 
parents over their children, of magistrates over their subjects, and even of 
men of science and of talent over those who do not possess these gifts ; this 
authority does not belong actually to those who exercise it : it belongs to God, 
who exercises it through them. In consequence it will be suspended as soon as 
they abuse it or use it contrary to the Will and the Counsel of God. Also at 
Geneva the Ordinance takes in hand the protection of the rights of children 
against unjust or negligent parents ; and the ministers defend the cause of the 
people and its rights over against the magistrate, and the Compagnie and the 
Consistoire constitute themselves the champions of justice, of the equality of all 
before the law ; they exact the punishment of highly placed culprits, of persons 
of quality, just as they do that of obscure and uninfluential culprits. However, 
if the Calvinist spirit is a spirit of justice and equality, that does not mean a 
spirit which abolishes all distinctions; it recognizes natural differences, 
Providential inequalities, special gifts, exceptional vocations, extraordinary 
talents. These inequalities, however, do not constitute from the Calvinistic point 
of view rights for those who enjoy them, but they constitute obligations of 
service. Calvinism has given to men of every kind the sense of their solidarity 
in their moral obligations and in their responsibility towards God.” Further, 



PROTESTANTISM 


903 

for the sense of individualism within this solidarity, see Choisy : La Thiocratie , 
p. 279 : “Also genuine Calvinists possessed to a high degree the sense of responsi- 
bility, the spirit of initiative, the need for veracity, and the moral energy of the 
will and full self-command.’ * Descriptions of the fundamental theory, of the 
“relation between individuals”, also in Kvyper> pp. 19-24. Here, however, 
there is an exaggerated emphasis upon the democratic results : “Their endeavour 
was to look first at God and then at their neighbour; this was their mood, 
their spiritual habit, which was created by Calvinism, and only from this 
devout reverence for God in which all were in the Presence of God did there 
develop a consecrated democratic sentiment. This means that all, whether 
man or woman, rich or poor, strong or weak, talented or ignorant, have no 
personal claims at all, all are God’s creatures and lost sinners; this means, 
therefore, that both as an individual and as a people, both before God and in 
all human relationships, we are all on the same level, and no other difference 
between human beings ought to exist excepting in so far as God has given to 
one a higher position than another or more gifts than another, in order that 
he may give more service to others and that in others he may render more 
service to his God. For this reason Calvinism condemns not only every kind 
of slavery and caste system, but just as decidedly all concealed slavery of 
women and of the poor ; it opposes all hierarchy among men and tolerates no 
other aristocracy than that which, whether in an individual or a race, obviously 
possesses a greater amount of moral or intellectual capacity through the grace 
of God, and thus shows that he does not wish to use this over-plus for himself 
in order to increase his own reputation, but that he wishes to use it for God 
in His world.” 

862 (p. 623.) Choisy , in particular, brings out the character of a “Christian 
Socialism”, the united care for external well-being, and the moral correctness 
of each individual exercised by the authority of Church and State, the common 
responsibility of the community for each member, the social reform and 
philanthropy which was carried out down to the smallest detail, and he 
illustrates this with numerous examples from the records. This Socialism is 
thoroughly anti-Communist, but everywhere it makes the community respon- 
sible for the individual members, and in certain instances it requires the greatest 
sacrifices of public and private means. In all this the clergy are the driving force ; 
their methods are partly the penalties of the municipal court of justice and 
partly the hailing of offenders before the magistrate who dealt with minor 
offences. They demand the regulation of the price of corn, see Choisy : L'itat 
chrttien , pp. 117 , 121, 244 ; laws against luxury and sumptuary regulations for 
the sake of frugality as well as of the maintenance of class barriers and of 
decency (pp. 118 , 148 , 231 ) ; rate of interest corresponding to the business 
situation (pp. 119 , 190 ) ; paying back of debts in the same value in which they 
were contracted (p. 120 ) ; the “Blue Monday” forbidden (p. 133 ) ; statistical 
inquiries according to districts about income, need of support, family circum- 
stances, etc. (pp. 166 and 257 ) ; supervision of inn-keepers and cheap prices for 
wine ( p . 167 ) ; impartiality and correctness in the administration of justice 
( p . 196) ; introduction of manufactures in order to give employment to the 
population, and a careful selection of those who are to be sent away from 
the overcrowded town (p. 246) ; strict morality and honesty of the troops in the 
occupied territories (p. 290) ; similar points of interest in pp. 302 and 342. 
All these matters came before the Council either in the form of a motion or a 
complaint. In other matters the court of discipline acted independently: it 
punished commercial deceit, dishonest coal-dealers, a velvet manufacturer 



904 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

because one of his lengths was short by one inch, a tailor who gave preferential 
treatment to foreign customers, a surgeon who asked too high fees ; it served 
as a peace-maker and a court of arbitration; it pointed out offences which 
had been overlooked by the civil authorities, protected the weak, and punished 
those who ill-treated children, etc. ( pp . 443 ff.). “The Consistory intervenes in 
order to restore peace and unity in family life and to call individuals to do 
their duty ; it takes in hand . . . reforms in favour of the helpless and the 
weak ; it censures the lazy and the idle as well as fathers and creditors who 
were too harsh ; it shows no mercy to usurers, monopolists, or tradesmen who 
defraud their customers. It strives against the coarse customs of the t time, the 
brutality of the men and the careless negligence in the treatment of sick people” 
{La Theocratic , p. 244). It is, otherwise, clear that in this Church social policy 
the methods and ideas of the old policy of the guilds and the municipality are 
transferred to the whole commonwealth. Doumergue has proved many of these 
things in detail. The acceptance of these principles by the Church, which acted 
in common with the State and the systematic unified extension over the whole 
of Society, marks the difference between this policy and that of the mediaeval 
Church and of Lutheranism, which left most of these matters to the State and 
the guilds and otherwise undertook essentially caritative Social policy. — In 
addition there were the taxes and loans in favour of the poor, both the poor of 
the district and the refugees, which were constantly increased until they 
reached the utmost limit ; without considerable and constant financial assistance 
from outside the whole system would have been impossible to maintain in 
Geneva, whose very existence was always threatened. Vitat chritien , pp. 428 ff. 
In this financial solidarity the early Christian love communism was revived. — 
For the Christian social character as the main factor in Calvinism, see also 
Rieker , p. 68 , and Gobel , //, 123 . — For the development of this guild Christian 
Socialism into modern Christian Socialism, see Held and von Schulze-Gavernitz : 
Zum sozialen Frieden. 

398 (p. 628.) The congregational character of the Calvinistic Church is 
undeniable. For the congregation has a share in everything, even although it 
may be only through carefully selected lay representatives, as in the court of 
discipline or through the power to vote as in the election of pastors; cf. the 
sentence from CR ., AX, 9, quoted by Holly p. 34: “les pseudod-evesques ont 
ravy a ^assemble des fideles et tire a eux la cognaissance et puissance d’excom- 
munier.” But the official positions themselves are not the expression of the 
free choice of the congregation, but they are a Divine appointment, hence also 
they are not bound to come into existence through the activity of the con- 
gregation ; see Rieker: Grundsatze reformierter Kirchenverfassung , pp. 32, 1 26 ff., and 
i2gff. Thus even in Geneva the Church constitution was very aristocratic, 
the election of pastors was carried out by the pastors, the community was only 
asked to consent. The elders on the Board of Discipline were chosen partly by 
the Council and partly were nominated by the pastors. Proposals which went 
further, suggesting, for instance, that the congregations should carry out the 
elections themselves or even that the congregations should possess the right of 
discipline, were rejected and, indeed, by the pastors themselves; see Choisy: 
Vitat chritienyp. 79, likewise in the sphere of the constitution of the State {p. 143). 
Cf. the description which Calvin gave himself in the letter to Olevian, who was 
at Heidelberg, as a model for the organization in the Palatinate {Briefcy //, 
The French Church constitution of the same character, see March ’ 
Coligny, I, i,p. 331 ; about Geneva, pp. 237 ff. The Synods also were not repre- 
sentative bodies, but governing bodies formed according to the Divine appoint- 



PROTESTANTISM 


905 


ment (Richer , 158). Everywhere, however, the tacit consent of the community 
is always presupposed, and the far-reaching right of protest was at least a 
democratic element. 

870 (p. 628.) This is the important section in Institutio IV, 20, 8, Equidem - 
cogitatio; cf. the synoptic impression of the edition CR,, XXIX, p. 1105. It is in 
opposition to the earlier passage (VIII, 20, 7), where the monarchy which 
condemns all men to servitude appears to be authenticated by the Scriptures 
for the restraint of human evil. On that point in Doumergue : Les origines his - 
toriques de la declaration des droits de Vhomme , 1905, pp. ioff., see the quoted passage 
from Calvin’s lectures which plainly reflect the experiences of Geneva: on 
Micah v.*5 : “The prophet here magnifies the singular kindness of God, that is 
to say, that the people will be restored to their liberty. And, in fact, it is a most 
desirable situation when the pastors (that means here the magistrates in 
general) are elected and created by the common voice of the people. For where 
empire and sovereignty is usurped by violence there is a tyranny which is too 
barbarous. There also, where the kings rule by right of succession and of 
inheritance, it does not seem very favourable to liberty” (CR., XLHI, 374 ). — 
On Deut. xvi. 1 1 : “When we see these examples (that is, of bad kings) we 
know that it is tn inestimable gift if God permits a people to have liberty to 
elect their leaders and magistrates . . . seeing then that it is an excellent gift, 
let us see that we conserve it and that we use it with a good conscience” (CR., 
XXVII, p. 41 /). This, then, became the official manner in which the Genevans 
spoke of their Republic as of a special gift of God which made it possible to 
Christianize the State, as Choisy shows in many places. Also in Beyerhaus there 
are similar passages (pp. 116-129). 

871 (p. 629.) Every biography of Calvin shows this fact about him, for example 
Kampschulte , II, 355-357. The negotiations with the magistrate about the cri au 
peuple and its effectiveness in Choisy: L'ttat chritien. P. 55: Colladin preaches 
against usury and the Council treats that as mutiny. P. 154: Beza preaches on 
behalf of the ministers against the prices of corn, etc. P. 190: sermon against 
usury and the responsibility of the ministers : “They are bound to say freely 
when the magistrate does not do what he ought. Faults are being committed. 
Those who hear them mentioned inquire into the matter, and they reply 
sometimes in general, sometimes in particular. These matters are sometimes 
overwhelmingly manifest, and yet people do not want to see them. If we should 
be silent, what would the people say? That they are dumb dogs. . . . Do people 
think that they want to increase their power by ruining the magistrates, or 
that they are trying to foment sedition as if they did not know that they them- 
selves would be the first to suffer? But they are afraid that instead of arousing 
others they will lose themselves. . .” Pp. 251 ff. : Six members of the Council 
(under Beza’s influence) explained to the magistrate, with an appeal to religious 
duty, the necessity of declaring war on Savoy, and they summoned the Govern- 
ment “to put their hand to the matter immediately and without delay if we 
do not wish to make shipwreck of the precious liberty which it has pleased 
God to give and to conserve to us until now . . . and what would be still more 
to be deplored, expose the holy Name of God, our Sovereign Father and 
benefactor, to blasphemy and dishonour for which we would be gravely 
responsible before His judgment seat”. The people are already murmuring 
against the Council. “Good magistrates must respect the voice of the people 
and the lamentations of men of good-will, especially in free states where 
without the people they are nothing.” The right to undertake this war is 
“ratified by the desire and the consent of the whole of this faithful people, 



go6 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

which is instructed in the fear of God. ,, The Council answers that it realizes 
the weight of this argument and hands it over to Beza to be considered. 
P. 298: the ministers decide against a resolution of the Council of the Two 
Hundred in appeal matters. To that is added a long struggle between the 
ministers and the Council, which regards this as rebellion. P. 347: the ministers 
protest against irregularities in an election and support this protest in sermons. 
When the Council protested on its part, the Compagnie testified to their 
‘‘displeasure that these gentlemen do not unite themselves with the people”. 
They declare “that being informed by the people of certain faults which are in 
the aristocracy, they are constrained to remonstrate with the magistrate”. 
Further examples, pp. 996, 375, 335, 396 , 399 , 610 . P. 413: the permanent 
significance of this cri au peuple in Geneva. P. 467: a striking comparison 
of the ministers with the present-day influence of the Press. P. 469: a good 
summary: “They were admirably well informed about the material, com- 
mercial, and moral circumstances of the population; this was due to the 
exercise of their functions as guardians of public morality. The part they 
played in supervising the doctrines and the customs of the citizens brought 
them into close touch with the details of the daily life of the Genevese. This 
role of popular defenders and tribunes, or, rather, of prophets of the law of 
God, contributed greatly to make them loved by the poorer classes ; indeed, it 
made them persons who were admirably situated to serve as impartial mediators 
between the different social classes.” — Choisy also rightly emphasizes the con- 
stitutional character of the whole commonwealth. P. 498: “The political edicts 
and the ecclesiastical ordinances enacted under the influence and with the 
participation of Calvin are an authority superior to the magistrate and limit 
his absolutist designs ; it is the constitutional law which he is not allowed to 
abrogate, and which he may not touch without the consent of the people 
united in general council. . . . The power of the magistrate is limited to a right 
of control and of conservation.” In case of conflict his only way of getting 
assistance is to call on the professional opinion of foreign churches. “Like the 
magistrate, the faithful ought to watch to see that all that is done in the Church 
is conformable to the ordinances of the Word of God ; they may oppose the 
election of a minister whom they judge to be unworthy of his charge, and they 
can ask the competent authority to depose a minister who does net fcilfil the 
duties of his office faithfully” — this alone is a decidedly democratic main idea, 
but characteristically the people is still only thought of in the person of its 
representatives who have been appointed by God. These representatives are 
in the highest sense the ministers, who therefore are particularly fond of 
comparing themselves with the Prophets of the Old Testament and their 
mission to the people {pp. 72 and 123). The people act directly only through 
the elections, but those who arc elected are only nominated after a very careful 
process of selection. 

87a (p- 630.) This is the famous treatise Dejure magistratuum , which previously 
figured anonymously among the writings of the so-called monarchomachi , 
even in Gierke: Althusius a , p . 4 , which, however, Cartier (. Bulletin de la Soc. 
d'histoire et d'archiologie de Geneve, Bd. II, 1898-1904 , pp. 187-206) has proved 
from the records of the Council to have been written by Beza. I have before me 
an edition of 1580 (from Basle) as a supplement to MachiavellVs Principe, together 
with the Vindiciae contra tyrannos . The Council refused to give their imprimatur 
to this work when they realized its content, for fear of the French Ambassador, 
and thus to a great extent the work appeared anonymously. Cartier indicates 
its content very aptly in the following sentences, P. 188: “The only will is that 



PROTESTANTISM 


907 

of the only God, which is the perpetual and immutable rule of all justice (it is 
‘jus illud naturae, a quo uno pendet totius humanae societatis conservatio’, 
266 \ conceived in its application to both Tables, soy ). — The peoples whom it 
has pleased to allow themselves to be governed either by a prince or by some 
chosen lords are more ancient than the magistrates, and in consequence the 
people is not created for the magistrate, but, on the contrary, the magistrate for 
the peoples. — All resistance of a subject to his superior is neither illicit nor 
seditious. — Rightful resistance by force of arms is not at all contrary to the 
patience and the prayers of Christians. — All ought to oppose those who wish 
to usurp power over their fellow-citizens or over others who are not subject 
to them.-*-The estates are above kings. — The estates or others who have been 
instituted to serve as a curb to sovereign rulers can and ought to restrain them 
in all the ways they can when they have become tyrants. — The public good 
and the rights of the nation are superior to those of the individual, even to 
those of the sovereign. — The unjust usurper of power can become a legitimate 
and inviolable magistrate provided that he gives his free and true consent to 
the terms by which legitimate magistrates are created. — If one is persecuted 
for religion it is right to make armed resistance with a good conscience. ,, — All 
this sounds ver^ modern and democratic, but we must not overlook the fact 
that the genuine Calvinistic restrictions in favour of historic right and its 
conception have been established indirectly by the Providence of God, and 
are, therefore, regarded as having been instituted by God Himself. I have 
noted them above in the text ; they appear again and again in the whole book, 
with emphasis on the Christian spirit of obedience. Above all, this is important 
for the conception of the rise of the State and the social contract. The rise of 
the State is always in the Aristotelian manner conceived as organic ; the social 
contract of a mutual obligation between subjects and rulers which binds the 
rulers to the observance of Natural and Divine Law is contained in this only 
silently and as a matter of course. Historic law is to be recognized everywhere ; 
it is, however, only Divine when its content agrees with Natural and Divine 
Law, otherwise every robber would be obeying a Divine Law ( p . 28y). The 
mutual obligation is taken for granted with the existence of definite positive 
laws ; if they are lacking it is based upon the tacitly assumed Law of Nature 
( pp . syf^and 2y$). There is no idea of a rational shaping of the State through 
a social contract ; all that is aimed at is to assert that in the historic law the 
Divine and Natural germ does exist if this should be denied. And it is true 
only in legitimate ways through the subordinate authorities ; private individuals 
can only act as those who have been commissioned by them, which, however, 
in the end means that the private individuals also are indirectly included ( p . 2yg ) . 
When the tyrant has been corrected, then historic law must be restored, whether 
by himself or through someone else acting in his place; p. 293: “Si quidem 
cum non nisi certis conditionibus administratio illi (that is, the tyrant) sit 
commissa: minime censendum est, novas pactiones cum ipso iniri, quoties 
interpellatur ut vel priores conditiones ratas habeat easque deinceps observet, 
vel alteri locum cedat, qui de illorum observatione magis sit futurus sollicitur. 
. . . Ordines vero vel status regionis (that is, the subordinate authorities who 
are justified in resistance), quibus haec autoritas a legibus est collata, eatenus 
sese tyranno opponere atque adeo ipsi justas et promeritas poenas irrogare et 
possunt et debent, donee res in pristinum statum restitutae sint. Quodsi 
praestiterint, tantum abest, ut seditiosi aut perduelles habendi sint, ut contra 
officio suo et juramento probe defuncti turn demum censeri debeant” ( p . 266 ). — 
The fact that Christ and the apostles did not resist the authority of the State, 



908 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

their whole emphasis on suffering, is explained by the fact that they were 
private individuals, and that there were no subordinate authorities in existence 
who could protect the law, and thus until the present day they are the norm 
for merely private individuals: “Dominus noster Jesus Christus, prophetae 
item ac apostoli, cum privati erant homines, sese intra metas suae vocationis 
continuerunt ,, ( p . 509) ! This means a most decided retention of historic law, 
and it is easy to understand that the Genevan Council approved of the content 
of the work. Even Luther, though only under the influence of the decision of 
the jurists of 1530, himself approached such views to the extent of accepting 
the idea of the right to execute a tyrant and the idea of the mutua obligatio 
between people and rulers, even Melancthon had already made the distinction 
between private individuals and magistratus inferiores ; likewise Osiander ( ?) ; 
also the Erasmian and the Scholastic doctrine of the State is here in the 
background ; see Cardauns: Wider standsrecht, pp. 8-15, 31 ff. — Beza has clearly 
expressed the positive reasons for the justification of his theory. They are: 

(1) the Christian aim of the State and its aim according to Reason (p. 216) ; 

(2) the consequence of the lower court of justice (p. 217 ). — That theories of 
this kind could proceed drectly from Calvin’s instruction is shown still more 
strikingly by Knox’s theory, which was formulated in Geneva* and the treatise 
by Goodman , the second pastor of the English Church, which teaches the right 
of resistance almost without safeguards, How superior powers ought to be obeyed 
of their subjects and wherein they may lawfully by God’s Word be disobeyed and resisted , 
Geneva , 1558. Calvin looked through this treatise, and the author reports that 
Calvin thought it harsh and needing to be used with caution, but that its main 
contention was right (Doumergue, pp. 28 ff.). The tractate by the English bishop, 
Poynet: A short treatise of politic power , and of the true obedience which subjects own 
to the King and other civile governors , 1356, written in Strassburg. Cardauns , 37-40, 
proceeds directly from the standpoint of Calvin’s Institutes. 

874 (p* 632.) On this point cf. Cartier , pp. 204-206; Figgis: From Gerson to 
Grotius; Baudrillart: Bodin et son temps , 1833; Cardauns: Wider standsrecht, 1330; 
Treumann: Monarchomachen, 1833 ( Staats - und volkerrechtlich Abhandlungen. hsg. v. 
Jellinek, Nr. /); Elkan: Publizistik der Bartholomausnacht , and Mornay’s Vindicae, 
1303 {Heidelberger Abhh. zur mittleren und neueren Geschichte, Nr. 3); Mialy: Les 
publicistes de la r if or me, 1303 ( Thhe of the Paris FaculU de The'ol. Prot.); fq lJurieu, 
see Doumergue, p. 22, and Luran: Les doctrines politiques de J ., 1304. In this respect 
it is unfortunate that the theological ethic of Calvinism has not been yet 
carefully examined, but in any case, from the time of Beza, its important 
representatives agree with the publicists and the jurists on this point. Thus the 
resemblance between the ideas of the Monarchomachi and the principles of 
Rousseau ought not to be overestimated. They are concerned with deductions 
drawn from the Scriptures, the Law of Nature, and theology ; they are not 
concerned with the decided rationalism of an independent philosophy of the 
State. Treumann , who calls attention to the lack of a clear distinction between 
the social contract and the contract of sovereignty (p. 30, also Elkan, 133 ), as 
well as in reference to the “theocratic” limitations, has also recognized this, 
but he has not emphasized its importance sufficiently. The question is not one 
of the “retention of the ideas of contract without attacking the theocratic basis 
of the right of the ruler” (p. 36), but it is a question of the introduction of this 
idea also as an ingredient into all historic law; not one of setting aside an 
ideal of the State, which previously had been absolute, theocratic, and 
monarchical (p. 77) — there was never an ideal of this kind in Calvinism — but of 
the introduction of methods of control into the constitution which was itself 



PROTESTANTISM 


909 


unaltered. The contract idea is, therefore, quite dissimilar from the conceptions 
of Hobbes, Grotius, and Rousseau, and it remains true to the standpoint of 
the historic and therefore Divine Law. — Thus their ideas lack also the neces- 
sary presupposition of the later philosophy of the State, of the social contract, 
and the contract of sovereignty, the original freedom and equality. It is true 
that Elkan ( p . 30) says : “Ultimately the whole structure was based upon the 
idea of freedom for humanity, which was absolutely taken for granted. No one 
took the trouble to find an argument for this doctrine, scarcely anyone even 
dreamed of doubting it.” Therewith he only proves the absence of this doctrine. 
In reality, the Calvinistic and non-modern character of this whole school of 
writers is«based upon the absence of this doctrine. To them the social contract 
of equal and free men is superfluous because the Aristotelian organic doctrine 
is applied to the rise of Society ; this, however, also implies inequality in rank, 
the distinction between private individuals and officials, the sovereignty of the 
objective law, not the subjective equal share in Reason. Further, the idea of 
equality is excluded by the spirit produced by the doctrine of predestination. 
The youthful work of La Boitie (who was certainly not a Calvinist): Discours 
de la servitude volontaire , which began at the standpoint of the original freedom 
and equality in tfie Stoic Humanistic sense, and declared that servitude arose 
out of willing submission, was rejected by the Calvinists ( Baudrillart , 68-73), 
Mdaly, 63 . — It should be noted that Cardauns derives the Calvinistic theory 
from the branches of Lutheran propaganda which were influenced by Hesse 
and Strassbuig in the days of the League of Schmalkalden, and of the Magde- 
burg struggles, as, indeed, Beza's tractate in its first edition (1574) was intro- 
duced as being “public deceux de Magdebourg Pan 1550” ( Cartier , 187). Also Ritter: 
Anfdnge des niederland. Aufstandes {Hist. Z eitschr . 38, 1887, p. 423), quotes from 
a letter of 1556, in which a tractate is mentioned which deals with the problem 
of resistance and the justification of the magistratus inferiores , and he holds that 
this tractate refers either to the Gutachten of the ministers and lawyers of 
Wittenberg, or to the Vermahnung der Pfarrherrn von Magdeburg , 1343. Cf. also 
Cardauns , p. 7/, Beza’s appeal to the people of Magdeburg. In point of fact, 
all the ideas of the Calvinistic theory are also found, although in a confused 
way, in the works of many German writers. Only the Calvinistic doctrines have 
one mayi theoretical feature and principle derived from the fundamental 
religious idea of Calvinism — the idea of the glory of God, and of the equality 
of all in the presence of God, which clearly distinguishes them from those 
Lutheran theories, and, indeed, these theories themselves were an illogical and 
passing phenomenon, and at the best only a by-product of Lutheranism ; this 
latter point is not sufficiently emphasized by Cardauns , see above, pp. 330 
and 532 . 

375 (p. 634.) Cf. Martin: De la Genhse des doctrines religieuses de John Knox , and 
De la Genkse des doctrines politiques de J. K., in the Bulletin de la sociiti de Phistoire 
du prot. frangais, 1306, 133-211, and 1307, pp. 133-221 . Cf. also Cardauns and 
Elkan. Cf. also in the book by Bastide on Locke , to be mentioned shortly, the 
section entitled Theories politiques en Angleterre au 16 et ij? me sikles , pp. 137-176. 
The conservative legitimist Calvinistic character of the Presbyterian and 
Independent movement is here rightly emphasized in contrast to that of the 
“Levellers” and kindred groups. We shall see later on that the latter were nearer 
to the spirit of the Anabaptists than to that of the Calvinists. The forces which 
were at work in the so-called “Independency” were utterly different. — Pareus 
in Heidelberg also taught that kings might be deposed, see Bastide , p . 144 ; 
this idea was not peculiar to the English Revolution. 



9io THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

876 (p* 635.) Cf. Gierke* s Althusius *, in which, with his admirable learning and 
industry, Gierke examines the origin of all these elements of thought. Gierke 
also rightly lays stress on the fact that the new theory stands out clearly from 
the previous religious theory, especially the presupposition of universal freedom 
and equality before the social contract ( pp . 29, yg, and ioy). Further valuable 
details dealing with this subject will be found especially on pp. 28 and 30 , 
59 and 69, y6 , 2iy, and 143. The view that subordinate authorities are justified in 
resistance under certain circumstances is discussed on pp. 34 and 55. Indeed, a 
Lutheran, Peter Gartz , has described the doctrine of Althusius as a product of 
“Presbyterian error” (p. y) ; it is, however, in reality a step beyond genuine 
Calvinism, and stands between it and the classic-Rationalistic Law of Nature. 

877 (p. 636.) The famous work of Grotius (which I have used in the transla- 
tion in the Kirchmannschen Philos. Bibliothek , i86g) shows everywhere its purely 
humanist, philosophical, juridical character and its fundamental connection 
with Stoicism ; the whole statement of the problem of war and of international 
law starts from the cosmopolitan Stoic idea of humanity ; from this standpoint 
it is believed that confessional struggles and conflicts can be absolutely over- 
come. Therefore, in his opinion, the Law of Nature, the a priori rational 
foundation, is entirely independent of all theology and of, all faith in God 
(/, p. 31). For the relation to the previous Protestant doctrine of the State the 
declaration regarding the Old Testament is characteristic: “Many would like 
to raise the Old Testament to the level of a Law of Nature, but they are wrong. 
For much that it contains proceeds from the decree of God, which is certainly 
not in conflict with true Nature” (/, 60). This means that the Law of Nature 
is no longer identified with the political ethic of the Old Testament. With 
reference to the New Testament he says : “I make use of the New Testament 
because that which is permitted to Christians I can learn from it alone. Unlike 
most other writers, however, I distinguish this content from the Law of Nature 
itself; for I am convinced that in this holiest of all laws a higher holiness is 
taught than the Law of Nature requires for itself alone. Yet I have always noted 
whether in certain instances some things are rather suggested than com- 
manded. Since it is wrong and punishable to depart from the commandments 
(that is, also from that which is commanded by Natural Law), whereas it is the 
sign of a noble temper, which will not go unrewarded, if one always strives 
to follow the highest, that is, the commands of the Gospel, which exceed those 
of Nature (p. 61). This means that the Protestant habit of identifying the 
Natural Law and the Sermon on the Mount has been given up, and it also 
means the final emancipation of the Natural Law from the commands of the 
Sermon on the Mount, as is shown in the long argument which follows. Then 
there comes the vigorous establishment of the contract upon the presupposition 
of an original communism and an original freedom and equality (/, pp. yo 9 y4 , 
y6 f 80 , go ) ; further, the rejection of anti-monarchist theories in the interest of 
a unified State authority which is far removed from religious conflict (/, 193). 
In accordance with this Grotius opposes the doctrine of predestination, and 
from the dogmatic point of view he takes the side of the Arminians and the 
Socinians. — The Natural Law of the period after Grotius departed still further 
from the Calvinistic basis. Of Rousseau, above all, Gierke says very pertinently 
that the idea of the contract of sovereignty is swallowed up in the social con- 
tract ( Alth ., 91 ff .) ; in so doing, however, he destroyed every historic right, 
and set up the ideal of small federated republics, in which the original freedom 
and equality should be preserved by basing all legislation upon the general 
will ; this may correspond to the Swiss republics, but it has nothing to do with 



PROTESTANTISM 


9 1 1 

the spirit of Calvinism; indeed, it is in complete opposition to it. — French 
Protestant apologists naturally approve of Rousseau’s estimate of Calvinism ; 
cf. the work by Mialy and also Doumcrgue (who is much more restrained) 
(pp. 53,55, and 63), Nevertheless, it is wrong. To describe Grotius and Pufendorf 
as “representatives of Calvinist politics” (p. 25) is simply false; the Genevan 
lawyer, Burlamaqui (d. 1748), whom Doumergue quotes with special emphasis, 
represents a purely individualistic rationalism of freedom and equality, which 
is quite remote from Calvinistic thought. Also Jurieu (d. 1713) already shows 
this foreign influence (pp. 22ff.). 

881 (p. 641.) Cf. Kampschulte, I, 385-480 , especially 423 ff.; II, 342-387; 
Wiskemamy National okonomische Ansichten zur Zeit der Reformation , pp. 80-87 ; 
Elster: Calvin als Staatsmann, Gesetzgeber und Nationalokonom. Jahrbb . f. National - 
okonomie und Statistik , XXXI (based on Kampschulte and Wiskemann) ; Rachfahl : 
Calvinismus und Kapitalismus , Internationale Wochenschrift , igog (in which there are 
references to Calvin based upon Kampschulte , Elster, and Lang); Max Weber: 
Protestantische Ethik und der Geist des Kapitalismus, Archiv XX and XXI; Laveleye, 
Protestantismus und Katholizismus in ihren Beziehungen zur Wohlfahrt der Volker, 
deutsch , p. 127; Choisy: Vital chretien ; E. Knodt : Bedeutung Calvins und des Cal- 
vinismus fiir die Protestantische Welt ( Vortrage der Giessener Konferenz), 19/0. — 
Weber's treatise is^o-day of fundamental importance. First of all he has handled 
the problem in its great setting of the history of civilization, and on its inward 
side he has linked the religious and ethical element with the social and economic 
element. For my own part I have adopted these views of his which I have 
found confirmed largely through a study of American life, and of that of the 
Lower Rhine, and have used them in my more general works on the nature of 
Protestantism and its significance for civilization, naturally not wholly without 
using my own judgment, but it is quite unnecessary to stress this point. — 
Rachfahl has attacked Weber and myself in the article which has just been 
mentioned ; I do not, however, consider that in these matters he is a competent 
judge. 

382 (p. 641.) Passages in Kampschulte, I, 430; see also Brief e, I, 433, the recog- 
nition of the poverty which Jesus commanded contrasted with monastic 
poverty. Numerous examples of a similar anti-mammon spirit among his 
followers in Choisy, 176 ff., to a proposal of the tradespeople to found a bank 
with the ifcte of interest of 10 per cent., they recognize the “belle apparence” 
of the project, but they fear “abus, d£sordres et dissolutions”, point out the 
dangers of banking business in Paris, Venice, and Lyons, and they also point 
out the destruction of Jerusalem and of Rome through riches: “Si ce change 
est introduit, on dira, qu’& Geneve cbacun est banquier et qu’il n’a que des 
preteurs. Si d’aventure Messieurs jugent n^anmoins que ce charge sera com- 
mode, ils prient de bien considerer s’il sera tolerable de prater k deux et demi 
par foire. ... Ils pensaient que la cit6 serait plus forte en demeurant pauvre”. 
P. 346: “The Venerable Compagnie announces that they will preach to the 
people on Tordre, Pob&ssance et la modestie*.” P. 223: They demand “qu*on 
demeure en toute modestie et mediocrity”. Calvin already was quite of this 
mind (Elster, igi) : ^Et en g^ndral, que chacun ait k se vestir honestement et 
simplement selon son cstat et qualite et que tous, tant petits que grands, 
monstrent bon exemple de modestie chr6tienne les uns aux autres.” — The 
Church in the Netherlands still has too high a rate of interest, pawnbrokers* 
shops and deposit businesses are vigorously opposed as methods of exploiting 
the poor; see Knappert: Geschiedenis der nederlandsche hervormde Kerk , ign, 
pp. 178-182 . 



912 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

,S4 (p. 643.) This reaction of Geneva is emphasized by Kampschulte , p. 423. 
Before Calvin Geneva had already a State system of legislation on interest, 
which he simply took over. The fact that Calvin threw himself into the com- 
mercial atmosphere of the city, which is taken for granted, is illustrated over 
and over again by his correspondence. Briefe, /, 33, mercantile speculations in 
respect of Calvin’s exile ; 81 and 306, recommendation of believers as appren- 
tices ; 2og, Calvin’s own difficulty of raising a loan for himself ; 283, difficulties 
of placing a nephew of Viret in a shop or as a traveller or as a collector of 
debts; 234, similar difficulties in raising securities for a colleague in the 
ministry. Advice to two citizens of Lausanne about financial transactions; 
//, p. iog 9 efforts on behalf of debtors in order to secure the credit of Geneva. 
Further illustrations of Calvin’s interest in financial and business matters can 
be found in his correspondence ; see the German edition of his Letters , especially 
the following pages in //, 360 , 740, 333 , 442. The same point of view is reflected 
in the extracts from reports quoted by Choisy , see especially pp . 31 and 332; 
34, 36 , and 58; 47 , 57, 140 , 134 , and 388. 

887 (p. 644.) The details of this subject belong to the economic presentation 
of the subject ; they are, however, not at all simple to represent statistically. 
To that we must add the fact that in the neighbourhood of Calvinism there 
were also other groups — Anglican, sectarian, and Lutheran— which also were 
to some extent influenced by Calvinism. The fact itself is well known and 
generally recognized. In addition to the literature which has already been 
mentioned I would call the attention of the reader to the good summary in 
Arnold: Calvinreden , pp. 28-33 ; here, p. 31: “Calvinism has produced this 
proverb, ‘Faith removes mountains and works at the same time with axe and 
spade*. Lutheranism also gave dignity to labour, but since all this was referred 
to work in one’s ‘calling’, the free initiative of the individual was less definitely 
released. . . . Calvin alone among the Reformers emphasized the fact that that 
which makes work productive is not merely the physical and the intellectual 
effort, but above all moral force. . . . The objective value of that which is 
achieved by labour, the economic result, consists, according to this view, not 
in temporary gain, but solely and only in the fact that honest work has been 
done. An idea capable of infinite expansion ! This capacity for development is 
so easily overlooked because people look upon it as such a natural thing, as, 
indeed, it is.” There then follows a sketch of the expansion and ii-fluence of 
Calvinistic industrialism and capitalism. — A characteristic example from the 
Netherlands is given by Weber from the work entitled Political Arithmetic , by 
the famous political economist W. Petty: Antikritisches , p. 184 : “Dissenters of 
this kind (he means the supporters of the struggle for freedom in Holland, who 
were primarily Calvinists) are, for the most part, thinking, sober, and patient 
men, and such as believe that labour and industry is their duty towards God.” 
This is not contradicted, but rather supported by the following passages from 
the same author, ibid.,p. 188: “These people (namely, the Puritan Dissenters), 
believing the justice of God and seeing the most licentious persons to enjoy 
most of the world and its best things, will never venture to be of the same 
religion and profession with voluptuaries and men of extreme wealth and 
power who they think have their portion in this world.” — The extension of 
bourgeois capitalism, in particular territories and the modifications which 
there obtain, is treated by Weber: Antikritisches , pp. 186-188 , 132 ; conclusion, 
pp. 571 and 334 ff. Here we see how also within a setting, which in itself was 
unfavourable to Capitalism — as in East Friesland, New England, and Hungary 
— similar, or at least related, influences were also operative. This development 



PROTESTANTISM 913 

of Capitalism is not dependent merely upon a favourable environment. — 
Gobel, //, jg, gives numerous examples of Calvinism in the Netherlands and on 
the Lower Rhine: “Its members (of the Calvinistic community at Aachen) 
consisted almost entirely of wealthy and noble merchants, while all the 
Lutherans were only tolerated as assessors.” //, p. 47: “The letters of credence 
of the delegates and elders to the synods had to be put in the form of mercantile 
letters of credit in order to avoid all danger of treachery or suspicion.” //, p. 106: 
“And (after a description of their ascetic strictness of life) since both in Julich 
and Berg they were excluded from all public offices, it was all the more natural 
that the whole trade of the Lower Rhine, and the whole of the industry of these 
parts which was here so important, especially fell into their hands, and that 
still to-day it is in their hands in particular. Hence the districts of Berg, Mark, 
and Julich, which have developed a remarkable manufacturing activity and 
an extended trade, have become some of the richest and most remarkable parts 
of Germany, which at the same time have gained a name for great attachment 
to the Church and for personal piety.” //, p. 205— the writer is here quoting from 
Labadie: “The elders and deacons fulfil their duties to the members of the 
Church and the poor in their own districts ; the judges love righteousness and 
the tradespeople carry on their trade in the sight of heaven and the masters 
labour for eternity.” For the economic significance of Labadism, see //, pp. 238 
and 2gg; in this respect it is only a heightened form of Calvinism. — With 
reference to the economic ethic of English Puritanism, Cunningham , the well- 
known English economic historian, says in a small book entitled The Moral 
Witness of the Church on the Investment of Money and the Use of Wealthy Cambridge , 
J 9°9> PP • 23 jf- : “As the defect of the present-day ethic of the Church (in 
England) is a one-sided tendency towards Socialism, so on the contrary the 
one-sided nature of Puritanism and its neglect of other factors was its peculiarity. 
Its fight against idleness and love of pleasure, and its recommendation of 
disciplined work, have made it absolutely capitalistic. Unemployment and 
idleness were the characteristic evils of the seventeenth century in England and 
Scotland ; the great need for introducing a godly, sober, and righteous life into 
the community appeared to be that of getting the population to submit to the 
discipline of work. There were no half-measures in the Scottish treatment of 
vagrants, according to the Act of 1663. Capitalists who set up manufactories 
were errif>owered to impress any vagrants and ‘employ them for their service 
as they see fit* for eleven years, without wages, except meat and clothing. 
Good subjects were recommended to take into their service poor and indigent 
children, who were to do any task assigned to them till they had attained the 
age of thirty, and to be ‘subject to their masters’ correction and chastisement 
in all manner of punishment (life and torture excepted)’. The seventeenth- 
century Puritans took a stern view of the discipline which was good for children, 
so that they might be kept from forming habits of idleness and drifting into 
evil of every kind. While there was a strong sense of the religious duty of 
insisting on hard and regular work for the welfare, temporal and eternal, of the 
people themselves, there was a complete indifference to the need of laying down 
or enforcing any restrictions as to the employment of money. Capital was 
much needed in England, and still more in Scotland, for developing the 
resources of the country and for starting new enterprises; freedom for the 
formation and investment of capital seemed to the thoughtful city men of the 
seventeenth century, who were mostly in sympathy with Puritanism, the best 
remedy for the existing social evils. They were eager to get rid of the restrictions 
imposed by the Pope’s laws, which it was possible to bring up in ecclesiastical 
VOL. n. 00 



914 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

courts as well as to be free from the efforts of the King’s Council to bring 
home to the employing and mercantile classes their duty to the community. 
The agitation against the interference of the bishops in civil affairs and the 
triumph of Puritanism swept away all traces of any restrictions or guidance in 
the employment of money. In so far as a stricter ecclesiastical discipline was 
aimed at or introduced, it had regard to recreation and to immorality of 
other kinds, but was at no pains to interfere to check the action of the capitalist 
or to protect the labourer. From the time when the rise of Puritanism paralysed 
the action of the Church (that is, the State Church), and prevented her from 
maintaining the influence she had habitually exerted, it has been plausible 
to say that Christian teaching appeared to be brought to bear on the side of 
the rich and against the poor. The Puritans were probably right as to the most 
serious evils of the day, and the economic means of overcoming them ; they 
may well have felt that religious duty impelled them to the line they took.” 
This book is otherwise also characteristic ; it is an expression on the part of 
the clergy of their views on a Christian ethic of economics, and on its side 
it develops a modern adaptation of early Christian ideas to the modern 
capitalistic form of life which is to be accepted as the natural course of affairs. 
With reference to Bremen, which is overwhelmingly Calvinistic, a conversation 
between a leading tradesman of Bremen and a tradesman of Vienna about the 
difference in the way of living of the luxurious Viennese tradespeople and of 
the austere and frugal tradespeople of Bremen, which I found in the Sonntags - 
blatt of the Bremer Nachrichten , Nr. 30 and 31 of igio {“Von alter Bremer Art”): 
“ ‘Do you know, Musje R. (the Viennese), why we don’t act like that? . . . 
Because we are free citizens of the Empire.’ — ‘But still’, says the other, ‘you are 
also important tradespeople!’ — ‘And just on that account’, the man from 
Bremen continues, ‘we need a lot of money, and also we have to save. But in 
order that you may understand me, I must explain to you what a large trades- 
man in an free imperial city really means. He is a man whp always works more 
in order to earn more, and who always earns more in order to work more, 
because in this way he does not use up his money, but gives it away in order 
to employ more hands and to be able to feed more hungry people. The 
Viennese merchant can buy estates and use up a good deal of his property. 
I don’t think the worse of him for it. If there is distress in the land his Emperor 
puts his hand into his pocket. But here, if there is distress, the free StSte turns 
to its free citizens for help. The rich citizen is ready and willing to help and 
to give. Also the citizen who is in difficulties naturally flies for help to the 
citizen who is in better circumstances. If one of the citizens has earned a great 
deal he has many claims to satisfy, and he does this gladly both as a fellow- 
citizen and as a Christian. And now I would like to give you the prescription 
for the medicine with which I want to die ! (The previous remarks were the 
prescription for life). It is in Matt. xxiv. 12, 13, “He who abides in righteous- 
ness and love unto the end will be saved”.’ ” The man from Bremen says that 
the reason for his way of life is the republican character of the city of Bremen, 
but the religious turn of the conversation shows that what is here in question 
is the Calvinistic ethic, as, indeed, the whole article shows that the author is 
strictly religious. — In the passages which have here been quoted there emerges 
at many points the connection between this development and the position of 
the Calvinists as a minority and their exclusion from official life, as also is 
emphasized by Weber: Antikritisches , p. 188 . In the light of other passages, 
however, this is not decisive. — An important point remains in the capitalistic 
development of Calvinism in the direction of the middle classes and the 



PROTESTANTISM 


9i5 


bourgeoisie. To this is due in England the contrast between the 4 ‘squirearchy 
and the bourgeois middle classes, who in the Cobden movement were charac- 
teristically supported by Dissent* * (conclusion, p. 558) ; bourgeois character, 
see conclusion p . 573: “It is now, however, one of the achievements of Ascetic 
Protestantism that it worked against these tendencies : the ‘idolizing of the 
creature’, the desire to secure the splendor familiae through the immobilization 
of property in order to bring in a large income, the aristocratic joy in ‘high 
life*, the voluptuous wallowing in aesthetic enjoyment and ‘selfish indulgence’ 
as well as the desire for insolent ostentation.” This bourgeois development is, 
in my opinion, one of the main problems of our subject, and its causes are 
still most obscure; cf. the remark by Weber: Antikritisches, p. 188: “The interest- 
ing phenomenon which can be observed in the relation between the classes 
and the religious life — almost in all countries — is the gradual transformation 
of the originally (often even including the Baptist movement) vertical cleavage 
in the social system (that is, group-formation conditioned by religion) into 
a horizontal cleavage (that is, a situation in which religious characteristics 
belong to certain classes in Society) ; this is where the materialistic ‘interpreta- 
tion* of history steps in.” This interpretation has, however, not yet been 
authenticated. 1$ the course of the whole of this book I have continually been 
faced with this problem ; I have, however, only been able to offer some meagre 
suggestions in explanation, especially on this point ; sometimes it seems to me 
as though the minority position and exclusion from official life were the cause, 
sometimes as though it were due to the inward logic of the Galvinistic ethic, 
and often it seems as if both causes combined were the reason. In any case, 
at the beginning the social classification played a much smaller part, and 
humanistic secular culture and aristocratic customs predominated. There is a 
great contrast between the Calvinism described by Afarcks in his Coligny and 
that which is described by Dowden and Gobel. Also it remains to be proved how 
far this shifting of emphasis was a general phenomenon. 

888 (p. 644.) No one has ever asserted that Capitalism is the direct product 
of Calvinism. We can, however, say that both possessed a certain affinity for 
each other, that Calvinistic ethic of the “calling” and of work, which declares 
that the earning of money with certain precautions is allowable, was able to 
give it aiyntellectual and ethical backbone, and that, therefore, thus organized 
and inwardly supported it vigorously developed, even though within the limits 
of anti-mammon. “There is no doubt that where an economic system and a 
‘spirit’ with which it has a certain affinity meet, there ensues a development 
along uniform lines which is also inwardly unbroken (that is, where the spirit 
and the economic system agree, which is not always the case), of the kind 
which I had begun to analyse (that is, like the Calvinistic development).” 
The conjunction of these two elements itself is an historic accident, as I have 
said already in describing the similarly comparatively close affinity between 
the mediaeval system and the Catholic ethic. But out of such accidents ( Weber: 
Schlusswort , XXXI , p. 580): “Humanity which through the meeting of religious 
and economic elements was created” ; p. 583: “Protestant asceticism created 
for it (bourgeois capitalism) a positive ethic, a soul which needed that restless 
activity in order that ‘spirit* and ‘form* might be one ” ; p. 588: A current of 
psychic elements which arose from a very specific moral and religious source, 
combined with capitalistic possibilities of development from which the great 
historical developments proceed. The Christian ethic only attained a great 
actual importance for world-history when it was supported by an “accident” 
of this kind. In itself alone, when it did not receive this support, it simply remained 



gi 6 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

in the realm of theory. The combination of these elements then reacted, 
however, upon the religious and ethical spirit, as I prove in both instances. 
In the history of the Christian ethic there have only been two “accidents” of 
this kind, the mediaeval system and the Calvinistic system, whose expansion 
through the bourgeois sect will be demonstrated in the next section. There are 
other certainly often finer and deeper conceptions of the Christian Ethos to 
whom an historic influence of this kind was denied, because they were not 
favoured by such an “accident” or in their very nature were unable to find 
such support. If I speak here of “accident**, this is naturally meant logically, 
i.e. that here there is no immanent development, not that these things have 
happened sine Deo. r 

889a (p. 645.) The rise and the nature of the “Capitalist system** is, as is well 
known, the main problem of economic and theoretical research at the present 
day. Analyses of the system are given by Weber: Prot. Ethik , XX, pp . 11-35; 
Sombart: Die Juden und das Wirtschaftsleben , igu, pp. 186-158; and in his well- 
known earlier works, Deutsches Wirtschaftsleben des ig. Jahrh., and, above all, 
Der Kapitalismus; see also the article K. by Traub , in RGG. An account of the 
“system** in England is given by Held: Z ur sozialen Geschichte Englands , in 
which there are excellent observations on social history in general. Held lays 
more emphasis upon the external technical and other reasons for the growth of 
the system. He only deals with the spiritual and ethical foundations in the 
analysis of the theories of students of politics and political economy ; but he 
does not follow the subject into the real popular ethos. Weber, however, has 
dealt with this question in studying the problem of the rise and nature of the 
“Spirit of Capitalism’*, Sombart in studying the problem as a question of the 
“economic spirit” ( Wirtschaftsgesinnung ), and both have explored the depths of 
the popular religious ethos. For the difference between the “Spirit of Capitalism” 
and “the Capitalistic system”, which do not need to coincide, and often do not 
coincide, see Weber: Antikritisches , pp. 201-202. The domination of Capitalism 
over the minds of men does not take place until by “accident” both these 
elements meet. Rachfahl cannot understand this distinction, and he only makes 
fun of it. Further, I wish to emphasize that Weber and Sombart are mainly 
concerned with the attempt to lay bare the nature of Capitalism, and the 
religious and ethical elements are only of secondary importance. My aim, on 
the other hand, is to make clear the significance of Capitalism in the develop- 
ment of Calvinism. Thus behind our researches the points of view are very 
different. 

890 (p. 645.) This is very clearly analysed by Weber: Schlusswort, XXXI, 582 ff.: 
“Of course at all periods praise and commendation for conscientious work have 
always been given to the laity (although only in a limited way in primitive 
Christianity, more among the Cynics). 

“Luther’s expressions of opinion in this direction are well known. Outside 
Protestantism, of course, there have been those who have taught the blessing 
that rests on secular work. But of what use is this if, as in Lutheranism, there 
are no rewards (in this case spiritual) for this way of life which will ensure 
that these theories will be put into practice? Or if, as in Catholicism, far greater 
rewards are offered for quite a different kind of behaviour, and further, when 
in the form of the confessional a means is given which over and over again 
makes it possible for the individual to unburden his mind of all kinds of errors 
which he has committed against the postulates of the Church? Whereas, on 
the other hand, Calvinism, in its development after the latter part of the 
sixteenth century, and similarly the Baptist movement in the idea of the 



PROTESTANTISM 


9i7 


necessity of ascetic proof, in life in general, and specially also in the life in one’s 
‘calling’, as the subjective guarantee of the certitudo salutis — as one of the most 
important signs of one’s own certainty of election — created a very specific 
spiritual reward, which in its effectiveness within this sphere cannot easily be 
excelled for the ascetic way of life which it required.” 

392 (p. 647.) This is one of the most important results of Max Weber's study. 
Only later on shall we be able to see its full significance, when, after the 
analysis of the Protestant sects, we come to the collective conception of Ascetic 
Protestantism. I maintain that these conclusions are right, although they have 
been criticized by Rachfahl ; Rachfahl , indeed, admits the fact, but he allows 
much les^ significance to be attributed to its significance for the development 
of economic history, and he is determined not to grant that it arises definitely 
from the spirit of Calvinism. In the first place he has, indeed, alluded to the 
exceptions which Weber has made, which of course allow for the existence 
of a number of other motives which have contributed to the rise of modern 
Capitalism; Weber, indeed, names some quite different groups as supporters 
of this development, but R. has not taken them into account. In the second 
place, his knowledge of the doctrine of Calvin and of primitive conditions in 
Geneva is only indirect, and gained from the works of Kampschulte , Elster , and 
Lang, and, therefore, he misinterprets both in the political and in the economic 
sphere the consequences of the most distinctive religious thought of Geneva. 
He considers Calvin a traditionalist in the Lutheran sense ; the only difference 
is that he thinks that Calvin has a broader view on the subject of interest, 
and that otherwise he emphasizes honesty and seriousness in work, that is, 
the various ethical elements in economic life. Otherwise, like Kampschulte, he 
regards Calvinism as an exaltation of religious feeling which is contrary to 
Nature, can only last a short time, and is unable to do anything great in the 
secular sphere. Rachfahl considers that modern progress is due to the Rationalists, 
and to Christians of the school of Erasmus who practise toleration, and also to 
the comparative emancipation of the Protestant State from religious considera- 
tions. The whole constitutes a defence of toleration in the wrong place. But 
toleration by itself does not mean anything in economic development ; it all 
depends upon the economic nature of that which is allowed to be tolerated. 
This is veg-y well illustrated by Bastide , p. 214, where he is dealing with tolera- 
tion in England : “The example of Holland had struck the English ; Sir William 
Temple . . . attributed the prosperity of this country to religious liberty and 
to the presence of numerous refugees. Finally, the arrival of the Huguenots 
(after the revocation of the Edict of Nantes), who were fleeing from persecution, 
and who made a great impression by their industrious habits and the quality 
of their work, confirmed the idea that the religious exile is a great help to 
public wealth. Sir W. Petty said that ‘commerce is practised most vigorously 
in all states and under all governments by the heterodox section of the nation, 
and by those who profess opinions different from those which are officially 
received*. We can remember what importance Shaftesbury gave to the economic 
argument in his Memorandum on toleration. This argument often reappears. 
Charles Wolseley ... in a little treatise upon liberty of conscience, mentions 
the departure for Holland of the dissenting weavers of Norwich. An anonymous 
author . . . without insisting ... on the theological side of the question . . . 
replied to Dr. Dove ‘that religious liberty was the school of noble and generous 
souls’. The artisans of Norwich who have emigrated are the best citizens : 
‘Are not the men who have religious principles sensible and serious men who 
do good to a nation? Are they not generally in all forms of trade and in other 



gi8 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

callings the most industrious and the most prosperous?* ** It is clear that here 
the allusion is not to toleration in itself, but to the acceptance or retention of 
a certain class of citizens ; these citizens are precisely the Calvinists with their 
well-known commercial qualities. It is also clear, as these authors observe, 
that the experience of religious oppression and exclusion fosters the growth of 
those business qualities, and, finally, that these qualities are connected with 
moral and religious principles. We might produce similar arguments in favour 
of the Baptist and Pietist sects, who also, through similar experiences, develop 
similar qualities upon a similar foundation of religion and ethics. It is not 
Calvinism itself which is here being considered, but Calvinism as it has 
developed in the school of oppression and as a minority. This development, 
however, is still connected with the fundamental Calvinistic ethic in general, 
and with its economic ethic in particular. There have also been Catholic 
minorities in England, but we never hear anything of this kind about them. 
Cf. also Weber in Antikritisches , Schlusswort , XXXI, pp. 565-569, and Antikritisches , 
XXX , 162-188 . — This toleration has also been to the advantage of the Jews. 
Sombart has made a study of their significance similar to that made by Weber 
on Calvinism and the sects. In my opinion, however, Sombart has overestimated 
and misinterpreted the r61e of the Jews. He is certainly wrong in his comparison 
between Puritanism and Judaism, based on the argument that the Calvinists 
lay so much emphasis upon the Old Testament. For the Calvinistic economic 
spirit is quite different from that of Judaism, and their connection with the 
Old Testament is very complicated ; see above, pp. 658-640. Many resemblances, 
however, have been noted. 

993 (P- 650.) Calvin is an opponent of Baptist communism, against which he 
strives repeatedly, precisely for social reasons ; for when all had sold their goods 
the rich would have to beg, and no one would have a house in which to dwell, 
or in which the poor could be sheltered ( R ., XXXV , p. 488). Otherwise his way 
of thinking is definitely social on a religious basis ; see, for instance, the summary 
of Christian ethics (Inst. Ill , pp. 7-10 ), which forms a supplement to the explana- 
tion of the Decalogue (II, 8), and deepens it with the Christian point of view : 
“Nostri non sumus : Inde consequitur, ut ne quaeramus, quae nostra sunt, sed 
quae ex Domini sunt voluntate et faciunt ad gloriam ejus promovendam. . . . 
Quum enim nos privatam nostri rationem omittere jubet scriptura, iion modo 
habendi cupiditatem, potentiae affectionem, hominum gratiam ex animis 
nostris eradit, sed ambitionem quoque et omnem gloriae humanae appetitum 
aliasque secretiores pestes eradicat” (III, 7, 2). “Perspicimus abnegationem 
nostri partim quidem in homines respicere partim in Deum** (III, 7, 5). Then 
follows the development of the first idea : “Jam inquaerenda proximi utilitate 
officium praestare, quantum habet difficultatis ! ... At Scriptura, ut eo nos 
manuducat, praemonet quidquid a Domino gratiarum obtinemus, esse nobis 
hac lege concreditum, ut in commune ecclesiae (that is, the whole Christian 
society) bonum conferatur ideoque legitimam gratiarum omnium usum esse 
liberalem ac benignam cum aliis communicationem.** All possessions are 
“deposita Dei ea lege fidei nostrae commissa, ut in proximorum bonum 
dispensentur”. There then follows the well-known Pauline parable of the 
organism : “Nullum membrum suam facultatem sibi habet nec in privatum 
usum applicat, sed ad socia membra transfundit. . . . Sic pius vir, quidquid 
potest, fratribus debet posse : sibi non aliter privatim consulendo, quam ut ad 
communem ecclesiae aedificationem intentus sit animus. Haec itaque . . . 
nobis sit method us : quidquid in nos Deus contulit, quo proximum queamus 
adjuvare, ejus nos esse oeconomos, qui ad reddendam dispensations rationem 



PROTESTANTISM 


9i9 

adstringimur. Earn demum porro rectam esse dispensationem, quae ad dilec- 
tionis exigatur regulam. Ita fiet, ut non modo alieni commodi studium cum 
popriae utilitatis cura semper conjungamus, sed hanc illi subjiciamus” (///, 7,5). 
At the same time we have to remember “non hominum malitiam reputandam 
esse, sed inspiciendam in ilJis Dei imaginem : quae inductis et obliterate eorum 
delictis ad eos amandos, amplexandosque sua pulcritudine ac dignitate nos 
alliciat” (III, 7, 6 ). “Ita secum quisque cogitabit, se, quantus quantus est, 
proximis debitorem rei esse, nec alium exercendae ergo ipsos beneficentiae 
statuendum esse finem, nisi quum facultates deficiunt : quae quam late exten- 
duntur, ad caritatis regulam limitari debet” (III, 7, 7). This is an absolute 
programme of Christian Socialism. — This point of view also determines Calvin’s 
insistence on the restriction of interest, his fight against usury, the civil legisla- 
tion about trade and consumption, and, above all, the establishment of the 
Church system of poor relief and social welfare. The Compagnie , under Beza, 
worked in the same direction, keeping their hand on the control of public life ; 
Choisy gives many illustrations of this point. On the question of the care of the 
poor and the enormous sums which were spent on this, see Uhlhorn: Liebestatig - 
keit, III, 141-169 and Choisy in general. — Where Church and State were not 
united the Christian social development was simply an intensive affair of the 
congregation itself, as in the refugee community in London organized by 
John k Lasko, and in the communities organized after the same pattern in the 
Netherlands and on the Lower Rhine ; on this point see Simons: Eine altkolnischc 
Seelsorgegemeinde, 1894, Aelteste evangelische Gemeindearmenpflege vom Niederrhein , 
1 899 , Niederrheinisches Synodal- und Gemeindeleben unter dem Kreuz, 1897; here p. 20: 
“Thus the Synod, from the modern point of view, is not very far removed from 
Christian Socialism.” For the Elizabethan social legislation, and its connection 
with Puritan ideas, see the work by Cunningham, which has already been men- 
tioned, and Held, 16-98. — On these restrictions and the fact that the Calvinistic 
ethic also retained the pretium justum, see Weber: Antikritisches , XXX, 188, 194, 
201 jf.; also Laspeyres: Geschichte der Volkswirtschaftlichen Anschauungen der 
Nieder l cinder, 1863, pp. 256-270: theological views on Capitalism which, it is true, 
admit the taking of interest, but which would like to see it restricted, with 
consideration for the poor ; on the other hand, attention is drawn also to the 
strongly geological elements in the economic theories even of non-theological 
thinkers (p. 31). Characteristically Calvinistic is the formula for the under- 
takings in Brazil (p. 82): “De hooghste Wet, rakende Brasil, behoovt te wesen 
de Eere Gods ende de Welstand der Participanten.” 

894 (p* 65°-) There are some characteristic remarks in a letter of Calvin to 
Bullinger (Brief e, 1,342): “We must also take this city into account, and indeed 
we must give it a very prominent position in our thoughts. If I were thinking 
only of my own life or of my own circumstances, I could go somewhere else 
at once. But when I consider how important this corner of the world is for the 
extension of the Kingdom of Christ, I am sure I am right to do all I can to 
protect it.” Calvin then goes on to advise a treaty with France, which he thinks 
is allowable, since Abraham made a covenant with the heathen Abimelech, 
and Isaac and David likewise made covenants with the heathen for the purpose 
of the Kingdom of God. 

8,7 (p. 651.) Calvin’s teaching on war, Inst. IV, 20, 11, and 12; the vigorous 
passage which defends war only appears in the later editions. The cause of 
Christ is only to be served through confession of faith, organization, breaking 
with the Catholic Church, suffering and endurance and trust in God. Human 
power is to be unconditionally renounced ; if it is necessary, God will work a 



920 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

miracle to save His Church. Numerous passages in the Letters take this point 
of view. Everywhere Calvin advised against taking up arms, and often on 
occasions which were either very favourable to the Calvinists, or times of 
great necessity. 

898 (p. 651.) This change of view comes out in several passages in Calvin’s 
Letters , /, 341 ; in connection with the plan for a treaty with France, which 
might lead to France going to war with Charles V ; in spite of all scruples he 
thinks that “we might ascribe it more to a blameworthy sense of security than 
to genuine trust in God, if we were to ignore means of assistance which, even 
though not desirable, are still permitted” ! II, 33: Calvin blames the Germans, 
who in 1555, by their laziness, threw away their chances of being protected by 
God, and therefore had so little success in war. II, 327: writing to Bullinger: 
“Believe me, I can assure you certainly that there is no danger of disturbance 
on our side unless the King of Navarre is openly attacked. In his defence, 
certainly, I hope that many would rise and fight.” II, 343: he deplores the 
rising of the Savoy Protestants against their lord. Ill, 442: he counsels the 
Calvinistic commandant of Lyons, in a very conditional way, to lay down his 
arms: “Further, if both wish to come to terms with you there would still have 
to be a legal basis for this, for without their help you cannot . . . carry the 
matter through. For something which has been begun without being called 
to it, and justified in it, can never work out well. I do not say that perhaps 
a good reason could not be found, but I do not know one, and on that account 
I would not venture to advise war to begin without being better informed.” 
Here also Calvin’s thought is not uniform, since if a legitimate reason can be 
produced both civil war and a war of religion are permitted. This also is the 
interpretation given by Marcks in his book on Coligny, pp. 338 , 361 , 380 , especially 
408; finally, it comes to this, that a legal reason has to be found to justify a war; 
this is where sophistry begins. 

309 (p. 651.) De jure magistratuum , 280. If the Estates and the magistratus 
inferiores are not strong enough to control the tyrant, then it becomes permissible 
to call in help from outside: “Licebit etiam saniori parti oppressae auxilia 
aliunde conquirere, praesertim apud Regni confoederatos et amicos.” He 
gives examples from the history of Israel, and of the Romans, and also recalls 
what was done by the Italian patricians through Charles the Great against the 
Lombards. In itself, however, the Kingdom of Christ has nothing to do with 
fighting: “Cum religio ad conscientias pertineat, quibus nullo modo vis inferri 
potest, non videtur ilia ullis armis stabilienda et defendenda, quam ideo 
pracdicatione verbi Dei, precibus ac patientia hactenus potius propagatam 
conspicimus. Extant praeterea loci permulti in scripturis, quibus ostenditur, 
quanta sit inter regna hujus mundi et regnum Christi spirituale differentia” 
( p . 234). To that are added the examples of the Prophets, of Christ, and of the 
Apostles. Only in those days there were no Christian lower magistrates. They 
confronted purely pagan governments, from whom they could not require any 
help for the cause of Christ, and to which they had to submit and suffer. Since 
now, however, there is a Christian State, with lower magistrates who have a 
duty laid upon them by God, the whole matter is quite different. “At ego 
contra praecipuum optimi piique Magistratus munus esse dico, ut quidquid 
mediorum autoritatis et potentiae illi a Deo concessum est, hue totum omnino 
conferat, ut inter sibi subditos Deus ipse vere agnoscatur agnitusque tanquam 
summus regum omnium rex colatur et adoretur.” Thus the authorities must 
establish the true religion, even by force of arms if necessary among their own 
subjects first, then, however, also among others. Certainly all in a legitimate 



PROTESTANTISM 


921 


way. The introduction of the true religion into a country can only take place 
with pure Divine means. “Hoc enim proprie Spiritus sancti opus est instrumentis 
spiritualibus utentis. ,, Thus the knowledge of the true religion is to be spread 
through preaching, and only those who resist in an obstinate way are finally 
to be compelled to accept it! Where, however, the pure religion is already 
established by law, there the authorities are under the obligation under certain 
circumstances to assist the realization of this legal position, also by force of arms. 
Christ and the apostles were private individuals, and had to remain within the 
limits of their “calling”, avoiding the use of arms. But the magistrates of a 
Christian State are, if there is no help for it, justified and obliged to resort to 
arms. They arc also justified in calling on the aid of foreign nations ; this state- 
ment is supported with many examples. This problem is treated similarly by 
the Monarchomachi , Elkan , pp. 116 and i68ff., Cardauns, pp. 5, 104 , where the 
passage from the Vindiciae is quoted: “ ‘Universam (Ecclesiam) singulis, 
singulas ejus partes universis commisit Deus ; itaque si unam ejus partem prin- 
ceps religionis illius curet, alteram vero oppressam, si opera ferre possit deserat 
et negligat, Ecclesiam deseruisse censetur.’ It is one of the established legal 
principles of the period that a prince of another nation may intervene to save 
a people oppressed by a tyrannical government.” 

400 (p. 652.) This pacificism is emphasized by Hartmann: Engl. Frommigkeit , 
p. 26. H. Oncken is instructive, Amerika und die grossen Mdchte ( Studien und 
Versuche zur neueren Geschichte , dedicated to Max Lenz y 1910 ), pp. 427 ff.: “One of 
the peculiar results of the Colonial situation of this State was that from the 
very beginning it was comparatively independent of foreign politics and its 
dangers. And, at least among the Puritan and Baptist elements, it was taken 
for granted that war, the sorrowful privilege of monarchies and oligarchies, 
was to be renounced for religious and democratic reasons. . . . The predomin- 
ance of religious feeling, which affected the development of this State behind the 
scenes in a great variety of ways, required insistently that the people of God 
should be sufficient unto themselves, and carry on their affairs without the use 
of arms ; strict abstention from foreign policy also produced that fundamental 
rationalistic utilitarian element in the American nature which arose from 
sources affected by Natural Law.” But,/). 469: “The first century of American 
history already shows that even a commonwealth which, from the days of the 
Pilgrim Fathers, was controlled by opposite influences, in the long run has to 
obey those laws, which, as inherent necessities, belong to the essence of the 
State and of dominion.” More on this subject in Oncken: Amerikanischer Im- 
perialisms und europaischer Pacifisms, Press. Jahrbb., 1911. Likewise, only with 
a different point of view and outlook for the future, Msaryk in a splendid 
article on Roosevelt from Mdrz , 1910, Nos. 12 and 13. 

401 (p. 653.) Cf. Gss and Luthardt; Alex. Schweizcr: Die Entwickelung des 
Moralsystems in der reformierten Kirche , Theol. Studd. und Kritt., 1830. In all these 
works the development of ethics from the point of view of its content is very 
largely ignored in favour of questions of the relation between philosophical and 
theological ethics, of freedom and the miracle of grace, of justification and of 
the moral law, statements of the problem which unfortunately usually almost 
exclusively dominate the theological treatment of ethics. There is more on the 
content of ethics in the History of Ethics within Organized Christianity , by Thomas 
Hall, New York, 1910. 

402 (p. 654.) On this point see Rieker: Reformierte Kirchenverfassung; Sohm: 
Kirchenrecht, pp. 642-657; von Hofmann: Kirchenverfassungrecht der niederlandischen 
Reformierten; Choisy: La Thiocratie and Uitat chritien ; also his inaugural lecture, 



922 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

L'itat chritien calviniste au 16 *** stick, igog. Here there is a pertinent emphasis 
upon the meaning of the Communion ( p . u): “The Communion is, in fact, 
in the Christian State, an act of obligation, a social and civic act. By participa- 
tion in the Holy Communion the citizen and the inhabitant of Geneva professes 
his faith in the only true God and manifests his intention to submit to His Law. 
It is the homage rendered by the Christian to the Sovereign Legislator and 
Protector of the city, and to Jesus Christ His Son, the Redeemer, the Supreme 
Head of the Church. This is why one cannot admit to the Holy Table those 
who openly violate the Law of God and shamefully outrage His truth. This is 
why, on the other hand, no one can be permitted to abstain from Communion 
without having been officially or publicly excluded from participation in the 
Holy Communion. However, even although it is a civic act, and thus obligatory, 
the Communion ought to be an act of personal piety, etc.” Sociologically, the 
Communion exercises the same function as the Sacrament of Penance in 
Catholicism, hence both attain a power of organization which does not 
characterize Lutheranism. 

403 (P* 655.) On this point I only venture to express my opinion with some 
reserve, since there are no works dealing with this theory of Society. The 
absence of the doctrine of the Three Estates is emphasized by Ricker , p. 184 , 
organization according to possessions in the laws on luxury in Elster , pp. 190-192, 
the continuance of the categories of “callings” and guilds in Choisy , p. 118 , 
note 3, and Gierke: Althusius 2 , 24. Here the “callings” are all treated as con - 
sociationes collegarum , p. 22 , at the same time it is pointed out that they are 
“entirely free associations, which can be formed and severed at will”. On 
equality in the sight of God, see Choisy: L'itat chritien , pp. 484~4 qo. Here also 
belongs the careful avoidance by the ministers of all Amtswiirde (dignity of 
the ministry), which does not allow the development of a conception similar 
to that of the Lutheran conception of the ministry. Concerning the peasantry, 
its neglect is deplored ; see Althusius , p. 25. On the democratic consequence of 
religious equality, see Rieker, p. 122. 

404 (P* 655 •) Cf. Brief e, 7 , 256 on the subject of the necessity for a mutual 
attraction to the knowledge of each other, as the presupposition of marriage, 
its relation to the aim of the holy community ( 7 , 331 and 369 ) ; on the equal 
position of male and female in Christ, and the duties of women compared 
with those of the greatest heroes ( 77 , 193) (to the imprisoned women in Paris) ; 
equality of husband and wife ( 77 , 268 and 451 ) ; always, however, the husband 
is the head of the wife ( 77 , 391 ) ; for the attitude of the State legislation and of 
the Board of Discipline in the control of the sex-life, see numerous examples in 
Choisy: L'itat chritien , especially p. 401 ; for the significance of marriage for 
Society (p. 487) ; on the whole subject, Elster , pp. ig4 ff., and the fine description 
by von Schulze-Gavernitz: Britischer Imperialismus , pp. 47-49: “Puritanism prepared 
the way for a view of sex-relationships which places the responsibility contained 
in procreation in the foreground, and makes possible an ethical construction 
of sex-relationships from the standpoint of the child.” — A monograph on this 
subject would be of great assistance. 

405 (p* 659.) Gobel has rightly recognized this connection with the problem 
of numbers of the masses and of the Christian civilization of the people, and 
in both directions, i.e. the Free Church movement and Pietism, he has em- 
phasized its significance ; he has also seen clearly the resemblance to the Baptist 
movement. The problem began with the exiled communities in foreign lands, 
the Church under k Lasko in London, the Lutheran Calvinistic community 
in Frankfort, and the Dutch groups of exiles on the Lower Rhine (Gdbel, 7 , 326). 



PROTESTANTISM 


923 


Here the communities became thoroughly democratic (/, 340 ff.), they had to 
choose their own officials, and they had no connection with the civil authority. 
Of decisive importance was the community in London under John k Lasko. 
Gobel calls it “a wholesome reconciliation between the Lutherans and their 
lack of a constitution and the Separatist Baptists, and thus he made possible 
upon German soil the founding of a Reformed Church which holds a central 
position between both” ( p . 326). “Under its freely elected preachers and elders 
it constituted itself independently of the bishop and the parish clergy, quite 
freely, according to its own principles; this, however, produced within it a 
clearly marked independent partially Separatist character, which distinguished 
it from the rest of the secular and civic life around ; when, therefore, this 
community migrated, and in an expanded form settled in Emden, Wesel, 
Frankfort, and Strassburg, and when it spread still farther in the region round 
the Main, and especially in the Rhineland, it was, of course, natural that the 
Calvinistic Church which it established in those places naturally bore the same 
kind of ecclesiastical character, and that in its flourishing Christian life it bore 
the stamp of decision and bluntness, of world-renunciation and of hostility to 
the world” (336). The same is true of the older communities in the Netherlands 
before they regained the character of a State Church, which, moreover, was 
always only comparative, as von Hofmann shows ; it is also true of the English 
Puritans, as soon as they were forced into opposition after 1567 by the harsh 
Elizabethan legislation, see Kattenbusch Art. Puritanismus in PRE 3 : they formed 
“private associations which were usually called ‘prophesyings’. The name was 
based upon 1 Cor. xiv. 13. They were societies for mutual edification and for 
the furtherance of a Christian life, and they originated in the community led 
by John k Lasko” ; at the same time the tendency towards Presbyterianism 
was developed: “The secular authority has no power over the Church”; 
they desire “the complete autonomy of the Church”, which for the time being 
was only possible in the form of separation. — Cf. further the description of the 
important resolution of the Synod of Emden, 1571, in Gobel , /, 418: “Thus in 
Emden there was established a Church-order which was set up not for a whole 
country, nor for a whole town, nor for a whole people, but only for those who 
joined it of their own free-will, and who submitted themselves to its order and 
Church discipline, and therefore also could leave it again at any moment.” 
This applied first of all to the communities in the Netherlands. The connection 
between this new Church principle and the opposition of the State authorities 
on the one hand, and with the difficulties of a mass and popular Christianity 
on the other, is developed (/, 423). On the analogy of this Church-order and 
sect-type, see /, 443: “In general the whole (Lower Rhine) Church . . . would 
have gradually fallen into the danger of remaining a sect, or of becoming 
one again; if, on the one hand, they had not remained in connection with 
the at least outwardly strong and flourishing National Church of the Nether- 
lands, and if they had not been preserved from such shrinkage by the develop- 
ment of their theology which took place in a splendid way at the Universities 
of Leyden (from 1575) and Franeker (from 1585), and, on the other hand, 
the union of synods, and, after 1609, their unexpected liberty and extraordinary 
expansion. All these things laid upon this Church the task of becoming, at 
least to some extent, a national or a territorial Church, and thus of leavening 
the whole country and the whole people with its own spirit. In spite of that, 
however, our Calvinistic Church could never entirely deny its Separatist 
origin, and there remained, therefore, within it the opposition between the 
world and Christianity, between the worldling and the Christian, between 



924 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

human statements and the Word of God, between the Papacy and the Gospel, 
so that as Church discipline slackened and the Church and Christian life 
became more secular, attempts were ever made anew, both from outside and 
from inside the Church, to restore the old severity and keenness, whether 
through the gathering together of individual awakened souls within the 
congregation, or through the separation of the latter from the great secularized 
Church, and the formation of special groups of their own.” This explains even 
at the present time the character of Church life in the Wuppertal and the 
Pietism of Elberfeld and Barmen. This applies, however, also mutatis mutandis 
to all territories in which Calvinism is predominant, owing to the idea of the 
holy community and of ecclesiastical autonomy over against the Stafce. 

406 (p. 660.) For the development of the ‘‘subsidiary Calvinistic conception 
of the Church”, cf. Rieker , pp. 190-203; Kuyper , 52-60, y 1-100, sees in this the 
distinctive fundamental tendency of Calvinism which was not quite plain to 
its early leaders; the excellent book by Rothenbiicher : Die Trennung von Stoat und 
Kirche , 1908, describes the rise and the nature of the principle ; the enthusiastic 
religious glorification of the principle as that of modern religion and the 
Church in general in A. Vinet: Essai sur la manifestation des convictions religieuses, 
et sur la separation de I'tglise de Vttat , 1842 (translated into Geunan by Spengler , 
1845 ), and also La liberti des Cultes 2 , 1892. Cf. also Troeltsch : Trennung von Staat 
und Kirche , der Staatliche Religionsunterricht und die theologischen Fakultdten , 1907; 
to my joy Rothenbiicher agrees essentially with the account I have given here 
of the Baptist movement and its origin. For the “Natural-Law” character of 
the Calvinistic Church conception, see Sohm: Kirchenrecht , /, 655 ff., 697 ff. 

407 (p. 661.) It is extremely important to emphasize the fact that in early 
Calvinism the conception of Truth was such that it made it impossible for it 
to renounce dependence on the brachium saeculare , or to allow different forms 
of Church life to exist alongside of each other; cf. Troeltsch: Trennung , etc. 
When the Netherlanders wanted to organize their Church life upon lines which 
made room for the existence of various churches, the Genevese characterized 
this as a despicable principle of toleration like that advocated by Castellio : 
Rachfahl , II, 727-75/. The churches of the Lower Rhine, which were practically 
Free Churches, still retained explicitly the idea of a State Church as the normal 
thing ; see Simons: Freikirche , Volks kirche, Landeskirche, 1895, p. 12. WhenjCalvinists 
found themselves under Catholic rule, and were forced to organize on Free 
Church lines, they always did it as a temporary arrangement, expecting the 
victory of the Truth, and maintaining that it is the duty of a ruler to submit 
to the Truth ( Rachfahl , II, p. 881 ; Rothenbiicher , p. 20). Where the hope of victory 
had been given up, and the Calvinistic Church life had to be organized along- 
side of other confessions, this still did not mean a general spirit of ecclesiastical 
liberty, it simply meant that toleration was restricted to Catholicism, Lutheran- 
ism, and Calvinism ; it is the toleration of minorities when there is no help for it, 
but it is not the principle of liberty of worship and of conscience ; see Rachfahl , 
//, p. 72#, and Frank Puaux: Les pricurseurs frangais de la tolirance au iy^ m * siicle, 
Paris, 1881; Rothenbiicher, p. 63. The Pilgrim Fathers returned to a strict 
theocracy, in which the Baptists were punished with death because they 
represented the idea of toleration ( Rothenbiicher , 1 20-1 23 ). — Nor is it possible to 
say that Calvinism was organized on voluntaryist lines. Rieker has asserted this 
against Sohm, who claims that there is a relationship between Calvinism and 
the Law of Nature, and he might have emphasized it still more strongly (see 
P • 133 )• Independency is expressly rejected (see p. 82), and Simons: Nieder- 
rheinisches Synodal - und Gemeindeleben , 189J, p. 75. The idea of a contract, held so 



PROTESTANTISM 


925 


strongly by Calvinism, applies to the State and the relation to the State, but 
not to the rise of the Church itself, as Rieker himself makes plain ( p . 79). In the 
refugee churches of John k Lasko, which lived under a government with a 
different religious outlook, and then in the Netherlands, H. von Hoffmann (Das 
Kirchenverfassungsrecht der niederlandischen Reformierten , 1902) makes it plain that 
the Church membership, both of those who had previously belonged to other 
forms of religion and of those who were already baptized, was only gained 
“through a covenant (contract)”; thus for the first time the Church here 
appears as a corporation, in the sense in which the word is used in modern 
law ( p . 86). Only the expression is expanded in modern legal language, and in 
this case it is not quite applicable since the correlated idea of a “right to leave 
the Church ( Austrittsrecht )” does not exist ( p . 83). All that it comes to really is 
this, that it provides a way by which individuals could take a personal share 
in an institution which existed by Divine appointment ; the Church Council, 
however, was always regarded as the primary method for exercising the royal 
sovereignty of Christ ; thus, wherever there is such a centre, it is the duty of 
individuals to join this institution, which is the one and only body in which 
Truth and Redemption reside (see pp. 87 , 88, 75, and 96) ! Freedom to form 
churches on a voluntary basis is not a Calvinistic idea, but it comes from the 
Congregationalists and the Baptists ; see Rothenbiicher, p. 90. Calvinism, there- 
fore, has always used it only for the outward constitutional form, it has never 
formed part of its nature ; see Rieker , 1 90-174. — The “Natural-Law” conception 
of the Church is, moreover, an intellectual method, which has grown out of 
the juridical way of thinking ; it has been used by all kinds of churches, and 
can easily be used in support of the idea of an institutional Church. In my 
opinion it has nothing whatever to do with the Calvinistic idea of the Church ; 
see Rothenbiicher , 68-72. — On the Scottish Covenants (with to some extent the 
text of the same), see Champlin Barrage: The Church Covenant Idea , Its Origin and 
Development , Philadelphia, 1904. — That in the Free Church movement there is at 
bottom a new conception of Truth which differs from that of early Calvinism 
is shown characteristically by Vinet: Darlegungen, p. 276 : “If the National 
Church system were to make an end of all sects, or were to make it impossible 
for them to arise, this would not be a cause for triumph, but for reproach. . . . 
There is qp life where there are no sects ; uniformity is a sign of death.” Cf. also 
p. 278 and p. 206. “It has been said that seeking for the Truth is more important 
than the Truth itself ; this might also be applied to religion in general, if, as we 
believe, it is right to say the first of all truths is that we ought to wish and seek 
for the Truth. The Truth is only half-realized if it is not sought. Here seeking 
is as important as possession. . . . This, we admit, is the heart of our theory” 
(p. 299). The real State Church system only arose, according to Vinet, out of the 
Reformation, and he considers that it is something which ought never to 
have been born (p. 279). Historically Vinet appeals chiefly to America (p. 996 ) ; 
this also illustrates the connection between the Free Church principle and 
democracy (p. 966). This democracy, however, only means the right of the 
people to self-determination ; it does not mean a democratic Church con- 
stitution, and there is no equalitarian removal of that patriarchalism in Society 
or in the sociological fundamental theory (p. 977). Vinet considers this 
genuine Calvinism, but in reality it is spiritual idealism with its subjective 
tendencies, 

408 (p. 662.) On the whole subject, see the excellent article in PRE* by 
hoofs entitled Kongregationalismus. The great work by Dexter: Congregationalism 
of the Last Three Hundred Years , New York , 1880, is out of print, and I was unable 



926 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

to obtain it. Further, see the highly interesting book by Burrage: The Church 
Covenant Idea , which gives numerous examples of these Covenants in full, follows 
their development, and treats in detail their resemblance to and connection 
with the Baptist movement; see p. 46: “In the same year, 1580, it is now 
generally admitted, Browne very likely came into contact with foreign Ana- 
baptists, and doubtless learned their simple ideas of forming their brotherhood 
churches or societies by a Bundy or a covenant with God. Their idea was that 
a Church may be composed only of believers. Browne accepted this view, but, 
following the opinion of his time in general, added, ‘and their seed*. ... It may 
be added that neither Browne nor any of his earlier followers seem to have 
been influenced to any great extent by the Scottish Covenants.” Further, the 
Covenant of the Brownists, and of all other Covenants, was not merely a 
Covenant with God, but also with their fellow Church members; see the 
passage in Browne's own Book which showeth the life and manners of all true 
Christians, p. 57: “How must the Church be first planted and gathered under 
one kind of government? First by a Covenant and condition made in God’s 
behalfe. Secondly, by a Covenant and condition made on our behalfe. Thirdly, 
by using the sacrament of Baptisme to seale those conditions and Covenants.” 
Cf. further Burrage: The true story of Robert Browne (1550?- 1633), Oxford , igo6. 
Here are the most important “spiritual” passages, p. 36: “There (speaking 
against the external Churchmanship of the Anglicans) is no duty, law, deed, 
cause, question, or plea, etc., which ought not to be spiritual, or is not deter- 
mined by the Divine and spiritual right, law and Word of God.” P. 20: Con- 
fronting Anglicans and Presbyterians he gives the motto: “The Kingdom of 
God should be within you.” P. 21 , against the use of Latin: “They spake the 
languages, saith the Scripture, as the Spirit gave them utterance.” This con- 
nection with “spiritual” religion is still more important than that with the 
Baptist movement ; on the difference between both see below. To Burrage we 
owe the discovery of several of Browne’s writings, upon which his new book is 
based: The Retractation of R. B., 1907, and A New Tear's Gift , 1904 ; for the use 
of these two books I am indebted to the kindness of the publisher. 

409 (p. 663.) On this point, see Powicke: Henry Barrow, Separatist {1550?- 1593), 
London, 1900 , a very instructive book and most illuminating for the Church- 
history of the period. Here (pp. 215 ff.): “On the whole it may b^said that 
Barrow was far nearer to the Anabaptists than he knew. . . . Indeed, apart 
from a number of comparatively superficial differences, due partly to circum- 
stances, and partly to a more scrupulous fidelity to their common principle of 
reverence for Scripture — there was nothing in the sphere of Church practice 
which need have held Barrow and the Baptists apart, except the doctrine of 
Baptism. . . . But this refers only to his ecclesiastical position. As to theological 
differences, the case is not the same. Here what meets us is diametrical opposi- 
tion rather than development. Barrow was a Calvinist, and accepted all the 
implications of this creed with full consent.” Powicke regards the retention of 
Infant Baptism as due merely to his fear of being called an Anabaptist ; I believe, 
however, that the deeper reasons which have already been mentioned were 
the cause of this. He rejects both the Baptist doctrine of free will and also the 
restriction of the body of the redeemed to those who have become members of 
a voluntary Church; this means the connection with still another Church 
conception ( p . 123) ; against equality (p. 94), asceticism (p. 149 ) ; we must note 
anticipations of Quakerism ( p . 118): “B. anticipated George Fox in some 
points, e.g. in his refusal to take an oath on the Bible; in his objection to 
naming the days of the week, Sunday, Monday, etc., and in his dislike of 



PROTESTANTISM 


927 

titles.” The Separatist-Baptist result of Puritanism (pp. 153 ff.) ; it is one of 
Whitgift’s main arguments, and individual Puritans seem rather embarrassed 
by Barrow. For the “spiritual” features, see especially the account on pp . 92-93* 
where Barrow is being examined ; Barrow appeals to the exposition of Scripture 
through the Spirit which is the fruit of the Word : “Andrews : ‘This savoureth 
of a private spirit.* — Barrow : ‘This is the spirit of Christ and of His apostles, 
and most publicly they submitted their doctrines to the trial of all men. 
So do I.* — A. : ‘What, are you an apostle?* B. : ‘No, but I have the spirit of 
the apostles.’ A.: ‘What, the spirit of the apostles?* B. : ‘Yes, the spirit of 
the apostles.* A. : ‘What, in that measure?* B. : ‘In that measure that God has 
imparted ynto me, though not in that measure that the apostles had by any 
comparison. Yet the same spirit. There is but one spirit.* ** This seems to me 
still more important than the resemblance to the Baptist movement, which is 
also strongly emphasized by hoofs. Could it possibly be that Schwenkfeld’s 
influence is behind this? 

410 (p. 665.) On this point see in particular Burrage: The Church Covenant Idea ; 
the possibility of developing in the direction of the Baptists, the Independents, 
and a new conception of a Church of the people, pp. 167-169. “Yet certainly 
they would not turn for rescue to the Baptists, whose baptism on profession of 
faith they had spurned, and thus lay open their full indebtedness to Anabaptist 
principles.** Powicke sees this question from the same point of view, showing very 
clearly hpw the Puritans swayed between the idea of a Calvinistic National 
Church and a Separatist voluntary Church; the opposition of Whitgift is 
characteristic ; he held that without a settled authority in Church and State, 
and without the agreement of both, the principle of the unity of Society was 
threatened. — The transition from the State Church to Separatism was made 
possible to the Puritans through the purchase of livings, when they then were 
able to choose their own clergyman and remain loyal to him as a congregation ; 
there were such cases even before Robert Browne, see Burrage: New Facts Con- 
cerning Robinson , 1910, pp. 31 , 24 jf. Also frequently Puritan clergy, whose 
preaching licence had been taken away from them preached in private houses 
or in the open air, and gathered congregations round them on a personal basis ; 
see Dexter: The England and Holland of the Pilgrims, Boston , 1906, p. 123. 

411 (p. 666.) Cf. Loofs: Kongregationalismus ; in particular also Dexter's book, 
which has Already been mentioned, which is full of detail on social and cultural 
history, also the section in Powicke on the Amsterdam Church, and also that in 
Burrage: Church Covenant , or the “ Half-way Covenant ", pp. 169-174. There also the 
adoption of the Covenant principle by the Baptists. The ecclesiastical democracy 
of the Barrowists was not really democratic in spirit, but it was regarded as the 
agreement produced by the Spirit of Christ, and therefore supernatural in 
character, for which reason it was always laid down that all resolutions should 
proceed from prayer and meditation. Cf. Powicke (p. 271), where Ainsworth 
declares : “Christ’s ruling power, which the Papists say is in the Pope, we say 
not (as this man calumniateth us) that it is in the body of the congregation, 
nor that it is in the prelates . . . nor (as the Puritans) that it is in the presby- 
tery . . . but that it is in Christ Himself. . . . The Word of God is given to all 
and every member of the Church to read and exercise privately ; but publicly — 
in the Church — there is a double use of it in prophecy and in office.” Dexter 
sums this up thus : “The mainspring of power for people and officers alike is 
in the living Presence of Christ.** This is undoubtedly the point of view of 
‘spiritual* religion; these statements exactly resemble those of Schwenkfeld , 
see Sippel: Schwenkfeld Ch . W, 1911, p. 869: The organization is, according to the 



928 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

apostolic example, not the work of the believers, but that of the Holy Ghost. 
The practical control of the community is not the business of certain elected 
representatives, but of the living and ruling Christ. He alone represents the 
government of the Church. Jesus rules in spirit through those who are endowed 
with the gifts of the Spirit, both the individual congregation and the Church 
as a whole. In the community of the faithful the charismatic offices and gifts, 
according to i Cor. xii, manifest themselves for the common good. The famous 
farewell discourse of Robinson ( Weingarten , 33; Dexter, 587), with his exhortation 
to the group not to cling to his (Robinson’s) authority, but to expect and wait 
for new illumination, is likewise conceived from the point of view of “spiritual” 
religion ; but it is not, on that account, to be overestimated, since a spirituality 
of this kind proceeds always from the Calvinistic interpretation of the Bible, 
and is only rejected by a rigid ecclesiastical orthodoxy like that of Lutheranism 
and Geneva. It is from this point of view that we must also understand Robin- 
son’s later concessions in the direction of spiritual fellowship with the members 
of other churches, and even his readiness in the settlement in Virginia to 
acknowledge an external civil authority of the bishops ( Dexter , 568 ff.!); the 
practice of lay-preaching and of the lay-criticism of the pastors is also to be 
understood from this point of view. This does not exclude the idea that in 
ideal conditions there ought to be only Congregationalist churches, and this is 
what happened in New England. Dexter , 567 thus describes the aim of their 
emigration: “Nor could they bring themselves to abandon the missionary 
purpose which they had cherished from the first, that they might demonstrate 
somewhere the value to mankind of a pure and democratic Church.” — For their 
history and development in New England, see the important work by Doyle: 
The English in America , London , 1887, and H. K. Caroll: The Religious Forces of 
the United States , New York , 1833. A good deal oflight is thrown on this subject 
by Roger Williams in his Bloudy Tenent , which will be discussed later; the 
Congregationalist churches will not allow the existence of any other churches, 
but they do not force all the colonists to become full members; in the first 
case they preserve the Calvinist idea of unity ; in the second, the subjective 
liberty of conscience ; of all they require outward conformity to the Law of 
Nature and to the Christian moral law ; thus there is one section of the popula- 
tion without any Church at all, but these people must at least hear the Word 
of God ; see Bl. Ten., 250! ' 

412 (p. 669.) On this point see Carlyle: CromwelUs Letters and Speeches a , 1846 ; 
Gooch: History of English Democratic Ideas , Cambridge, 1838; Shaw: History of the 
English Church, 1640-1660 , London, igoo; Glass: The Barebones Parliament, 1633 , 
London, i88g; Firth: CromweWs Army , London, 1302; Gardiner: Cromwell, 1833: 
all these works are very important, and to a great extent they supersede 
Weingarten 9 s classic work Die Revolutionskirchen Englands, 1868. Weingarten has 
made too little distinction between the groups within Independency, and he 
has altogether misunderstood the distinction between the Baptist movement 
and ecclesiastical Protestantism. — Weingarten 9 s excellent account of Cromwell, 
however, agrees entirely with the article by Kolde on Cromwell in PR 3 . The story 
of the religious development of Cromwell, of his relation to Harrison, of his 
adoption of “spiritual” ideas, still needs to be cleared up. “Spiritual” religion 
is represented in its extremist form by his two chaplains, Dell and Saltmarsh, 
as will be shown later. This also is a point which Weingarten has not noticed, 
and which distinguishes Cromwell from the actual Baptist movement. Here 
are some “spiritual” expressions: “The true succession is through the Spirit, 
given in its measure” (Kolde, IV, 341) ; the formulation of the only sign of a 



PROTESTANTISM 


929 


real Christianity as of those “who believe in the remission of sins through the 
blood of Christ, and in free justification through the blood of Christ, who live 
upon the grace of God ,, } is Pietistic in its outlook ( Kolde , 342) ; “spiritual” also 
are the signs of a true minister required by the Examination Board : “They 
must not admit a man unless they were able to discerne something of the 
grace of God in him ; grace of God which has to be so inquired for, as not 
foolishly or senselessly, but so far as man could judge according to the rules 
of charity” (Glass, 133) ; “spiritual” and not Baptist is his whole Church 
principle of “comprehension”, which allowed different groups to exist freely 
within a Church which merely carried on an external administration: “A 
system of*State aid and regulation of parishes leaving to individual churches 
a free hand for variety of doctrine and freedom in forms of worship.” — Glass , 
131; Cromwell’s speech, 1657: “I think if there be freedom of judgment it is 
here. Here are three sorts of godly men whom you are to take care for, for 
whom you have provided in your settlement. And how could you put the 
selection upon the Presbyterians without by possibility excluding all those 
Anabaptists, all those Independents? As you have put it in this way, that, 
though a man be any of those three judgments, if he have the root of the matter 
in him he may bp admitted” (Glass, 133). Francis Rous, likewise, the untiring 
Convener and worker in all the Ecclesiastical Commissions of the Long Parlia- 
ment and of Cromwell, was also full of similar “spiritual” ideas; this is his 
declaration quoted by Glass , 48: “From Christ’s time place is approved by 
truth and not truth by place. He that freed true worship from being tied to 
Jerusalem, and tied it to the service in spirit which may be in all places, gave 
true religion a large scope, even as large as the world itself.” Further, Rous, 
as is well known, is a mystic whom Ritschl: Gesch. d. Prot., I, 128-130, considers 
influenced by “mediaeval example”. “As in the English Church Calvinism 
of the Independent type came very near to the Anabaptists, so this work 
(by Rous) proves that in that direction they had also drawn upon the in- 
dispensable example of mysticism!” Also in the whole view of “Church 
comprehension” there are “spiritual” arguments and motives ; cf. Shaw, II, 75, 
where this declaration is made to the Scots with reference to Ircton’s report : 
“For the toleration of all religions and forms of worship that their letter 
objects, wg know not whom they intend in that charge; as for the truth and 
power of religion, it being a thing intrinsical between God and the soul, and 
the matters of faith and the Gospel being such as no natural light doth reach 
unto, we conceive there is no human power of coercion thereunto, nor to 
restrain man from believing what God suffers their judgment to be persuaded 
of.” There are suggestions of a connection with Schwenkfeld in Sippell: Ch.W, 
ign, p. g66, and William Dell's Programm, p. 81, where the reference to Osiander 
would have been better if applied to Schwenkfeld. To the extent, as we shall 
see later, that Schwenkfeld’s teaching was already a combination of “spiritual” 
and Baptist ideas, it naturally contains indirect Baptist influences. — For the 
relation of Cromwell to Harrison, see Glass, 61 and 64; Firth, 318, 341 ff., 370 . — 
On the Independent army chaplains, Dell, Saltmarsh, Sedgwick, Hugh 
Peters, s tt Firth, 320 ff., in Lilburn’s regiment, John Canne; in Cromwell’s 
John Owen, Thomas Patient, Robert Stapylton, see Firth, 324 and 323-327, 
On John Owen, the friend and confidant of Cromwell, as a Pietist who was 
above all sectional interests and respected by all, see Heppe: Gesch. des Pietrsmus, 
*879> PP- 43ff-'y Dell and Saltmarsh are “spiritual” idealists; Hugh Peters, 
originally a Puritan, developed into a democratic Radical (Gooch, 134-136 and 
j 75); Canne, who was first a Baptist preacher, became likewise radically 

VOL. II. HH 



930 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Anabaptist (Gooch, 174 ff.); John Goodwin was originally an Anglican clergy- 
man, but later he developed in the direction of “spiritual” religion (Gooch, 
1 3 2 ff .). — Cromwell himself had a strongly Calvinistically conservative strain. 
His conception of the Law of Nature was distinctly a class conception : “A 
nobleman, a gentleman, a yeoman, the distinction between these is rightly 
of great interest to the nation. Was not the natural constitution of the nation 
not almost trod underfoot with scorn and contempt by people with levelling 
principles?” (Bernstein, 630 ). As from the point of view of doctrine he was a 
Calvinist who held predestinarian views, his conception of revolution and of 
civil war was first of all that of the Calvinists and Huguenots. But the more, 
in the social chaos, things became confused, the more he explained events and 
inward resolutions as revelations and guidance from God for the course of 
events willed by God. This is fanaticism. He also tended to cherish the expecta- 
tion of the speedy return of Christ, and in connection with that he cherished 
an indefinite hope of a universal reordering of conditions in the spirit of the 
Christian idea. But the maintenance of civic and State order, the rejection of 
all pure democracy and Communism, the appeal to the army as “a lawful 
power called by God”, the appeal to the salus populi as the rational legal basis 
of the State — all these, on the other hand, are Calvinistic characteristics, in 
absolute contrast to the Chiliastic idea of reform, a view which he held for a 
time, owing to the difficulty of knowing the Will of God, but which he finally 
regarded as a point of view which led to the wanton destruction of *11 order. 
After the dissolution of the Parliament of the Saints he returned with increasing 
decision to the old Calvinistic theory of authority, since he regarded himself 
as the legal authority, called to this position by the people in the absence of all 
other legal authority. Of Independency he retained nothing beyond liberty of 
conscience. Otherwise his policy was such as could only be conceived on the 
basis of the Calvinistic relative Natural Law; he was always sure that “the 
cause of Christ and the cause of the people agree well together”. Cf. my article 
Moralisten, Englische in PRE 3 , XIII, 443-448. 

418 (p. 670.) On Locke, see Bastide and Lezius , especially Rothenbiicher, where 
the further development of the philosophy of law and of the State is described 
(pp. 46-112). At the same time it is characteristic how everywhere the distinction 
is made between the theorists who have been more or less determined by 
Independent American ideas, and those who defend and exalt the modern 
Enlightenment against the Church. R. considers that the latter appear pre- 
dominantly in Catholic countries where people are accustomed to a uniform 
religion, and where the Catholic unity is only replaced by the Enlightenment. 
The latter type is that to which the Deist religion of the State of Rousseau 
belongs, alongside of which freedom is given for particular private convictions. 
Also from this side Rousseau is anything but an inheritor of Calvinistic or even 
neo-Calvinistic ideas ; see also Jellinek: Erkldrung der Menschen- und Burgerreckte *, 
1904; also my Trennung von Staat und Kirche , 1303. — On the practical American 
form, see also the works named on p. 328, and also Rothenbiicher, 116-170 . 
When Hdgermann points to the Law of Nature and to Locke, he does not 
realize the idea of the Christian Natural Law which is concealed within this* 
theory, nor the way in which Locke is affected by Independency. Natural 
Law and Christian arguments are not in opposition as he thinks they are ( p . 151). 
Hence Methodism in America has found such a response, and from the social 
point of view there is there still to-day a very massive orthodoxy and strict 
morality. Usually the European of the Enlightenment never quite understands 
this phenomenon. 



PROTESTANTISM 


93i 


414 (p* 67°.) For the fact that the Calvinism of the present day has in some 
directions very largely accepted the Free Church principle, see Vinet and 
Kuyper , and the great survey of Rothenbiicher of the Free Churches in existence 
at the present time. — For the connection between this Church principle and 
political democracy, see Rothenbiicher , 472. — The Pilgrim Fathers, even while 
they were still on the Mayflower , made a political covenant on the pattern of 
the Church Covenant ; see Barrage: Church Covenant , pp. 86 and 93. “By 1639 the 
Covenant idea had become so popular in the minds of the Massachusetts and 
New Haven colonists that even towns were organized by covenant.” Cf. also 
Jellinek: Erklarung,pp. 36-39. The connection between Calvinism and democracy 
is almost t&ken for granted in modern Calvinist literature, whether in the form 
in which Christianity and the Bible are completely identified with democracy, 
or in the theory that Calvinism is the final form of development of Christianity 
in which democracy and religion have finally become one, and which, therefore, 
is destined to triumph over the world. We find these ideas in Vinet, Kuyper, and 
Rauschenbusch. The French emphasize the agreement between Christianity and 
democracy ; see the work which has already been mentioned of Mialys ; further, 
P. Sabatier: A propos de la separation 2 , 1900, and R. Allier: Une revolution, 1806. 
Choisy, who is sudi an excellent Calvin scholar, closes his inaugural lecture at 
Geneva entitled L'etat chretien calviniste, 1909, with the words : “To sum up ; 
the theocratic regime, which was carried out by the Christian State of Geneva, 
was a rude but salutary training in justice, morality, and virile piety for that 
epoch. It prepared the way for liberty of conscience in the future and for 
the development of the spirit of fraternity and solidarity in the Christian 
democracy” (p. 32). On Dissent in England, see von der Goltz: Staat und Kirche 
in Grossbritannien, Preuss. Jahrbb., 84, 1896. Originally this union of Calvinism 
and democracy was only achieved to a limited extent in England, where the 
Independents of the Calvinistic turn of mind, especially Ireton and Cromwell, 
as far as possible remained even politically Conservative and legitimists, and it 
was only groups like the “Levellers”, which had been influenced by Baptist 
ideas, which represented pure democracy; see Rothschild: Der Gedanke einer 
geschriebenen Verfassung in der englischen Revolution, 1903 , also Gooch: English 
Democratic Ideas. Cromwell, indeed, declared in 1654 ( Carlyle , III, 29): “liberty 
of conscience and liberty of the subject — two as glorious things to be contended 
for as any God has given us”, but he immediately adds : “yet both these 
abused for the patronizing of villainies”. In this, from his relative conservative 
standpoint, he rejects radical democracy. His own views on the connection 
between the Free Church movement and democracy were peculiarly confused. 
— This union of ideas was only clearly perceived, free from all the elements of 
early Calvinism, in America ; on this subject, see the great work of Tocqueville: 
La democratic en Amirique 8 , 1830. In England it is only the work of the nineteenth 
century, where Dissent after the reforms of 1832 became the support of 
Liberalism and of democracy, and at the same time permeated these ideas 
with religious enthusiasm; see Ostrogorski: La democratic et V organisation des 
partis politiques, /, 1903 , pp. 21-26 ; also Held, p. 48. 

414a (p. 671.) On the sense of superiority in Calvinism in this respect, see 
Kuyper, p. 13: “Lutheranism remained ecclesiastical and theological ; it is only 
Calvinism which both inside and outside the Church has left its mark upon all 
forms of human life. No one speaks of Lutheranism as the creation of a distinc- 
tive way of living ; even the name is scarcely mentioned, whereas all who know 
history agree more and more in calling Calvinism the creator of a distinctive 
world of human life.” P . 26: “It is as clear as day that the main force in the 



932 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

development of the human race after Babylon, Egypt, Greece, and the Roman 
Empire, and after the Papal supremacy, has finally come into the hands of the 
Calvinistic peoples of Western Europe”; p. 37: “Calvinism means the com- 
pleted evolution of Protestantism which in the sixteenth century led the 
development of our race into a new and higher phase . . . Therefore everyone 
who refuses to start from the standpoint of atheism or anti-theism must go 
back to Calvinism in order to learn to think and to live according to the 
Calvinistic principle, naturally in our day in a form which corresponds to the 
life of our time.” Or cf. Dexter , pp. 594 ff>: “In the Plymouth Colony, and later 
in that of Massachusetts, the Free Church system flourished. It had a large 
part in shaping the thought and life of the colonists. It tinctured thefr political 
idea and aided powerfully in preparing the way for American Independence, 
and ever since their day it has continued a potent factor for good in our 
national life. In the Mother Country also, although hampered by many 
hostile conditions and not wholly free even yet to do its best work, it has 
become conspicuous and effective, and during the nineteenth century it has 
accomplished much of what it could not bring to pass in the seventeenth. . . . 
It would be a mistake to regard the Pilgrim Colony in America ... as merely 
ecclesiastical in origin and development ... it was one of the earliest manifesta- 
tions of that resistless impulse of expansion and conquest . . . which changed 
the whole face of the globe. It opened a fresh and vitally important era in 
human history. It was practically the beginning of the civilized permanent 
settlement of an almost unknown Continent. It prepared the way for the birth 
of a new and mighty nation. The world’s debt to the Pilgrims is not limited 
by any denominational lines. It is universal. The adherence of the Free Church 
systems may fairly claim to possess special justification for pride in the Pilgrim 
history, but nobody can monopolize it. All lovers of intelligence and civil as 
well as religious liberty have the right to share it.” This is Americanism in its 
relative connection with Calvinism and sectarianism. — From the opposite 
point of view Shaw complains in his English Church , /, 316: “The earliest 
Reformation had never proclaimed such a separation of the civil from the 
ecclesiastical government. It was the fatal and malignant heritage of the 
genius and life of Calvin, and how adversely it has affected the later history of 
European progress can hardly yet be estimated.” — There are* numerous 
excellent observations in Tocqueville's book on the special character of Puritan 
Anglo-Saxon democracy contrasted with nationalist French democracy. 
In /, 5/ he gives rightly as the guiding principle of the whole the words out 
of the old Matthew Magnolia Americana: “Let us not delude ourselves about 
that which we call our independence. In reality, there is a kind of corrupted 
freedom which is common to men and animals and which consists in doing 
whatever one pleases. This kind of freedom is the enemy of all authority, 
it endures rules and regulations unwillingly ; in giving way to this we descend 
below our own level ; it is the enemy of truth and of peace, and God Himself 
has found it necessary to speak out openly against it. But there is a civil and 
moral freedom whose strength is in unity, and to protect which is, indeed, the 
nature of all power ; this is the freedom to do fearlessly all that is right and good. 
This holy freedom in all fateful hours we will defend, and for this, if necessary, 
we will sacrifice our lives.” Cf. also the observations in the preceding pages 
on the fundamental sociological theory of Calvinism; also Ostrogorski , /, 93: 
“From the moment when the individual soul awakened to affirm himself 
before God and Society ‘man* had entered into the social and political life of 
England, never to leave it. In England he entered by the door of ethics, as he 



PROTESTANTISM 


S>33 

penetrated into France by that of logic.” Cf. also in a similar vein, Morley: 
Life of Gladstone , 1 , 163 . 

416 (p. 673.) On the history of toleration and the liberty of worship, which 
goes far beyond mere tolerance, see the article entitled Tolerant, by Friedberg, 
in PRE 8 ; Rothenbiicher, 74 ff., 1 16-131 ; Jellinek : Die Erklarung der Menschen - und 
Biirgerrechte 2 , 1304; especially Ruffini: La libertd religiosa , I, Storia della idea, igoo. 
For the very limited tolerance of the Brownists, Barrowists, and Pilgrim 
Fathers, see the works which have already been mentioned by Burrage, Powicke, 
and Dexter', in New England, see Jellinek, pp. 39-43; toleration and the Long 
Parliament, Shaw, II, 33-97 ; among the Independents, Jellinek, 36; Shaw, II, 
46-32; Goodwin and a memorial by the Brownists shows that they went a 
good way in this direction, cf. Glass, p. 21 f (here with the “spiritual” argument, 
“Let every spirit praise the Lord”) ; on Cromwell and religious toleration, 
see Glass and Kolde; Speech III ( Carlyle , III, 68) deals with the question of the 
fundamental laws which every system of legislation must regard as natural 
rights. “Again, is not Liberty of conscience a fundamental? . . . Liberty of 
conscience is a natural right ; and he that would have it ought to give it. . . . 
Liberty of conscience, truly that is a thing which ought to be very reciprocal ! 

. . . This, I say, is a fundamental. It is for us and the generations to come.” 
Otherwise this toleration was very limited, as Glass proves with detailed 
illustrations. Milton travelled farthest along this line ; in addition to the usual 
Puritan-independent and “spiritual” motives he added the broader element 
of rationalism, which, however, remained confined to the idea of the Christian 
State. Locke took up the subject at this point. — Complete independence and 
freedom were demanded only by the Baptists and the spiritual idealists of the 
time. For the former see Tracts on Liberty of Conscience and Persecution, 1614-1661 
(a publication of the Hanserd Knollys Society, 1846). Roger Williams, whose 
name is held in high honour in America at the present day, was one of the 
most important representatives of this spirit ; see The Bloudy Tenent of Persecution 
for Cause of Conscience of 1664, published with a biographical introduction by 
the same Society, 1848. R. W. was a Puritan of a very devout kind, who laid 
great stress on “holiness of life”, and as such he was strongly opposed to any 
union of Church and State, a combination which had already taken place in 
the Congregationalism of New England ; closely connected with that he was 
rigidly democratic and keen on an ethical system of politics, which led him 
(like Penn at a later date) to desire to deal with the Indians on a basis of 
justice and kindness, and he established missions amongst them; from this 
point of view he opposed the Colonial Charters, which made grants of land 
belonging to the Indians without any regard for their rights. This fact, together 
with protests against the mingling of affairs of Church and State, led to his 
being banished from the colony. In Providence he founded a purely democratic 
State with entire religious liberty (for the fortunes of this enterprise, see Doyle), 
and went over to the Baptists in 1639 (the biography remarks : “Infant Baptism 
and persecution, as in other churches, in sisterly embrace together”, XXVI, 
and mentions, p. XXXIII, a Baptist asserting as one of the results of Infant 
Baptism that “hence also collaterally have been brought the power of the 
civil magistrate into the church”, which shows a right sense of the fact that 
Infant Baptism implies the Church of the people or the National Church, and 
that this means finally the domination of the State in the Church). Roger 
Williams did not remain a Baptist for very long, however; he then gave up 
belonging to any denomination at all, believing (like Schwenkfeld, Coornheert, 
and Franck, as well as the Collegiants) that the true constitution of the Early 



934 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Church had long ago disappeared, since the days of the Apostles, in fact, and 
that now there was no longer in existence any Church at all which had been 
instituted by God. Thus he then adopted a position which was entirely indi- 
vidualistic and non-denominational (XXVII). His Bloudy Tenenty 1644, was 
linked on to a Baptist treatise in favour of liberty of conscience, which is 
defended (XXX). Only in the same year did the Independent, John Goodivin, 
come forward. R. W. went too far for the Independents : “They are willing to 
grant liberty only to those sound in fundamentals, the identical views of their 
brother Congregationalists of America” (XXXV). The feeling of the Bloudy 
Tenent is radically individualistic, although the argument as a whole is the 
Baptist argument, and only combines with this the specific Puritan c sentiment 
of superiority to the world and of possessing a victorious mission to spread the 
Truth. “Spiritual” elements are not emphasized particularly, although it 
seems probable that the writer was acquainted with and influenced by spiritual 
and mystical literature. The following quotation seems to bear this out: 
“Whatever worship, ministry, ministration, the best and purest, are practised 
without faith and true persuasion that they are the true institution of God, 
they are sin, sinful worship, ministers, etc. . . . Without search and trial no 
man attains this faith and right persuasion. . . . Having tried we must hold 
fast upon the loss of a crown” (p. 8). His “inwardness” often reminds us of 
Luther’s earlier period ( p . 118): “I hence observe, that here being in this 
Scripture (2 Cor. x. 4) held forth a twofold state, a civil state and a spiritual, 
civil officers and spiritual, civil weapons and spiritual weapons, civil vengeance 
and punishment and a spiritual vengeance and punishment. . . . These states 
being of different natures and considerations, as far differing as spirit from 
flesh, I first observe that civil weapons are most improper and unfitting in 
matters of the spiritual state and kingdom, though in the civil state most 
proper and suitable.” His exegesis is often explicitly mystical and idealistic in 
the extreme. See his appeal to the “famous Waldensian witnesses” (p. 155), 
to Luther (p. 171), against Galvin, appeal to Gal. i. 8 (p. 181). It is worthy of 
note that the Baptist treatise upon which this work is based itself appeals in 
detail to Luther’s earlier “spiritual” conception of the Church (pp. 75 ff.). 
Roger Williams himself bases his individualism upon the doctrine of pre- 
destination (p. 82): “The Church or spiritual state, city or kingdom, has laws, 
orders, and armories ... to defend itself against the very gates 6f earth or 
hell. . . . The Lord Himself knows who are His and His foundation remaineth 
sure; His elect or chosen cannot perish or be finally deceived.” We shall come 
upon similar references to the earlier period of Luther and his “spiritual” 
ideas among the English mystics of the Cromwell period. A monograph on 
Roger Williams would be very interesting; in many respects he is very 
original. — Kuyper — although in a somewhat sophistical way — illustrates the 
adoption of liberty of conscience as one of the principles of Neo-Calvinism. 
He asserts (quite against the spirit of Calvin) that the “government of the 
Church on earth is democratic to the very marrow” (p. 5 6 ), and, moreover, he 
describes liberty of worship and religious toleration as an “essential” feature of 
Calvinism (p. 92). In so doing, however, Kuyper approaches very closely to 
that idea which is inevitably connected with the whole idea of toleration, 
namely, that all religious knowledge is merely relative, and with this he is 
renouncing an original principle of Calvinism. “By its strong emphasis upon 
religious freedom Calvinism abandoned the idea of the unity of the visible 
Church” (p. 94). “Since the very fact of the destruction of the unity of the 
Church naturally meant that the relative nature of all creeds must come into 



PROTESTANTISM 


935 


prominence, Calvinism, by making possible the formation of various churches 
of different kinds, also brought to light the limited nature of our belief in the 
Truth !” In ecclesiastical matters the State has no right to interfere, “not from 
a false idea of neutrality, nor from any idea of indifference to the truth, but 
because as the ruling authority it lacks the presuppositions which would enable 
it to give a true judgment, and the attempt to do this would too easily override 
the sovereignty of the Church” ( p . 97). Hence the State must not attempt to 
hinder a Church from setting up a system of the strictest orthodoxy within 
itself, but every Church must also tolerate the existence of other churches 
alongside of itself, and must not call upon the State to put an end to their 
existencet “Nothing can destroy the fundamental rule, that the civil govern- 
ment ought to honour the whole body of Christian churches as the many-sided 
revelation of the Church of Christ upon earth” (p. g8). “The State ought to 
recognize that every citizen ought to be granted full liberty of conscience as an 
original human right, belonging to him by nature” (p. 99). This is precisely 
the spirit of the constitution of New Hampshire, quoted by Jellinek , p. 21. 
Certainly the only element in it which is Calvinistic is the assertion of the 
sovereignty of the Church over against the State. The relative element in these 
statements is du«*to the influence of the Baptists, of mysticism and of rationalism ; 
Kuyper himself is unable to deny that “frequently ( !) it was the Baptists and 
the Remonstrants who even three hundred years ago defended the system of 
the Fret Church against Calvinism” (p. 92). Real toleration is found only 
among mystics and spiritual idealists and reformers, but among them this 
very easily merges into rationalism. The Baptist movement, with its absolute 
conception of Truth, is ultimately only tolerant to the extent of desiring to be 
independent of the State, and only from that standpoint does it advance to the 
inevitable conclusion that liberty of worship is also desirable. All these influences 
are fused in Neo-Calvinism. For the secular reasons for toleration which also 
existed, see Max Weber: Archiv XXI , 42 f. — The view upheld by Jellinek of the 
significance of this formulation and of the practical carrying out of liberty of 
conscience for the legal formulation of a still more comprehensive list of 
natural human rights, and therewith of the introduction of the conception into 
the constitution of the modern state in general, has been very largely questioned 
or deprecated. The second edition of his book takes some of these objections 
into consideration. The Catholic Paulus ( Kolnische Volkszeitung, Literarische 
Beilage , igo6, Nr. gg) argues that the rights of humanity arc exclusively derived 
from the Natural Law theory of the State and the philosophy of the Enlighten- 
ment ; Wahl: Z ur Geschichte der Menschenrechte ( H . Z-> 103, pp. yg-Sg), emphasizes, 
alongside of the religious influences, the general political situation of the states 
which were united together with their entirely different church organizations, 
and the influence of the ideas of the Enlightenment. That is probably right. 
Hdgermann: Die Erklarungen der Menschen- und Biirgerrechte , igio ( Eberings Hist. 
Studd., 78 ), likewise lays stress on the literary influences of the Enlightenment 
and reduces the religious influences to a minimum, but his ideas about the 
latter are very confused. He has misunderstood Roger Williams and his 
opinions altogether, he does not know that a conception of Christian Natural 
Law exists, and the influence of Milton and Locke, which he rightly emphasizes, 
is not interpreted in connection with its religious basis. Much in the book is, 
however, instructive and interesting ; he is right in pointing out that equality 
is a purely rationalistic growth, and his emphasis upon economic, political, 
and personal influences is thoroughly justifiable. Jellinek never argued that the 
American revolution was due to Puritanism, but it was only the rights of 



936 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

humanity and the argument for these which sprang out of Puritanism. In my 
opinion this is still true, even though he treats the Enlightenment too sum- 
marily. For all students of the religious development the explanations (text in 
Jellinek) contain the specifically religious sense of the invulnerability of con- 
scientious convictions and of the religious element which ought not to be 
touched by the State at all ; this shows the Calvinistic-Baptist origin of this 
development of the idea. — For a more recent work see Klovecorn: Die Entstehung 
der Erkldrung der Mcnschen - und Burgerrechte , igu. 

416 (p. 674.) That the classic Law of Nature is the emancipation of the Stoic 
elements from their connection with the ecclesiastical dogma and ethics, and 
from the ecclesiastical myth of primeval history, appears in all ther mass of 
average literature dealing with the Law of Nature, as described by Glafey: 
Gesch . des Rechts der Vernunft , iygg (see especially p. 54; Illy ig3f), and 
Hinrichs : Gesch. der Rechts- und Staatsprinzipien, 1848-52 (especially /, 227; II, 13). 
Aristotle, whose organic theory of the formation of the State was coupled 
together in the very mixed ecclesiastical theory of the Law of Nature with the 
contract theory and with the doctrine of the Divine origin of government, 
is entirely set aside ; increased individualism now works solely with the Stoic 
doctrines of an original freedom — (whether actual or only virtually present) — 
equality, and goodness of men in the Golden Age, out of which there arose, 
through the egoism of men and their non-social qualities, the necessity for the 
development of Society in the form of the State, in order to protect the original 
goods granted by Nature. In so doing, however, the ideas of Stoicism are not 
only released, but they also lose their Christian aspect, since (a) the Law of 
Nature is derived purely out of the nature of humanity, that is, out of the 
social and reasonable character of mankind, without any admixture of the 
Law of Nature with the desire to imitate the justice of God, and without any 
sense of need for the direct connection with the conception of God at all; 
(b) since in the definition of the Law of Nature the difference between the 
Primitive State and the fallen State increasingly disappears, and the Law of 
Nature is interpreted as originating in humanity as it is in itself; (c) since the 
rise of the State and of Law does not appear as a merely relative Natural Law 
of the fallen state, but as progress in civilization for the preservation of the 
natural disposition against passions which would endanger its existence. 
Henceforward the views of men become independent of primaeval history and 
its desirable social organization, and develop into purely rational sciences, 
which allow scope for the Church and for revelation alongside of themselves, 
but which are really independent in principle. Cf. my article Das stoisch- 
christliche Naturrecht und das moderne profane Naturrecht , //.£., igu, also Ver- 
handlungen des I. deutschen Soziologentages , igu. When Gothein and Kantorowicz 
here point out the importance of Roman Law in this process of transition, 
I would like to observe that already in the confessional philosophy of law 
Roman Law was the ratio scripta and the historical-positive development of the 
Law of Nature, identical with the Decalogue in its spirit and its meaning. 
This process is quite evident in the development of Hugo Grotius, who belongs 
from the very outset to a circle which was inwardly not Calvinistic ; he was 
also very much under the influence of Stoicism, and in his view there is a 
curious blend of utilitarian and idealistic elements ; Grotius evolved his ethical 
theory, his theory of the philosophy of history, and his theory of law quite 
independently of all confessions ; cf. the Heidelberg Dissertation by W. Geibel 
on Ethik und Theologie des H.G . For further details on this subject see Gierke: 
Althunus *, and Figgis: From Gerson to Grotius ; on the whole subject, see Bluntschli: 



PROTESTANTISM 


937 

Gesch, des allgemeinen Staatsrechtes und der Politik , 1864 , and Bergbohm: Jurisprudent 
und Rechtsphilosophie , 1892 ; it is, indeed, hard to say how, once the ecclesiastical 
doctrine of Society had been destroyed, the modern doctrine of Society could 
or should have been established in any other way. 

4l4a (p. 675.) In the Bloudy Tenent of Roger Williams there is one of the most 
important ideas for the possibility of the building up of Society and of the 
State according to the Law of Nature and the Second Table (of the Decalogue), 
without the interference of the State with the sovereign rights of the purely 
spiritual Church, but also without the need to create a Christian support for 
bourgeois morality and expediency. Even Heathen, Jews, and Turks are 
capable of a far-reaching politico-civil ethic, which in actual fact will always 
fit in to the Christian ethic, since indeed the Law of Nature is only the Second 
Table of the Decalogue. Roger Williams also combines with this idea a purely 
external utilitarian conception of the State ; for the same reasons this is also the 
case in Locke (see the book about him which has already been mentioned by 
Bastide ). When the religious duties and ideals are taken away from the 
ecclesiastical conception of the State it then falls a prey altogether to utili- 
tarianism. On Bayle , see Jodi: Gesch. d. Ethiky 7 2 , 420 ; on Milton, Stern: Milton 
und seine Zeit, 1^77-99, The unbroken process of development from the 
ccclesiastical-Calvinist Natural Law into a purely rational conception of 
Natural Law is seen in the New Englanders described by Hagermanny especially 
in Otisy whom he describes as the real father of the American system (pp. 44-98). 
Those who are familiar with the Calvinist doctrine of the State will here be 
able to note everywhere both the Calvinistic root, and the development in the 
direction of a rationalistic Natural Law. Hdgermann quotes on p. 92: “He who 
desires to realize the doctrine of unlimited passive obedience, which allows no 
resistance to man at all, is not only a Nero or a rogue, but he is also a rebel 
against the sanity of human intelligence as well as against the laws of God, 
of Nature, and of his country. 55 With that he couples freedom of conscience 
and the rejection of the priestly and the military caste, as, with an appeal 
to Saul, Roger Williams had also taught (p. 99). In Boston, therefore, he 
was compared with Isaiah and Ezekiel (p. 47). This is still clearly the atmo- 
sphere of Calvinism. Hdgermann gives several other examples of this process of 
development. 

417 (P- 6 ^ 5 -) Cf. on this question the often-quoted article by Max Weber: 
Kirchen und Sekten in Nordamerikay and Antikritisches , p . 202; Tocqueville: Dimocratie 
en Amtrique; von Schulze-Gdvernitz: Deutscher Imperialisms und englischer Freihandely 
pp. 42-64; Hartmann : Englische Frommigkeit. It is very interesting to note 
(Rothenbiicher, 149-169) how American law, from the point of view of the idea 
of associations, tries to do justice, by means of suitable fictions, to the idea of 
the Church as an institution. Here two different worlds of sociological thought 
come into collision. This contact is well illustrated by a passage in the account 
of Locke’s argument against patriarchalism and against the institutional idea 
in Bluntschliy p. 173: “The (opposing) argument is this : the children are bound 
by their fathers, and this argument is false. The father has no right to give away 
the freedom of his son. When the son reaches man’s estate he is no less free than 
his father was. Since the states are in existence, and children are born into them 
and educated as dependent members of the families which make up the State, 
since the land and the possessions of the citizens are permanently controlled, 
since in these conditions it is only one at a time, and one after another that 
individuals attain their majority and become free, and not a whole number at 
once, the act of freedom which the man who has come of age has consummated 



93® THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

when he unites his life to that of the State is overlooked. He is free, if he will, 
to choose to belong to another State. ,, In reality, this is the pivot of the whole 
question, and it is evident that there is here a very close resemblance to the 
ideal of the sect, which essentially claims that no human being is born into an 
institution, but that it is his duty to enter into a voluntary congregation on 
reaching maturity and of his own free will ; this implies that Adult Baptism 
and not Infant Baptism should be the rule. — At the same time we must 
remember, on the other hand, that Gierke , in his Genossenschaftsrecht , derives the 
mediaeval conception of the corporation, of the institution, of the unity of the 
State, from the analogy of the ecclesiastical Corpus mysticum. 

418 (p. 676.) Here the Life of Gladstone , by Morley , is very instructive (1903). 
Gladstone developed from Anglican Conservatism into a combination of 
Calvinism and Liberalism which had a great influence upon the inner life of 
the English nation, and which has found its chief support among English 
Nonconformists. His Conservative successor, Lord Salisbury, called Gladstone 
“the great Christian ,, J and the biographer adds : “nothing could be more true, 
or better worth saying. He not only accepted the doctrines of that faith as he 
believed them to be held by his own communion ; he sedulously strove to apply 
the noblest moralities of it to the affairs both of his own n?tion and of the 
commonwealth of nations” ( 7 , 4). For that very reason, at least to some extent, 
he even envisaged the possibility of Disestablishment. He separated the spheres 
of Natural Law and the churches, reserving the former to the State and the 
latter to Revelation and its various interpretations ; cf. a characteristic state- 
ment of Gladstone’s on “the highest ground of natural justice” ; it is “that 
justice which binds man to man ; which is older than Christianity, because it 
was in the world before Christianity was born ; which is broader than Christ- 
ianity, because it extends to the world beyond Christianity ; and which underlies 
Christianity, for Christianity itself appeals to it” (/, 363 ) ; this is to him, for 
example, the rule for the war with China. Erich Marcks certainly remarks on 
this point, that this Christian-ethical policy was only possible because Glad- 
stone’s predecessors had already established the supremacy of England both 
on sea and land so that it could not be questioned, thus giving Gladstone the 
luxury of carrying on a moral policy, while at the same time he was fortunate 
in having Disraeli as the representative of the opposite policy ; cf. Afarcks : Die 
Einheitlichkeit der englischen Auslandspolitik , 1910. To-day we are again experienc- 
ing the same ethical Liberal tendency in the internal politics of England. The 
visits of English clergy to Germany in the interests of Peace are part of this 
movement. The following incident, which I read in a Church paper, is charac- 
teristic: a German “General Superintendent” writes with great astonishment 
to tell how his very devout host entertained him with true Christian hospitality, 
and then told him, perfectly naturally, that in the same guest-room which 
his friend was occupying, the radical Liberal Theodor Barth had also stayed. 
This certainly is not possible within Lutheranism, and this impossibility is 
one of the most difficult problems in the religious situation in Germany. — 
Further, we must not overlook the fact that English Liberalism has also a 
decided anti-religious, purely utilitarian tendency of the school of Bentham 
and Mill. — Kuyper here is typical, speaking of Gladstone as a “Christian 
statesman who was a Calvinist to the very marrow” (p, 195). He speaks of 
“a sacred spirit of democracy” ( p . 21). “In Calvinism we first see the people 
itself come to the fore, and out of its own spontaneous impulse attain a higher 
form of social life” (p. 31 ). Here there rules the “universal grace”, the “order of 
creation”, or the Lex Naturae, “In the world we have to honour the effect of the 



PROTESTANTISM 


939 

universal grace of God, and for this reason we must free the world from 
ecclesiastical bonds . . (p. 24 ). “All that proceeds directly from the Creation 
possesses all the presuppositions for an independent (i.e. free from the Church) 
development in Nature as such. . . . It is altogether the life of creation according 
to the ordinances of creation, and, indeed, in organic development” ( p . 84 ). 
“Thus the Church retired to a position, where she was nothing more and 
nothing other than the community of the faithful, and thus the life of the 
world was set free, not from God, but from the Church. . . . Thus family life 
once again became independent. Trade and industry were now free to act on 
their own initiative; art and science were released from their ecclesiastical 
bonds anjl their own inspiration was given back to them, and the subordination 
of the whole of Nature to man, corresponding to the order of creation given by 
God in Paradise, was seen to be the true order’* (p. 23). “Fundamental legal 
rights” (p. go). “In the Declaration of Independence John Hancock expresses 
this in other words when he says that America, in virtue of ‘the Law of Nature 
and of Nature’s God* had come into being, that this nation acted as ‘endowed 
by the Creator with certain inalienable rights’ . . . that this Declaration was 
made with ‘a firm reliance upon the protection of Divine Providence’ ” ( p . 79). 
This conception of Natural Law is purely utilitarian : “The well-being of man 
must be the visible sign of His Divine Wisdom” (p. 74). This, however, is an 
American form of Neo-Calvinism : “Calvinism was transferred to America 
that it might develop there in a higher freedom” (p. 30). Here is the summary 
of this Neo-Calvinism ( p.33 ). “Remember how first the song of freedom arose 
through Calvinism, that consciences which had been oppressed now burst 
forth into praise, that our constitutional civil rights were only won and secured 
by means of Calvinism, and that at the same time that mighty movement 
went forth from Western Europe which permitted art and science to flourish, 
opened new roads for trade and industry, renewed family and social life in a 
brilliant manner, elevated the status of citizenship, placed the workman on a 
level with his master, brought with it a rich development of philanthropy, 
and, beyond all this, through its Puritan earnestness, it has exalted, purified, 
and ennobled the moral life of mankind” (p. 33). For Kuyper the State is still 
an institution of the Natural Law of the fallen State, a “mechanical” system of 
authority, placed over the world of Natural Law for the repression of evil, but 
for that vfcry reason to be kept carefully within certain limits, in order that it 
may not interfere with human rights (p. 86). In spite of all these democratic- 
liberal, Free Church toleration, utilitarian-Natural-Law principles, Kuyper is 
still the leader of orthodoxy, and of the forces of reaction which are combined 
with the Catholic Party, just as American and English Calvinists as a rule are 
very orthodox and keep the churches within strict limits. Opposition to the 
French conception of the equality of Natural Law (pp. 1J3 ff .). — All this agrees 
with the statements in the American Declaration of Independence ( Jellinek , 
p . g): “We hold the following truths as self-evident, namely, that all men are 
born equal, that they have been endowed by their Creator with certain 
inalienable rights, that to these rights belong life, freedom, and the endeavour 
to attain happiness, that, in order to secure these rights, systems of government 
have been set up amongst men, which derive the just authority from the consent 
of the governed ; that whenever a form of government works against these aims, 
it is the right of the people to alter it or to do away with it, to appoint a new 
government, and to establish it upon these principles, and to order its powers 
as may be best for its happiness and usefulness in the world.” — How utterly 
different is the conception of the State in Germany (under the influence of 



940 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Lutheranism), and how this conception of a Kulturstaat still means for 
many people the absorption of the religious aims of life into the tasks of the 
State, appears especially in the attempts to interpret the separation of Church 
and State in a German way in Otto Mayer: Staat und Kirche in PRE 3 , and 
E. Forster: Entwurf eines Gesetzes betr . die Religionsfreiheit , 1911, especially pp. 39 
and 47, with references to Freiherrn, v. Stein and Hegel ; here it is argued that 
it is in the interest of the State to use the means it has at its disposal of the 
external care of the churches to support the unity and continuance of the chief 
great religions, because its nature is not regarded as purely rational and 
utilitarian. The same point of view in Max Lenz: Nationalitat und Religion . 
Preuss. Jahrbb.y 1907 , here also upon a foundation of Lutheran sentiment. 

419 (p. 676.) See, for example, Kuyper y p . 184: “Calvinism is the high-water- 
mark of progress; ‘Modernism* does not mean progress since it has no new 
ideas of its own. — The material progress of this century (nineteenth) has 
nothing to do with progress in the sphere of principle.” Thus Pietism also has 
been able to combine technical knowledge and the study of natural science in 
a quite neutral way with dogmatic orthodoxy. It is thus expressed by Kuyper: 
“Our Calvinistic denomination speaks of two ways through which we come 
to the knowledge of God, Nature and the Scriptures, and it i,s far more note- 
worthy that Calvin, instead of treating Nature with neglect, said that the 
Scriptures were like a pair of spectacles which gave us the power of reading the 
Divine Scripture in Creation which had been faint and defective before” {p. 113). 
“Thus the Calvinist was still a pilgrim, but a pilgrim who on the way to the 
eternal fatherland had a vast task to fulfil. Above, below, and around there 
stretched the world with all the wealth of Nature. This whole vast field must 
be cultivated. The earth, with all that is in it, was to be made subordinate to 
man. Thus there flourished in my present fatherland as never before industry 
and agriculture, trade and seafaring. The new life of the community awakened 
new needs. In order to be able to control the earth it was necessary to know 
the nature of the earth, of the seas, of the qualities and laws which govern 
Nature” (p. 122 ). It is along this line that we must interpret the orthodoxy of 
so many great English natural scientists. Also the entirely different attitude 
to missions among these peoples must also be explained from this point of 
view; it is not merely due to its desire for colonies and its gift for colonial 
expansion, although naturally these interests probably played some part. 
Everywhere it is the possibility of “making the best of both worlds’* (Dowden, 

p- ‘ 75 )■ 

420 (p. 677.) See Powicke , where much emphasis is laid on the presence of 
the “spiritual” element in early Congregationalism (/>. 218): “A result of his 
two first principles working in combination : his faith in the Inner Light and 
his reverence for the written Word. For faith in the Inner Light, at least, 
in the case of the more deeply thoughtful and devout of its disciples, really 
meant faith in the highest intentions of spiritual reason; and this, when 
brought to a study of the written Word, could not fail to operate selectively, 
fastening on what was agreeable to the most worthy conception of God 
and man and tacitly ignoring all else.” Thus also one section else branched off 
into Unitarianism. 

422 (p. 678.) On this point sec Gobel: Christl. Leben , 7 , 318-331 . Here already 
we meet the democratic tendency in congregational organization, and the 
strict separation from the world, also the “prophesyings”. Heppe {p. 20) thus 
describes the Puritan “prophesyings”: “The ruling idea was this — that 
Christianity was of necessity life, and, indeed, that it ought to be a serious life, 



PROTESTANTISM 


94 1 

entirely regulated by the Word of God, in which the Christian must not be 
idle, but in which he must unceasingly exercise himself, proving himself by the 
Word of God, and striving for an ever more complete sanctification through 
prolonged prayer, through meditation and fasting, and, above all, through 
systematic asceticism.” Note the element of asceticism. 

428 (p. 678.) For the name and its history, see Douglas Campbell: The Puritan 
in Holland , England , and America 4 , 1902, I, p. XXVII; Kattenbusch , article Puritaner 
in PRE 3 t who here absolutely identifies Puritanism with Pietism ; Heppe: Gesch . 
des Piet., p. 6. The names praxis pietatis and others are also frequently found in 
the English literature of the subject (Heppe, pp. 23 , 30). The terms “Precisians”, 
“Puritans”, or even “Martinists” were used even by Barrow; the latter term 
comes from the Marprelate Tracts ; see Powicke , p. 149. Another term which 
occurs again and again is that of “godliness” or “saintliness”, the “godly 
men” or the “saints”. Weingarten , unfortunately, did not perceive or describe 
this tendency, as Heppe, p. 14, rightly points out: this is why he has not 
made clear its relation to Presbyterianism, Congregationalism, and the 
Baptist movement ; yet only when these distinctions have been drawn is it 
possible to understand the collective expression “Independency”. — Their 
opponents still Uked to call them “Libertines”, following the ancient custom 
of Geneva. 

424 (p. 681.) The most important sources, Works of the English Puritan Divines, 
London,* 1843-48, 10 vols., used very largely by Heppe and Max Weber . Also 
Heppe: Gesch. d. Pietismus, in which, however, the position from the standpoint 
of the history of dogma of early Calvinism and of Lutheran Pietism is not 
made clear in any way, and there is no reference to the general history of 
civilization in which this movement was set. Ritschl: Gesch. des Pietismus, entirely 
ignores this Pietist movement ; the accidental fact that Ritschl did not know 
English gave to his views and to those of his followers a very considerable and 
a very unfortunate twist. Douglas Campbell has a great deal of information, 
but the book needs to be used with caution ; in his mind Puritanism is mainly 
Calvinism of the individualistic rigoristic type, and he regards this type of 
Puritanism as the origin, to a very large extent, of almost the whole of the 
present Anglo-Saxon world ; thus his view of the basis of modern civilization is 
similar tc^that oIKuyper, only without his orthodox colouring ; he also includes 
the sects within Puritanism. This work, which is in two volumes, reached a 
fourth edition, a clear sign of the response which there is to such views. For 
Pietistic Puritanism as a special group, distinct from Presbyterianism and 
Congregationalism, see also Shaw: English Church, I, 6 f, 51-53 ; for a description 
of the Puritanism of the later years of the reign of Elizabeth and of the Stuart 
period, contrasted with the Puritanism of earlier days, which was supported 
rather by theologians and affected very largely by the anti-Catholicism of 
Geneva, see Glass, 4-13 ; this later Puritanism he calls “revivalism”, and says 
it may be compared with the Methodism of a later period. See also Dexter: 
The England and Holland of the Pilgrims, pp. 122 ff.; it is a “reformation within 
the Reformation”, an “evangelical purpose”. Max Weber also describes this 
form of Puritanism in its fusion with the sects, and also rightly distinguishes it 
from the primitive Calvinism of Geneva. — The question of the reasons for the 
rise of this Pietist movement, which was behind the Great Rebellion and was 
one of the formative elements in more recent English history, is raised by 
Douglas Campbell , 7 , X; he attributes it to the influence of the Calvinistic 
exiles from the Netherlands, who came over in great numbers (75,000 fathers 
of families), and who were welcomed by Elizabeth on account of their 



94a THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

usefulness in trade and industries. “ ‘These Netherlander helped to make 
England Protestant, and this laid a lasting basis for her wealth ; but, at the 
same time, they did an even greater work than this ; for in helping to make 
her Protestant they also helped to make her free”. . . . “It was Protestant 
England that ultimately controlled the ocean and the markets of the world, 
colonized America, and girded the earth with an empire” ( p . 429). — For the 
aspect of the movement which affects the history of civilization, see Taine: 
Hist . de la literature anglaise , II, 1863 , pp. 273-433, and, above all, Dowden: 
Puritan and Anglican, London, 1900 . Both these writers describe the Puritan 
hostility to the world and their systematic asceticism, which, however, does not 
mean withdrawal from the world but the active domination of the Me of the 
world ; in Dowden there is a very fine description of the secularization of the 
Puritan spirit in the comparison between Bunyan and Defoe ( 274-278 ) ; here 
he says of the secularized Puritan : “To make the best of both worlds was the 
part of prudence, and of the two worlds, that on which our feet are planted is, 
at least, nearer and the more submissive to our control. Divine Providence is 
doubtless to be acknowledged, but it is highly desirable to supplement Divine 
Providence by self-help. . . . Adventurer, trader, colonist, missionary, we hail 
him as one of our makers of empire.” For the ethical hostility and the opposition 
to the Elizabethan literature, see Douglas Campbell, II, 114-136. There was 
good reason for the hostility and the literary class was very meagre. Here also 
is the explanation of the austerity of the Puritans, so different from the attitude 
of Calvin ; it was due namely to their hostility to the worldliness, immorality, 
and brutality of the rest of the nation (pp. 132-163), here, however, the Cal- 
vinistic element is greatly underestimated ; social and political reform efforts 
(pp. 171-176) ; see also Glass for an estimate of the value of the legislation of the 
Barebones Parliament, in which the minority consisted of Pietists of this kind ; 
here Pietists opposed Baptist fanatics. 

425 (p. 682.) For the class relationships see suggestions in Glass, pp. 6 and 23/., 
Dowden, p. 233 especially Glass, p. 32: “Puritanism was a movement of the 
people, with not a few leaders among the aristocracy. For a time its temper 
was high and courageous, hopeful and even audacious in new experiments. 
Its religious spirit tended to abolish or modify social distinctions : all mortal 
men were alike sinners before God, and peer or peasant, if true members of 
the congregation, were equally saints. Its favoured ecclesiastical schemes and 
platforms were of a democratic kind. Its political ideal was not a loose and 
incoherent democracy ; it aimed at vigour in government, and was willing to 
confer immense powers upon chosen individuals ; but its political culmination 
was a Republic.” P. 4: “The mundane spirit of the Renaissance (?) in its 
lower form of commercial interests by degrees allied itself with Puritanism.” 
Later (p. 273): “The middle classes advanced in wealth, power, and in influence. 
After the jagged precipices and forlorn valleys — scenes of spiritual exaltation 
or despair — a tableland was reached — safe, if unheroic — where man might 
plough and build.” Douglas Campbell has investigated the problem with 
vigour, but he solves it too externally with his favourite theory of the influence 
of the Dutch immigrants ; he describes the facts of the situation, however, in 
the following terms : this movement was the rise of the middle classes through 
the religious movement to a position of importance which they had never held 
before, which had permanent results in its effect upon the rise of England and 
America to a power over the rest of the world, after Elizabethan England had 
been behind the rest of Europe, owing to its defective adoption of the culture 
of the Renaissance; pp. 483 /., 490-492 : “No people on earth have a higher 



PROTESTANTISM 


943 

order of virtue than the English middle classes. They bear a courage which 
never falters, an earnestness of purpose which brooks no obstacles, a love of 
justice and fair play, a devotion to home and country, and an instinctive 
morality and real belief in a Higher Power which are not so common among 
the Latin races. . . . Their daily life was a sermon on the Christian virtues of 
industry, temperance, and charity”; 496: “The opposition to the arbitrary 
power of the Crown grew with the development of the industrial classes. The 
tiller of the soil, as Irish history has shown, can exist even when denied almost 
every human right. But manufactures and commerce require the air of free- 
dom. . . . The wealth came, but with it the ideas and spirit that in the next 
century (jmder Cromwell) bred a revolution.” The Dissenting middle classes 
were shut out from official positions, and, therefore — like the Jews — they 
turned to business, to a capitalistic form of agriculture, to manufacturing, and 
to trade, this tendency being further strengthened by the Huguenots (II, 401), 
their importance for the Liberalism of the nineteenth century (II, 404): “They 
forced the passage of the Reform Bill, widening the suffrage. Then they began 
to look round for social, legal, and other political reforms.” They now began 
to follow Puritan America : “Rejuvenated England has followed America in 
her system of popular education, freedom of religion, freedom of the Press, 
the secret ballot, prison reform, and the entire reformation of her legal system.” 
The origin of the secret ballot from the Dutch system of election within the 
Church, see II, 437. In spite of his insistence on the fact that all these things 
were due to the influence of Puritanism, Campbell does not throw much light 
upon the inner psychological connection. The ascription of these effects to 
“Puritanism” in Holland renders it particularly necessary to explain the latter ; 
C., however, takes this for granted. Further, the influence of Puritanism in 
England and in the Netherlands was a mutual one. There are similar descrip- 
tions of the English middle classes in Held, p. 48. Weber, in the articles which 
have often been mentioned, deals with the psychological analysis of this whole 
subject in a very fine and illuminating manner ; he takes points which have 
merely been touched upon or suggested by these other authors and expands 
them along this line. For the transmission of this spirit to New England and 
through the Dutch to New York, see Campbell, II, and Doyle : The English in 
America. 

424 (p. 385.) Cf. Gobel, I; Heppe; Ritschl, I; Knappert: Geschiedenis der neder- 
landsche hervormde Kerk gedurende de i6e en ije Euw, Amsterdam, 1911 ; for the 
constitution see von Hoffmann: Das Kirchenverfassungsrecht der niederland. Kirche 
bis 1618. For present conditions, see Rothenbiicher , 423-429. Heppe and Ritschl 
take almost no notice at all of the aspect of the question which concerns the 
history of civilization. The connection with England is brought out by Heppe , 
xoy-rio , j 40-1 44, 148, 136, 164, 183. Ritschl scarcely touches this point, but, on 
the other hand, he analyses the contrast with primitive Calvinism, the con- 
nection with the fundamental impulse of Calvinism, the development of this 
Pietism out of a mere effort to provide more adequate means of grace and more 
pastoral care in order to build up believers in the life of sanctification, into a 
legalistic individualism, into a mysticism of the St. Bernard type, into evangelical 
emotionalism. He regards this as the destruction of ecclesiastical Calvinism by 
the spirit of the Anabaptists and of Catholic mysticism. He does not see, 
however, that in reality this represents the exaggerated endeavour of a whole 
people striving after holiness, and the natural result of the failure of rigorism 
in this task — thus a result of the Calvinistic principle itself— -because his idea 
of the normal Christian life is summed up in the certainty of salvation, trust 



944 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

in God, and loyalty to the duties of one’s calling ; this produces an ecclesiastical 
popular morality, from which, he says, Calvinism, through Pietism, has 
departed. — His endeavours to trace resemblances to Liberalism within 
Pietism are interesting ( p . 267): “The student of history may assert, that . . . 
the expectation of inner and outer changes in the Church and in the world 
has hindered the Protestant Church no less than the well-meaning hopes of 
the political Enlightenment and of doctrinaire Liberalism endangered the 
health of the moral life of the people. Religion of the Pietist type is, at this 
point, assigned a close relationship with political Liberalism, whereas this 
school of thought considers itself to be exactly opposed to it. This, however, is 
due to the fact that originally Pietism did not trouble at all about the State 
as such, but that its endeavours which resemble Liberalism were all under- 
taken within the sphere of the Church. The adherents of the Enlightenment 
and of political Liberalism, however, know that Pietism prepared the way for 
their movements.” Their ascetic and revivalist character is emphasized by 
Knappert , p. 273. — For their connection with the history of civilization in 
general see Laspeyres; Douglas Campbell , II, 287-336; Busken-Huet: Het Land van 
Rembrandt 2 , 1886. We must not overlook the fact that the Arminians, like the 
Anglicans, are defenders of the State Church or “Erastianj,”, and that also 
for this very reason the theology of the Stuart period was Arminian, or at least 
it was called so. See also Campbell , 304 , for the views of Oldenbarneveld on 
certain Calvinists whom he called “Puritans and double Puritans”. Here the 
difficulty is not merely opposition to the doctrine of predestination. It is plain 
from the complaints of the Pietist section that their opposition was directed 
further against the worldliness of a politically, economically, and scientifically 
progressive nation which disapproves of asceticism. Above all, they strove 
against the exemption of certain practical callings from religious rules, and 
against the restriction of the latter merely to private and personal life. Often 
they almost hover on the brink of formulating the idea of an “intramundane 
asceticism”. Cf. Ritschl , I, 123: “Voet accepts as the definition of mysticism 
the phrase of Gerson: Vita contemplativa est status hominum extra mundum. . . . 
Voet (who himself to a great extent accepted the mystical and ascetic 
literature of Catholicism ( Heppe , 131) ) discerned in this tendency the founda- 
tion of monasticism . . . and replies : unde ipsos videre est separare invicem primae 
tabulae praecepta a praeceptis secundae tabulae .” P. 274: “It is, however, appro- 
priate that if contemplation whose home is the cloister is to be carried 
out, the rule of the canonical hours must be rediscovered (i.e. the Puritan 
form of discipline and ordering of time, even to the extent of determining the 
length of time which may be spent in sleep). But this can only be permitted 
within civic activity, which is just as legitimate in the Calvinistic Church as it 
is customary among the Dutch people.” P. 278: “Here we meet the ideas of 
self-examination and penitence, of self-denial and scrupulous behaviour, of 
the spiritual permeation of secular business and of the desire for perfection, 
and finally of public and private worship.” Busken-Huet , II, 84 (alluding to a 
book on the theologian Bogermann) gives an account of the ascetic require- 
ments, and then adds : “Hunne levensbeschouwing was somber en stemmig als 
hun kleed. Zy geleken monniken, die hunne cel verlaten hadden, en het boze 
menschdom wilden overreden om, boete doende, de wereld voor zich tot een 
kloster te maken.” This was everywhere the same as that word of Sebastian 
Franck, which I quoted earlier in this book ( Kultur d. G., N.S., 443) : “Detach- 
ment from the world and self-denial is the duty of all Christians ; it is no use 
trying to throw the responsibility on to monasticism.” Rachfahl calls all this 



PROTESTANTISM 


945 

only “common Christian morality”. Unfortunately, Knodt , p. 26, also takes 
the same point of view. 

427 (p. 686 .) A tendency to appeal to the lower classes among the people is 
asserted by Heppe , p . 51 ; Knappert {172) speaks of democratic tendencies in 
the Puritan preachers, which are in accord with their middle-class origin; 
the same is emphasized in the Dissertation by Geibel , which has already been 
mentioned, where it is asserted that wholesale business was (on the whole) 
carried on by the “Libertines” and trade by the Puritans or “Precisians”; 
see also Laspeyres, Busken-Huet, and Douglas Campbell . — An interesting illustra- 
tion is given by Campbell of the supposed superiority of the Hollanders in the 
words of>a London merchant named Lamb, who told Cromwell (II, 327): 
“In Holland, when a merchant dies, his property is equally divided among 
his children, and the business is continued and expanded, with all its traditions 
and inherited experience. In England, on the contrary, the property goes to 
the eldest son, who often sets up for a country gentleman, squanders his 
patrimony, and neglects the business by which his father has become enriched. 

. . . The honesty of the Hollanders in their manufacturing and commercial 
dealings. When goods are made or put up in Holland, they sell everywhere 
without question; for the purchaser knows that they are exactly as represented 
in quality, weight, and measure.” Laspeyres says that the high position of 
Holland was due to religious toleration, and to the fact that persons who were 
engaged* in trade were attracted into the country ; also he speaks of the “moral 
advantages”, such as frugality and honesty, which also helped to raise the 
whole tone of social life, and as a further factor he states that the question of 
religious denomination did not enter into business dealings (pp. 122-124 ). 
None of the other writers has mentioned this point, although both Douglas 
Campbell and Busken-Huet connect the flourishing state of the republic with its 
Puritan Calvinism. In general, too, the researches of Weber are very illuminating 
on this whole question; cf. Weber: Antikritisches, u.s.w., pp. 186-188, and his 
Schlusswort, pp. 570-371 . He describes the Puritanism of the Netherlands as one 
which continually “broke down at important points, even though not at all 
points”. Their missionary efforts in the colonies, for example, were suppressed ; 
indeed, in the colonies as a whole the religious life was made to conform to the 
interests o^trade, and in spite of certain scruples slavery was justified (. Laspeyres , 
106, III). 

420 (p. 000.) Cf. Miinsterberg: Die Amerikaner , 1504, and W. von Polenz : Das Land 
der Zuhunfty 1903 ; both these books, however, throw very little light on this 
question at this point ; even in Tocqueville there are only hints and suggestions ; 
W. Muller: Das religiose Leben in Amerika , 1911, does not give very much ; there 
is more in the works of Rauschenbusch. Max Weber gives a good many individual 
examples, which are drawn from his study of the resemblance between the 
Pietism of the Lower Rhine andofWestphaliaandthe Puritan groups of England 
and America. Just because these groups are so different these resemblances are 
all the more valuable evidence for the existence of a definite social-ethical 
tendency and result of Calvinism (these two do not always coincide). Weber 
lays stress on the fact that these results happened in very unfavourable sur- 
roundings, like East Friesland and the young English colonies. It is, of course, 
understood that in each case other influences beside that of Calvinism have 
also contributed to bring about these results. 

421 (p. 688 .) For the conception of Christian Socialism connected with 
Neo-Calvinism, see Rauschenbusch und Holl: Calvinreden , p. 35. — For the relation 
to Lutheranism, see the characteristic observations of Kuyper , p. 15: “In all 

VOL. II. II 



946 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Lutheran countries the Reformation started rather with the princes than 
among the people, and thus it came to be under the power of the Government 
. . . and in consequence it has not transformed either social or political life 
by the power of its own vital principles. Lutheranism has remained churchly 
and theological; Calvinism alone has set its seal upon all the expressions of 
human life, both within and without the Church. No one speaks of Lutheranism 
as of the creation of a distinctive form of life, even the name is seldom men- 
tioned ; whereas all students of history agree in ever-increasing measure to 
salute Calvinism as the creator of a distinctive world of human life.” Thus 
Calvinism feels itself to be the one great Christian social system alongside of 
Catholicism ( p . io): “Of Romanism alone can we say that it has incorporated 
its own thought about life in a distinctive world of sentiment and practical 
expression. But alongside of, and over against, this Romanism, Calvinism 
arose, not simply as a system of Church reform, but in order to create a quite 
different form of human life, to give to human society another form of existence, 
and to fill the human heart with other and different ideals and conceptions.” 
“This unity of the conception of life we do not find in the narrow idea of 
Protestantism . . . but alone in the mighty historical process, which, in the 
form of Calvinism, drove its way through circumstances, aryl hollowed out a 
channel, through which the powerful current of its life could flow. It is, thanks 
to this consciousness of unity within Calvinism that you here in America, and 
we in Europe, can again take up our position alongside of Romanism, *and over 
against modern Pantheism.” — So far as Catholicism is concerned, here is the 
contrasting picture, mentioned by Prezzolini: Wesen , Geschichte und £iele des 
Modernismus, pp. 98-60: “The Catholic ideal is a well-fed people, who think 
little, and are led and controlled by a theocracy. But this kind of social activity 
is utterly different from that which grew up during the nineteenth century, 
and, indeed, at two points: (a) in the predominance of the priesthood, and 
( b ) in the exercise of charity. . . . The predominance of the theocracy is 
replaced by a strong emphasis upon the laity, and the idea of charity is replaced 
by that of the necessity for a fundamental social reform. . . . The attitude of 
Latin Catholics towards social democracy is divided. The Old Catholics 
represent the standpoint of love to one’s neighbour and of good-will, and they 
are perpetually criticising economic Liberalism. . . . They believe that it would 
suffice if guilds on the mediaeval pattern and all kinds of co-operative societies 
were established, and more scope were given to the laity within the parishes. . . . 
Their highest ideal is that of a mediaeval society established upon a theocratic 
basis, with trade unions among the workpeople. The young Catholics are 
gradually becoming bolder ; they desire more modern and quicker methods, 
and they do not shrink from imitating the methods of Social Democracy, and, 
in contrast to the Old Catholics, they refuse to combine with the reactionary 
bourgeois parties in politics.” Hence, as is well known, in Italy they have been 
censured by the Pope. 

433 (p. 692.) Cf. Hegler: Geist und Schrift bei Sebastian Franck , 1892 y p . 168 n. 
The significance of the Sermon on the Mount ought to be emphasized still 
more strongly, as this has been done in the writings of L. Keller, which will 
be mentioned shortly. For the significance of the Sermon on the Mount as an 
ideal of life among the Baptists, see Gottfried Arnold: Unparteiische Kirchen - und 
Ketzerhistorie , 1700, //, pp. 529 jf. We find the same thing in Sebastian Frajick: 
Chronica , Z^buch und Geschichtsbibel , 1 536, in the Ketzerchronik, p. 146: “Therefore 
there belong to these (to those who falsely reverence the Scriptures) all those 
who thus break up the Scriptures and who do not observe one word of God 



PROTESTANTISM 


947 

as strictly as another, and who do not preach so willingly and so frequently 
from the fifth to the seventh chapter of Matthew and the sixth chapter of Luke 
as they do from the Epistles to the Romans and Galatians.** Cf. also Dilthey in 
his important essay, Auffassung und Analyse des Menschen im 15. und 16. Jahrhundert , 
Archiv.f. Gesch. d. Philos ., V , 1892 ; his words on p. 278 are very striking : “In the 
Protestant community the principle of the inner Word was in conflict with 
that of the Scriptures — the Gospels with Paul — the Apostolic life with mankind 
as it is — the Christian ideal with statecraft — above all, however, the Word 
of the Bible with the progressive form of religious life produced by the 
Reformation.** 

434 (p. 693.) Illuminating, though decidedly grim in its irony, is the treatise 
of Luther, in this connection, entitled Wider die himmlischen Propheten von den 
Bildern und Sakrament , of 1525 ( B . A. Ergdnzungsband, I). So far as both Luther 
and his opponents regarded the whole Bible, and Paul in particular, as an 
inspired authority, Luther’s attack is certainly right, and it represents the 
logical consequence of his fundamental ideas. This situation is excellently 
described by Erbkam : Gesch. d. prot. Sekten , 1848 , pp. 167-171 , 483-488 . The 
development out of mysticism is very well described in the book by Braun , 
which has already been mentioned, Bedeutung der Konkupiszenz in Luthers Leben 
und Lehre, 1908. The most recent study, based on newly discovered early works 
of Luther by Sc heel: Entwickelung L.s bis zum Abschluss der Vorlesung fiber den 
Romerbrief (Sc hr if ten des Vereins fur Ref Gesch., 1910) underestimates the sig- 
nificance of the mystical element in an amazing way ; see in particular pp. 192 f 
and 201 f. For Luther’s connection with mysticism see also the excellent work 
of H. Hering: Die Mystik Luthers, 1879. See also above, pp. 494 ff. 

488 (p. 694.) Cf. Karl Muller: Kirche, Gemeinde und Obrigkeit nach Luther, 1910 , 
especially pp. 32-40, 84. I consider Muller's argument entirely valid; it also 
agrees with my own conception, see above, pp. 487-494. Even in these smaller 
communities Luther has retained the general Church conception of an organ 
of salvation produced by the Word. His idea was simply that these groups were 
to be smaller and more closely knit circles within the Church itself, and that 
gradually from these groups the influence of the Word should be carried out 
into the popular and national churches. All that they possess is due only to the 
effect of the Word, but it is the real, strong, and visible effect of the Word which 
is concentrated here and which finally should be spread outwards over the 
whole. Thus the general idea of the Church is maintained, but within it there 
still takes place a certain approximation to the ideas of the sect. In all this the 
idea of the Church certainly predominates, and in consequence, upon the whole, 
Luther’s development is essentially straightforward, as I have described it 
above. He did not suddenly incline towards the sect and then return to the 
Church ; he only made the attempt to make room for the sect-idea within the 
Church. That, however, is a very difficult matter, and that is why in this 
question Luther did not get beyond the stage of drawing up plans. The decisive 
element is the idea of the Church, which determines all the rest. This has 
already been understood quite rightly by Erbkam, pp. 9-13 . — I therefore do 
not agree with Rieker and Achelis that this approach to the sect simply meant 
that for a time and against his own principles Luther was influenced by the 
Baptists ; in my opinion this approximation towards the idea of the sect was 
due to an inner conflict within his own thought which arose from his study of 
the Bible. 

4M (p. 694.) Appeals to the younger Luther, who is supposed to have betrayed 
his earlier ideals, are general among the Dissenters. Hochhuth gives examples in 



948 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

his great series of articles from the published records of the Hess. Archiven , 
Z.f. hist. Theol. , XXVIII-XXXII ; especially XXVIII , pp. 542, , 6jj; 

/>. 77,9. Here is the letter of an Anabaptist : “Even their own prophet, Martinus 
Luther, has also written about these things (in a little book which is called 
Eine Weise christlichi Mass zu halten) that people should come together behind 
closed doors and set things in order. Once again he said : *1 am not yet bold 
enough to begin such a thing lest it should be thought to be some kind of 
fanatical sect.’ ” Everywhere here the complaints are given as the reason for 
the Anabaptist movement that the new Church achieves nothing in the moral 
sphere, and that Luther did not venture to continue his first attempt for lack 
of genuine Christians to carry out his ideas. — The interpretation which 
W. Kohler , in the reformatio Hassiaca , has given as a working out of the same 
Lutheran ideas, is also connected with this subject. ( Entstehung der ref eccles. 
Hassiae of 1526 , Deutsche Z»f Kirchenrecht , 1906, pp. 199-232). Even when in the 
case of Lambert these ideas were attributed at an earlier period to Franciscan 
ideals, the instinct was still right because they are sect-ideals ; but at the time 
the fact was overlooked that Luther himself in his earlier period had tried to 
unite these ideas with his later conception of the Church; cf. W. Kohler: Z u 
Luthers Kirchenbegriff, Chr. W ., 1907 . — Among the Independents, William Dell, 
who has already been mentioned, and who will be treated more fully in a later 
section of this book, referred expressly to Luther in his original combination of 
mystical, Congregationalist, and State Church ideas ; see Sippell: William Dells 
Programm einer “ lutherischen ” Gemeinschaftsbewegung , 1911. So far as Schwenkfeld 
is concerned, Ecke , in his Schwenkfeld , Luther und der Gedanke einer apostolischen 
Reformation , 1911, and also Sippell , in his article, Caspar Schwenkfeld , Chr. W., 
1911 , Nr. 37-41 , have shown the connection with Luther’s ideas. — Franck , in 
the splendidly objective article, Martin Luther , in his Ketzerchronik , emphasizes 
the idea of the more exclusive Christian community with its own sacramental 
celebrations (II, 173b ). Hegler points out everywhere that Franck and the 
Anabaptists have a close connection with the original ideas of the Reformation. 
— But Gottfried Arnold also is quite clear upon this point. Thus Arnold appeals 
to Luther’s original rejection of war, in which he agreed with the Anabaptists ; 
cf. also Franck's Kriegbiichlein. “After which Luther altered his opinion which 
had been previously formed in harmony with the Will of Christ, because he 
felt that the Gospel does not do away with Natural Law” ( Arnold , It, n and 12). 
In his opinion, Luther’s ideas were “stifled by the jurists” (II, 20). The urgent 
impulse towards real sanctification which characterized the earlier stages of 
Luther’s career, in which Luther’s monastic ideals were still active (II, 46) r 
which, however, unfortunately he gave up later on (II, 93). The idea of 
particular smaller communities as a useful adjunct is emphasized in II, 132; 
practice of electing pastors by the congregation unfortunately given up (II, r6i) ; 
likewise prohibition of usury unfortunately given up (II, 162). — Spener's 
Pia desideria appeals, it is true, in reference to the Collegia Biblica not to Luther’s 
ideal of groups of genuine Christians, but to his ideal of the priesthood of 
all believers (see Edition of 1 706, p. 109). Further, to Luther’s recommendations 
of Tauler, Thomas k Kempis, and the Theologia Germanica, p. 140; he also 
emphasizes the Christian Utopian characteristics of the Lutheran ethic: 
avoiding of lawsuits (p. 41) ; communal holding of possessions in a different but 
analogous sense like that of the Early Church in Jerusalem (p. 43) ; everywhere 
in general recourse to the Apostolic Church and the assurance that that was 
no respublica Platonica. For the relation of the Pietist Collegia Biblica to Luther’s 
“more exclusive groups”, see K. Muller: Kirche, Gemeinde, u.s.w.,pp. 83 ff. 



PROTESTANTISM 


949 


440 (p» 695 •) The most important presentation of the subject is given by 
Gottfried Arnold in his Kirchen u. Keizer geschichte, a Church history which is not 
yet out of date and which can still be used along with modern Church histories. 
It uses an unbelievable wealth of source-material, and brings one into the 
atmosphere of the Protestantism outside the Churches as no other book does. 
Further, there is also Sebastian Franck's famous Geschichtsbibel , in which the 
Ketzerchronik is incorporated ; here the Anabaptists are described with special 
emphasis, and obviously out of a wide personal experience and exhaustive 
research. Bullinger: Der Wiedertaufer Ur sprung, Fiirgang , Sekten, We sen, Zurich, 
1560. This writer takes one into the hostile atmosphere of a national Church 
and into the relative right of defence ; a national Church could not come to 
terms with these people. — Modern presentations of the subject suffer, above all, 
from this defect, that they do not distinguish between this Anabaptist, sectarian 
movement, and mysticism ; while in actual fact the two were often united they 
are, nevertheless, distinct in the inner structure of thought. The custom of early 
heresy-hunters to call all heretics “ Schwenkfeldiani , Anibaptistae et alii id genus" 
and then to include them all under one head, and Luther’s habit of calling 
them all fanatics and saying that they perpetuate the Catholic heresy of good 
works, legalism, And monasticism, has greatly obscured our understanding of 
this subject. Hegler , who is the most expert and understanding student of this 
subject, has rightly warned us that we ought to distinguish between the two, 
and in so’doing, above all, he has already pointed out the sociological differences 
between the two; Anzeige von Harnacks Dogmengeschichte Theol. Litztg. , rgo8, 
pp . 253-258. — Rilschl ( Gesch . d. Pietismus, I) also follows Luther’s and Bullinger’s 
track; “as a Lutheran theologian” and Churchman he feels obliged “to adhere 
to the opinion of the Reformers” (p. 7), hence he argues that the Anabaptist 
movement and mysticism have developed out of Catholicism — mainly, it is 
true, out of the popular expansions of the Franciscan movement, whose origins, 
therefore, were not well known. At the same time he recognized the difference 
between the sect and mysticism as something which “in itself is quite a matter 
of indifference” (pp. 28, 35) ; but he thinks that the coupling of both together 
arose already out of monasticism, which, on the one hand, desires to renew the 
Apostolic life of detachment from the world, and, on the other hand, owing to 
the fact th^t it had no profession or occupation within the world, very naturally 
gave way to mysticism of an emotional kind ! — Ludwig Keller has also maintained 
that the Anabaptists were non-Protestant in character ( Reformat . d. dlteren 
Reformparteien , 1885, Staupitz und Anfange d. Reform ., 1888, Anfange d. Reform, u. 
Ketzerschulen , 16J97), but for his part he does not attribute this to Catholicism, 
but to the voluntary Church, purely primitively Christian, which had a separate 
existence from the time of Constantine — the so-called early Evangelical com- 
munities who had a high standard of social morality and religious toleration — 
which, with Peter Waldo and the Anabaptists, only underwent a certain 
transformation, and which in his opinion represent the genuine Christian 
tradition as compared with Catholicism and Protestantism. Even though this 
idea of “early Protestant communities” at least in this form may be a fantasy 
picture, still the researches of Keller are certainly very instructive and stimulat- 
ing. His chief defect is that he does not analyse clearly enough the essence of the 
sect in contradistinction to that of the Church, and that he includes under his 
conception of the sect all forms of opposition to the Established Church, 
mysticism, humanism, etc. In particular, the failure to distinguish between 
mysticism and the sect in the case of the Friends of God, Tauler, etc., makes 
it very difficult to get any clear picture of the real situation. He always makes 



950 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

mysticism and the sect explain one another; “the theology of the latter must 
be used as the complement of German mysticism at every point in which the 
latter is in the habit of evading a definite pronouncement !” Staupitz, 143: 
Mysticism is said to be only “half the system of the earlier Protestants’* ( ebd ., 
224 ). If now the Anabaptist movement does not quite correspond to this 
mingled ideal, consisting of mysticism and a tolerant voluntary Church, this 
then must be ascribed to the fact that the Anabaptists in earlier times had 
transferred to the whole Church an ascetic doctrine and a rejection of the 
world which was only meant for Apostles (ebd., 321 ) — a statement which is 
nowhere proved. All this points to the fact that these component parts which 
Keller combines ought to be separated, and that the problem of the origin of 
each from the Middle Ages and of its relation to the Reformation principle 
must be stated. Then, however, the phantom of the early Protestant com- 
munities disappears altogether, and the relation between the Anabaptists and 
the earlier sects proved by Keller loses the striking significance which Keller 
gives it as the apologist of the “early Protestant communities”; he even argues 
that the Reformation was due to them through Staupitz. — Thudichum: Die 
deutsche Reformat., 1517-37, 1307-1303, follows Keller's line; he obliterates the 
difference between the sect and mysticism with the words* (II, 114): “The 
expression ‘mystics’, which the newer Protestant theologians are so fond of 
using, which really means esoterists (Geheimtuer), is very unsuitable, and it is 
high time that we avoided this foreign word.” — The whole question* appears 
under a different aspect among those who hold that the Anabaptists and 
“spiritual reformers” are the logical result of the principle of Church fellowship 
and of liberty of conscience of the Reformation, like Weingarten: Revolutions - 
kirchen Englands, 1868, p. 442; and A. Dorner: Grundriss der Dogmengeschichte, 1833 , 
pp. 253 ff. Thinkers of this school usually overlook the fact that the Dissenters 
are also in the direct line of the mediaeval development, only they belong to 
a tendency which is different from that which the Reformers are carrying 
forward. The emphasis on a manifold relationship with the ideas of the 
Reformation, which had not yet become ecclesiastically settled, is quite right. — 
The able book by Erbkam still deserves attention at the present day ; it contains 
much suggestive matter, but he is quite wrong in his conclusions. In his 
opinion the Anabaptists represent ethical mysticism, while the “spiritual 
reformers” represent intellectual mysticism. Together they are thus supposed 
to be a continuous supplement, brought down from the Middle Ages, of the 
objective and institutional character of the Church, which ought to have 
formed the complementary movement in Protestantism. These movements, 
however, broke away from Protestantism in an unhealthy manner, and some 
of them merged into pantheism; he concludes by pointing out the peril of 
separation from the Church as the organ of salvation. — A wealth of source- 
material, and an illumination of the whole movement from local points of 
view, can be found in Hochhuth: Protestant. Sektengeschichte in Hessen , Z- f hist. 
Theologie, XXVIII-XXXII. Here also everything starts from the Reformation 
and the criticism of its defective moral achievement. — There is an excellent 
description of the German Anabaptist movement in Cornelius: Gesch. d. Miins- 
terschen Aufruhrs, 1855-60; a socialistically coloured collective description in 
E. Belfort Bax: Rise and Fall of the Anabaptists, London, 1303 (the closing chapter 
is particularly important with its indications of continuations in the English 
Revolution) ; from the Baptist standpoint, A. H. Newman: History of Antipeda- 
baptism, Philadelphia, 1897, the most detailed account of the whole movement, 
unfortunately only until 1609 ; finally, the article “ Tdufer ”, by Kramer: PRE*. — 



PROTESTANTISM 


95 * 

There is also a good deal of important material in Gobel: Gesch . des christl. Lebens. 
For the connection of this movement (including the Pietist Separatist groups) 
with the weaving and cloth-making industries, which appeared especially 
among the Waldensians, see I, 37-39 ; for the connection with the numerous 
Waldensians of the Rhineland, I, 40-42. Gobel connects with this also the 
victory of Calvinism over Lutheranism in these lands, since Calvinism was 
more closely related to the Waldensian ascetic Christians. A very good descrip- 
tion of the Baptist movement as a sect-type (/, pp. 143- 149). Here also his view 
is fair : “a quite definite tendency of Christian life which, in its fanatical form, 
could indeed be fought against and also violently stamped out, but in its 
truth and necessity could never be completely suppressed and overcome”, 
“it also should be definitely recognized as a Christian movement” (/, 133). 
In Pietism he sees only the reappearance of this tendency ; /, 757, and in other 
places. In all this, however, he has not distinguished clearly enough between 
the ideas of the sect-type and of mysticism. 

441 (p. 696.) Cf. the description in G. Arnold , II, 264 ff., and 524 ff., who, 
however, separates himself clearly from them: “Although there was much 
human foolishness, blindness, and weakness among them, there was also to 
be seen in many # a great simplicity and fidelity of obedience, because they tried 
to follow the letter of Scripture with so great exactitude, that also in so doing 
they fell into other untimely opinions (this means that they became exclusive 
and intolerant) and they themselves came into disrepute and fell on evil 
days.” Arnold himself sides with the mystics. In Arnold, II, 266, we have Luther’s 
opinion: “This monster can be controlled neither by sword nor by fire. They 
leave wife, child, house, and farm, all that they have.” Also the opinion of 
Melanchthon: “No one should be distressed when they see the Anabaptists 
going to death so confidently and suffering so many things, because Satan has 
hardened their hearts.” The Calvinist controversialist, Hornbeck, is somewhat 
milder: “It was not so much that the Anabaptists withstood the orthodox 
Protestants with their doctrine by adding another or a new doctrine, as that 
they did not quite understand the doctrine of orthodox Protestantism.” In 
Arnold, 11,524 , we have a later orthodox opinion : “If I regard the Anabaptists 
and the Mennonites they seem to lead forsooth a hypocritical kind of life, they 
avoid fine clothes, swearing, lying, gluttony, drinking, adultery, villainy, 
quarrels, and contentions like the devil, so that whoever comes into their 
community or their society stands almost amazed, thinking that he has not 
come among men, but among angels in the form of men, or, at least, that he is 
among living saints and elect, genuine Christians.” — Of fundamental impor- 
tance also is the description given by Sebastian Franck ( Ketzerchronik , 193-201 ), 
whom Keller very wrongly calls a “genuine Baptist” {Ref., p. 462), and who in 
any case knows nothing about Keller’s early Protestant communities. Franck 
says simply about their origin : “In the year 1526, both during and after the 
Peasants’ Revolt, there arose a new sect and a separate Church founded upon 
the letter of Scripture which some call Anabaptists and others Baptists, who 
began to separate themselves from others with a particular baptism and to 
despise all other communities as unchristian ; also they believed that no one 
could be saved or be their brother who did not belong to their sect or their 
party. They began to baptize all those who joined them for the second time, 
ot± rather, as they gave out, to baptize according to the command of Christ. . . . 
Their overseer and bishop was first Balthasar Hiibner, then Melchior Rink, 
followed by Joh. Hut, Joh. Denck, Ludwig Hetzer. . . . They appeared to teach 
nothing but love, faith, and the Cross, in much suffering they showed them- 



952 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

selves patient and humble; they broke bread with one another as a sign of 
unity and love; they helped each other faithfully with lending, borrowing, 
giving away, and they taught that all things should be in common ; they called 
each other brethren. If, however, anyone did not belong to their sect they 
scarcely greeted him, they would not stretch out the hand to him, they kept 
together, and increased so greatly from year to year that the world was afraid 
that they would cause an uproar/ * The terrible persecution and the number of 
martyrdoms convinced the masses that these were true Christians, and thus 
they again gathered large numbers of adherents. Then it seems that many 
Baptists went beyond the good which was undoubtedly in them. “They 
became in spirit somewhat uppish, they began to judge everyone, anc^in many 
places they became disunited amongst themselves and they had as many 
doctrines as they had leaders. . . . Although I entirely believe that it is true 
that many pious, simple people were and still are in this sect, and that many 
of their leaders also have been ardent for God, but to my thinking not with 
knowledge. However, one ought not thus to tyrannize over them when they 
are obstinate and will not allow themselves to be taught, but we must commend 
them to God, who alone can give faith, root out heresy, and give good counsel 
in the whole matter.” These are the characteristic features of the sect-type 
until the present day. “In their communities there is so much excommunication 
that every community excommunicates the other, and there is as much 
freedom to believe what they will as there is among the Anabaptists. Vyhoever 
in their communities does not say Yes in all these matters, they say that 
God has stopped his ears, and they begin to pray for him with sighs and tears. 
If he does not soon change his mind they cast him out” (193*). Thence also 
a great confusion : “Although all sects are split amongst themselves, yet the 
Baptists are so specially disunited and broken up amongst themselves that I do 
not know how to describe anything certain and complete about them” (i93 b ). 
If we tabulate the different shades of opinion which Franck describes, we find 
that there are two main groups : those who have joined settled organizations 
and are bound by the law of the Scriptures, and those who favour rather 
enthusiasm and mysticism, and therefore become individualists without fellow- 
ship, but who still find their adherence essentially in Baptist circles. Later on 
we shall hear more about this difference. The “free Baptists”, which were so 
called from the time of Bullinger, were not Baptists, but spiritual Klealists. — 
Schwenkfeld and Franck agree. Cf. Ecke, 89, 204-212. 

442 (p* 6970 Cf. the well-known collections of passages in which Lutheranism 
testifies against itself in Dollinger and Janssen. Still more striking is the treatment 
of the subject by the honest Gottfried Arnold, and this point of view also prevails 
in Franck’s Geschichtsbibel. Quite rightly Hegler has attempted to understand 
Franck entirely from this point of view, just as Ecke has tried to do with 
Schwenkfeld. Also in the splendid book by Paul Drews : Der evang. Geistliche i. d. 
deutsch . Vergangenheit, 1905, the description of the moral condition both of the 
clergy and of the laity gives a very dark picture. It is not sufficient to explain 
this meagre success as the after-result of earlier Catholic education, or to recall 
the later chaos caused by war. The very limited moral success of the Reforma- 
tion is certainly due to something in its own nature ; see Ecke , 88. The ideals 
were too high and the means of education were limited. It was impossible to 
realize these ideals until Pietism undertook the care of souls, and later the more 
humane morality of the Enlightenment, and popular education were also of 
great use. How very limited this morality was, however, is revealed, for 
example, by the well-known autobiography of the notorious Magister Lauck- 



PROTESTANTISM 


953 

hardt. The raising of the average morality of the masses has, indeed, in general 
only been achieved by elementary education and the modern State, in which 
then, however, the ideals were not primarily drawn from a highly idealistic 
Lutheranism. 

445 (P* 699*) Thus it appears as though Munzer left the circle influenced by 
Luther and went over into the conventicles of Zwickau ( Thudichum , /, 215 ) ; 
Keller also has made it seem probable that Grebel was connected with the 
Waldensians ( Reformation , 381-388 ) ; also it is obvious that many of the Baptist 
preachers had already been leaders of conventicles even before Adult Baptism 
had been introduced ( Ketzerschulen , 32). In the protocols of the trials of the 
Anabaptists which are mentioned in Wappler: Inquisition und Ketzcrprozess in 
Zwickau , 1908, there are several references to a Waldensian origin (pp. 121 , 
I2 3 jff •)• On the other hand, the heretical “godless painters of Nurnberg”, with 
whom Denck was in touch, seem to have been of a very different character. 

447 (p. 702.) An opponent ofjoh. Arndt says very strikingly, even though with 
the characteristic disapproval of Arnold : “Those people would be wrong who 
would apply to all the teachings contained in Arndt’s or Tauler’s books since 
ordinary life requires quite other manners” ( G . Arnold , //, 438). This is also the 
central point of Bullinger’s criticism of the Anabaptists ; they are against the 
Christian love \thich embraces the whole of humanity and endurance of 
circumstances “willed” by God; cf. Sebastian Franck: Ketzerchronik , p. 133. 
On the .other hand, Schwenkfcld directs his criticism precisely against the 
national Church and recognizes its connection with popular “sacramentalism” 

( Ecke , 103). 

460 (p. 706.) Cf. the sketch in Barclay: The Inner Life , pp . 79-89 . The acceptance 
of the Calvinistic ethic of “the calling”, in which the old Baptist asceticism is 
only carried on in the avoidance of all outward luxury and all external honours, 
is rightly emphasized by Max Weber: Archiv f. Soz., XXI , p. 69. The criticism 
of the Radicals from the standpoint of “spiritualist” asceticism frequently in 
Hylkema: Reformateurs ; further, see Kramer: PRE z y the article on Memo und 
Mennoniten; also Gobel , II, 690-697. Here is an extract from a letter by 
William III of Orange: “I have always been assured of the submissive and 
peaceful spirit of the Mennonites, who behave themselves with resignation and 
perfect obedience towards their superiors, leading a peaceful and laborious life 
and contributing willingly to the upkeep of the State and of the country in 
which they live, to which they render themselves useful by their industry and 
their work.” Here also there is information about their industrial capitalistic 
character. 

463 (p. 707.) The Particular (that is, Predestinarian) Baptists are not to be 
connected with this. The latter are pure Calvinists who deduced Adult Baptism 
from the theory of the Free Churches, just as, on the other hand, the Free 
Churches in their day arose out of the ideal of believers’ Baptism. That becomes 
plain when we remember the formal connection between the Free Church 
and the sect-ideal which was explained when we were dealing with Calvinism ; 
Newman , p. 393; Barclay , p. 318 : “They consisted of little companies of 
respectable, godly people, gathered from Presbyterian worship, into what they 
deemed a more Scriptural form of Church discipline, and gradually became 
convinced of the importance and Scriptural sanction of immersion.” 

464 (P* 7°9«) Gf. Glass: The Barebones Parliament. Weingarten makes too little 
distinction between the Anabaptists and Independents; his statement on 
p. 138: “In Cromwell the Anabaptist movement reaches its high-water mark, 
but it was also his doing that Anabaptism ceased to be a power”, is only 



954 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

accurate to a very limited extent. Further, Gooch: The History of English Demo- 
cratic Ideas in the Seventeenth Century, Cambridge, 1898, a very solid and instructive 
book, which Weingarten expands and carries further. For the economic and 
social historical side of the matter, cf. the important work by E. Bernstein: 
Kommunistische und sozicdistische Stromungen wahrend der englischen Revolution des 
18. Jahrh.,m“Geschichte des Sozialismus inEinzeldarstellungen” , I, 1895, pp. 507-718 ; 
here, of course, according to socialistic historical dogma all that is religious is 
only a transparent veil for economic social endeavours which are here present 
in their pre-Marxian, thatis, their ideological, and, indeed, Christian Anabaptist, 
stage ; further, Belfort Bax: Rise and Fall of the Anabaptists, London , 1903, in which 
the whole is indirectly ascribed to the Baptist movement. — All the, accounts 
recognized the essentially Baptist character of the later radical movement, 
which removes the Presbyterian and Calvinistic-Independent character ; both 
the accounts of the question and the sources make constant reference to strong 
remnants of radical Baptists ; cf. Weingarten, pp. 1 03-103, the witness of Baillies, 
Weingarten, pp. 127, 179, Anm. 2, 263. Further, Gooch, 73-75, 128-129, 174 ff., 
267-270 ; Bernstein , 509, 522; Vorspiel im Jahre 1549 , 523-327; Lollharden und 
Tdufcr. For the relation to Luther see a pamphlet in Weingarten, p. 114: “The 
time of Jerome of Prague or of Luther was but a little better Jhan the darkest 
time of Popery.” That is the language of Baptists and of “spiritual reformers”. 
There are many references to the radical Baptists who are distinguished from 
the peaceful General Baptists in Barclay: The Inner Life, and in the important 
book by Firth: Cromwell's Army, 1902, which, unfortunately, does not pursue 
this subject in further detail. Dispute of the Army Chaplains about Infant 
Baptism (p. 325) ; in favour of lay preaching, by Lieut. Chillandon in the tract, 
Preaching Without Ordination ; the lieutenant became an Anabaptist preacher. 
P. 336: Lay preaching, especially that of the officers, came into being because 
the Presbyterian pastors were withdrawn from the army. Firth, 334 ff., likewise 
Bernstein, 546. It was connected with Chiliasm, since at the coming of the 
Kingdom the settled ministry will disappear. This lay preaching of the officers 
and their religious discussions, easily led to religious-political theories (Firth, 
p. 337). Yet the right of free preaching was never unrestricted and uncontrolled ; 
it ended with the cleansing of the army from all “Anabaptist” elements, 
whereby, however, Cromwell expressly desired to retain the more peaceful 
“Anabaptist” in the army. A pamphlet of 1655 (Firth, 342 ff.) thuff addresses 
Cromwell : “And so were you at Dunbar in Scotland, or at least you seemed 
so by your words and your actions ; for you spake as pure Independency as any 
of us all then, and made this an argument why we should fight stoutly because 
we had the prayers of the Independents and Baptist Churches. So highly did 
you seem to love the Anabaptists then, that you did not only invite them into 
the army, but entertained them in your family.” The ethical religious argument 
for the war against the previous authority was at first that of the Huguenots, 
the Scots, and the Calvinists, the soldier’s catechism in Firth, 330, and the tract 
by Bridge about the right of armed resistance in Hanbury: Historical Memorials 
Relating to the Independents , II, 189 ff. With the incursion of Chiliasm the argu- 
ment becomes different : the task is now to prepare for the Kingdom of Christ. 
A tract by Archer entitled The Personal Reign of Christ upon Earth, 1642, which 
Herr Sippell has most kindly lent me, is particularly instructive upon this 
point. With that the conception of the right of war becomes very similar to that 
of the Baptists or is directly dependent upon it. — Otherwise the influencing of 
the army through politics is the result of the break with Parliament and signifies 
the rise of a definite political and social class in the army (Firth, 318, 351-354 ). 



PROTESTANTISM 


955 

Originally consisting of men who had been impressed, it had no interest of 
its own. Since 1651 the army consists only of volunteers because its one aim 
is to fight for one’s people and one’s religion. The real headquarters of these 
volunteers was from the beginning in Cromwell’s cavalry. — For the absolute 
Natural Law of the sect which arose with that at the same time in contrast 
to the relative Natural Law of the Church, and the Natural Law of the social 
contract of the Huguenot and Scottish type which was still conceived on class 
lines, see Gooch , pp. 108 ff., also pp. 117 and 133-162 ( Ireton ) ; the transition to 
radicalism,//*. 176 (Godwin) and 180 (Milton) ; the radical Natural Law of the 
Primitive State, of Reason, and of Christ, without compromise with sin, 
pp . 184 ffp, ng , 328. Particularly in the treatise of Berens about the Diggers, 
which will be mentioned directly : “First we demand yea or no, whether the 
earth with her fruits was made to be bought and sold from one to another? 
And whether one part of mankind was made to be a lord of the land and 
another part a servant by the law of Creation before the Fall?” For Bunyan, 
see Belfort Bax , pp. 379-381. 

465 (P- 7 11 *) Forthe “Levellers” thebest account in Gooch, pp. 139- 157, 193-206, 
256-239. Here the conception of Weingarten seems the most singular ; he secs 
in them disguised Rationalists and even the beginnings of Deism, because he 
does not recognize the absolute Natural Law in its identity with Reason and 
the law of Christ as the early sect-idea. The absolute Law of Nature appears 
to him to be modern Rationalism, which it is not. Bernstein goes still further : 
he thinks that the religious element was merely superficial and was only used 
as a cover for something else. The treatise by Overton : Man's Mortality , to which 
he appeals, pp. 579 ff., still only denies the so-called intermediate State and 
teaches a full physical resurrection. The Epicurean expressions of Walwyn 
{pp. 581 ff.) show a good deal more, although they are reported by opponents. 
In Lilburn himself and the whole movement there can be no doubt at all 
about the essentially spiritual and religious basis. The rejection of dogma and 
of the plan of salvation, also its allegorizing tendency, reveals a spirituality 
of the type of Sebastian Franck, but not a concealed surrender of its religious 
basis. The treatise, entitled The Craftsman's Craft, 1649 > quoted by Weingarten: 
p . 307, as well as the treatise written in defence of Walwyn, The Charity of 
Churchmen fboth probably by the same writer), has been made known to me by 
the kindness of Herr Sippell. Of the religious element it contains more than 
the mere confession of the existence of God quoted by W. It defends Overton’s 
expression of opinion about the mortality of the body (which was touched 
upon above), expressly asserting the resurrection of the spirit and its reincarna- 
tion; it protects itself, further, with a characteristic limitation, against the 
reproach of Anabaptism of the Munster pattern: “Where proofs are wanting 
there are resemblances insinuated in their stead ; and comparisons made either 
in such things as are true of neither, or else the Party that is to be made odious 
is likened to such as are already in some particulars not material; and yet thereby is 
suggested a similitude in all the rest." This, however, amounts to a confession of 
the Baptist ideal, apart from some particulars not material. Above all, there is 
the argument of the demand of the “Levellers” as a movement : “We answer, 
that we cannot suppose, nor do we think any rational man to believe, the thing 
unlawful in itself; for then the primitive Christians did what was unlawful." The 
principle in itself is Christian and reasonable ; only it must not be forced upon 
people with violence : “To make it lawful there must be an unanimous and 
individual consent of every man thereunto.” This also shows in what consisted 
the particulars , which the “Levellers” disapproved in the Munster Anabaptists ; 



956 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

in the spirit of violence which was against the Christian spirit. The statement 
quoted by Weingarten,p. 304, shows, however, only the spirituality of the people, 
whose non-rationalistic spirit we shall learn more about later on. 

456 (p. 712.) Cf. Gooch, pp. 214-223; Bernstein, pp. 383-608; above all, the book 
by Berens: The Digger Movement in the Days of the Commonwealth , London , 1306 , 
which provides the most important account of the subject. The fact that W. 
describes God as Reason, or Creative Reason, has led many people to think 
that these ideas are essentially rationalistic. W., however, begins with the 
Familists and ends with the Quakers. The Creative Reason is the Logos identical 
with the indwelling Christ: “This spirit of Reason is not without a man, but 
within every man ; hence he need not to run after others to tell him of to teach 
him ; for this Spirit is his Maker, He dwells in him, and if the flesh were subject 
thereunto he would daily find teaching therefrom, though he dwelt alone and 
saw the face of no other man” (p. 43). “Even so, Christ, which is the spreading 
Power, is now beginning to fill every man and woman with Himself. He will 
dwell and rule in everyone : and the Law of Reason and equity shall be Christ 
in them. . . . This is the Church, the great congregation which, when the 
mystery is completed, shall be the mystical Body of Christ all set at liberty from 
inward and outward straits and bondage, and this is called thoholy breathing, 
that made all new by Himself and for Himself” ( p . 67). “The Golden Rule, do 
to another as thou wouldst have another do to thee, which God, Christ, and 
Scripture have enacted for a law” (p. 171). “The law of creation and equity 
of the Scriptures” (p. 138). “That their intent is to restore the Creation to its 
former condition” (p. 37). In this sense the idea is always also that of the 
birthright or of the inborn right, or of the rights of humanity. Here already 
we meet this significant idea, and, indeed, as one which is based upon religion. 
The birthright is, at the same time, the pre-Norman English right of the 
people, as once in the Wycliffe movement; before the Conquest the Law of 
Nature prevailed. Such passages are innumerable ; this is the Christian Natural 
Law in the form of the sect which is well known to us, and, further, it is united 
with mystical spirituality. For W.'s relation to the Baptists, see/). 63 (they are 
too external for him). — For Plockboy, see Bernstein, pp. 683-634 , and Laspeyres, 
pp. 103 ff . — For Bellers, see Bernstein , pp. 634-728. 

468 (P* 7 * 4 *) For this cf. my treatment of the subject which ^eals with 
Independency and the significance of the Cromwellian period in Kultur d. G., 
IV, 12 , pp. 388-600. The material which is there united is here broken up into 
its various component parts, and each one is dealt with in connection with its 
position in the course of development. “Independency” is, indeed, something 
very great and complicated in which the most varied elements are united. 
My treatment of the influence of the Baptist element, which there was dealt 
with in a very general manner, and which, further, was too much at that time 
under the influence of Weingarten, is now more exactly defined. With that are 
removed the partially justified misgivings which were aroused by Loofs in his 
Luther und Mittelalter : p. 13. 

459 (p. 719.) Cf. the excellent article by Mirbt: Pietismus, in PRE 3 , XV, further 
Ritschl; Heppe; Grunberg: Spener , 1833, J 9°5> T 9o6; Gobel: Geschichte d. christlichen 
Lebens in der rheinisch-westphdlischen ev. Kirche, 1843 , 1832 , i860. Stephan: Pietismus 
als Trdger des Fortschritts, 1308; W. Kohler: Anfdnge des Pietismus in Giessen, 1683- 
1633, i n Giessener Festschrift of 1307. For the social connections, see Gustav 
Freytag in his Bildem aus der deutschen Vergangenheit; Bertholdt: Die Erweckten im 
prot. Deutschland (Raumers historisches Taschenbuch , 1832 and 1833), here the 
Calvinistic, non-Spener character of the phenomena, which have been 



PROTESTANTISM 


957 

described, is not taken into account ; Drews: Einfluss der Kirche auf die gesell - 
schafilichen Zustande , Z-f- Th. u. K., 1905; Uhlhorn: Liebestdtigkeit , III , 236-261; 
especially Ritschl, II, 500-505; Max Weber: Archiv XXI, pp. 39-36. Weingarten 
in general does not sufficiently distinguish the various currents of thought, 
and unfortunately he has paid no attention to the Pietist current in its difference 
from Congregationalism and the Baptist movement in England, even though 
incidentally he actually describes it excellently . — RitschVs work — in its own 
way magnificent — is based upon the clear recognition of the sectarian character 
of Pietism, and for this reason, from the standpoint of a complete bourgeois 
and Churchman, is a polemic which on account of its absolutely inquisitorial 
penetration is of the highest importance. It is most interesting and instructive 
that in Ritschl this hostile attitude towards Pietism is caused by the fact that 
he saw clearly that only a Territorial Church system, based upon the doctrine 
of the remission of sins, and only a Church which is guided by an objective 
ministry, can support the moral relativism necessary for a popular Christianity 
of the masses and the relatively moderate Rationalism of a scientific theology. 
“Christianity, in the shape of a people’s Church, in order to maintain its own 
existence, is obliged to take the middle path in matters of public custom, and 
also to allow for many varieties and degrees of individual religious experience” 
( 7 , 178). “The # root cause of all Separatism lies in the fact that the relative 
character of ecclesiastical relations is not admitted” ( 7 , 430). “Originally 
Pietisrq concentrated its attention upon the moral security of the salvation of 
each individual in opposition to the world, and on the rejection of all con- 
siderations which the Church usually practises towards the world” ( 7 , 450). 
“Lutheranism, which gave all its attention to purity of doctrine, remained out 
of direct contact with the ethical and aesthetic needs which ought to be met 
within the sphere of the religious education of a people.” Thus so far Pietism 
in his opinion was already prepared for by the Church itself ( 77 , 88). “He who 
in his place does his duty as a Christian must thus judge in the faith that 
where the Gospel is purely and sincerely preached there God has His Church.” 
( 77 , 131). “A life which starts from conviction of sin and a genuine conversion 
may still bring about very many more testing experiences of Christian per- 
fection. It has, however, moved away from the sphere of the exclusive Church 
connection, and if it finds a corresponding sphere of fellowship in sect or 
clique or Enlightenment, this has not been foreseen in that principle” ( 77 , 194 ). 
These statements illuminate excellently the spirit of the Church-type. There is, 
however, no need to emphasize, on the other hand, the fact that the sect and 
mysticism are nearer to primitive Christianity than the Church, and that the 
appeal to the Early Church in Jerusalem is relatively justified. — The latter 
point has been seen much more clearly and truly by Gobel : “All these orgies 
and dangerous excesses (of Pietism) are so closely connected with the (Scrip- 
turally) thoroughly justified ways of the Christian life that they still always 
ought to be regarded as Christian phenomena; indeed, frequently the right 
method only develops itself out of the excess which was originally combined 
with sinful one-sidedness and error ; for instance, it was only through mysticism 
and Separatism that genuine mysticism and asceticism came to their right 
position both in individual believers and in special groups, as well as by a 
reflex action in the dominant Church itself” ( 7 , 3). A splendid collective 
characterization, which completely agrees with my own conception ( 77 , 617- 
621). Mirbt explains Pietistic asceticism as “occupation with Holy Scripture 
to whose ascetic elements the Pietisticaliy inclined Bible-reader of that day, 
who was already under the influence of eschatological tendencies, brought 



958 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

understanding” (XV, 804). — The opinion of Uhlhom, p . 260: “Pietism has not 
yet found the right attitude towards secular things, particularly to the State, 
to science, and to art. It regards them from its subjective standpoint (that is, 
from a non-ecclesiastical standpoint which is only interested in conversion and 
the maturity of the individual Christian), as justified so far as they are of use 
to it; unlike Lutheranism, it judges by itself that their substance is justified.” 
(This is erroneously and obscurely formulated ; it means that over against the 
peculiar mixture of world denial and world acceptance in Lutheranism 
the Pietistic ethic completes the ascetic consequence by linking up with the 
Calvinistic ethic (see Max Weber: Archiv XXI , pp. 46-50), which takes away 
from the secular all value of its own, but moulds it in a quite utilitarian way, 
rationally and methodically, as a means to an end; hence also the ideals of 
Pietism with regard to education are exactly the same as those of Puritanism.) 
Piety is for it not the principle of life which penetrates everything, but the sole 
content of life. For that reason Pietism has no interest in social questions. 
From its point of view such things are just part of “the world”, which it regards 
in a cool and detached manner. In spite of the tendency to intervene everywhere 
in all these spheres of life, it still remains unfruitful. Pietism has helped to 
weaken the importance of the Church in these spheres of li{jp, and it is also 
due to it that works of charity, especially the care of the poor, have been 
brought into the hands of the State.” — It is important to notice that Ritschl 
has entirely ignored English Puritanism, which everywhere merges into 
Pietism. Ritschl knew no English, and this circumstance led to very one-sided 
results in the studies of those who followed him in this subject. — Here Heppe 
and Barclay must complete the picture. — For the social and economic effects, 
Weber, pp. 55 ff. : “Quite obviously thus in German Lutheran Pietism the 
preparation of the religious need for a present inward, emotional sentiment 
thus contained a minimum of stimulus for the rationalizing of activity within 
this world, contrasted with the need of the preservation of Calvinistic “saints” 
which was directed only towards the future life, whereas they, for their part, 
over against the traditionalist piety of the orthodox Lutheran, which centred 
in the Word and the Sacrament, were always adapted to develop a maximum 
of methodical religious penetration of life.” The increasing development of a 
merely emotional tendency is also connected with the social divergence of the 
movement towards the clergy and the nobility. “If here we should characterize 
one practical consequence of the difference . . . the virtues which Pietism 
brought forth may be described rather as those which, on the one hand, 
the loyal official, workman, and home-worker, and, on the other hand, the 
patriarchally minded employer would display in a condescension which is well- 
pleasing to God. Calvinism seems in comparison with that to have a greater 
affinity with the hard legal and active spirit of bourgeois capitalistic entre- 
preneurs.”-— The peculiarities of Wurttemberg Pietism, which in Germany is the 
only kind which has been really popular, are connected with the insignificance 
of the nobility in that part, with the disposition of a free peasantry towards 
religious individualism and with the early connection in that region of Pietism 
with the Church, against which, however, there react until the present day 
Separatist peasant movements ; see Mirbt and Ritschl ; also Kalbe: Kirchen und 
Sekten der Gegenwart s , 1910. — For the fact that Pietism within the Church 
belonged to the aristocracy, the clergy and the official world, and that of the 
radical Pietists to the lower classes as a result of the social upheavals of the 
wars of religion, see Becker: Zmjendorf, pp. 240-243 ; at any rate, that is the view 
of the Count. — For the genuine inner connection of Calvinism with Pietism* 



PROTESTANTISM 959 

according to which the conventicles do not disturb the Church idea at all, 
and its inner opposition to and disturbing effect upon Lutheranism, see the 
views of Zinztftdorf: ebd., pp . 246-250 . — For the darker side of the Pietistic 
sectarian movement, see Harnack : Alte Bekannte , Aus Wissenschaft und Leben , 
//, 277-288 .— Quite lately I have seen Goters : Vorbereit. d. Piet, in den Nieder- 
landen, 1911, obviously a linking-up of the German development with the 
Netherlands. 

480 (P* 721.) Cf. Ritschl : Gesch . d. Piet., Illy in which, however, the pedantic 
treatment of the subject, the derivation of all the “dangerous errors” of the 
“theological dilettante”, Zinzendorf, from a “careless” interpretation of the 
Lutheran, conception of the Church, is intolerable. In addition to Ritschl , 
the following book is indispensable, Jos. Th. Muller: Z • a ^ s Erneuerer der alten 
Bruderkirche, 1900. With regard to the main point, the recognition of the tension 
between the mystical supra-ecclesiastical ideal and the sectarian ideal of the 
Moravians, Ritschl had, however, quite a right understanding of the case, 
and he also rightly recognized the danger for the Church. Cf. also Muller , p. 40: 
“Where an approximate historical realization of this conception (of an ‘evident 
community of Christ’) is attempted, there the structure which arises out of 
it — whether it b^an ‘evident community of Christ* or whatever one may call it — 
will always be more capable of realizing the Christian ideal than the popular 
and State churches, in the midst of whom it lives. ... At the same time, 
howeves, it follows necessarily out of the conception of an ‘evident community 
of Christ* that, in a community which has arisen out of an historical situation, 
this character cannot remain attached to it as an inalienable possession, nor 
can it become a birthright, because every time it depends upon the personal 
Christian piety of the members.” It is precisely upon the understanding of this 
difference between Church and sect that everything depends. — It is from this 
point of view also that we must answer the question which Loofs once put to 
me in a letter : Could Lutheranism — under quite other external circumstances 
— have produced an ethic exactly similar to that of the Moravian Church? The 
question is very instructive, since here the theoretical ethical basis is un- 
doubtedly Lutheran both in its spirit and in the letter. We must, however, 
remember that the ethic of a sect and of a State Church is still always entirely 
different. The sect is very little confused by being drawn into official positions 
in the Start, politics, law, or war, and therefore it does not need, like Luther, 
to deduce all these things from the Christian Law of Nature and to take them 
into the Christian ethic as matters of fundamental importance. The difference 
between official and personal morality, which is so important in Lutheranism, 
here entirely disappears, and all that remains is personal morality. This personal 
morality, however, on account of mutual control, the effects of the smallness 
and narrowness of the circle, and the habit of measuring everything by the 
standard of the Bible, resulted in a strict morality which fostered a spirit of clear 
detachment from the world. Scruples about the oath, official service and war, 
similar to those of the Anabaptists, are mentioned by Muller , 27 , 92; Ritschl , III, 
244; Approaches to Communism , III, 296; Renunciation of State Law and Arbitration 
within the Community , III, 346-348 ; it is the spirit of the Sermon on the Mount, 
which Ritschl , however, recognizes to such a limited extent that in all this he 
sees nothing but “freaks”. But the ethic of proof and active holiness here play a 
much greater part ( Ritschl , III, 398 , 439, 247) than in ecclesiastical Lutheranism, 
as Ritschl and Muller both rightly admit. It is certainly quite possible to argue 
that the agrarian character of Luther’s economic ethic, and the overwhelming 
industrial character of the Moravian ethic, is due solely to external circum- 



g6o THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

stances (see Ritschl , III , 347; Muller , 79 am/ #4). This also, however, is connected 
with the difference between the free and mobile Church association ( Muller , 
pp . 24-27 , 40) and the State Church. The former is adapted to the mobile 
industrial population which at that time was in request by mercantilism, 
whereas the State Church had to consider the peasantry which was bound to 
the soil and the landed nobility. Also the business enterprise of the community 
belongs to the nature of the sect, which must maintain itself, and does not live 
on benefices and subsidies from the State. The difference, therefore, is an 
essential one, based upon something inward, which, just because of the equality 
of the theoretical ethical foundations and because of the brokenness of the 
sect-character in the Moravian Church, is most characteristic for the sociological 
effect of the sect-type, which is so different from anything that the Church-type 
can produce. In addition, cf. Max Weber: Archiv XXI , pp. 50-37. — It has not yet 
been clearly established how far Calvinistic business morality may have also 
influenced the Moravian ethic in detail ; this question still needs to be studied. 
It is, however, significant that the Count likes to take his parables from the 
world of business ; speaking of the inwardness with which the treasure of grace 
of the Church becomes one’s own possession of the heart, he says: “I will have 
fellowship, therefore I must have a treasure, a share in the society, to which I 
wish to belong. . . . And where can one find that better than in His immediate 
presence?” ( Becker : Zinzendorf^p. 26) ; about the justification of the conventicle 
in the Lutheran Church: “What reasonable man would say that if twelve 
citizens introduced a merchant company for the furtherance of trade they 
ought eo ipso to be separated from all the other citizens and from their country?” 
(p. 134). It is also significant that in these words there is a connection with the 
non-Lutheran Natural Law of Grotius and Pufendorf (further, in detail, see 
Becker, p. 117) ; Spener also had already shown a preference for the Natural 
Law of Calvinism. This is connected instinctively with the sect-idea or with 
mere religious sociability. The Count also had much sympathy with a man 
called Bayle. 

461 (p. 724.) Cf. the brilliant presentation of the subject by W. C. H. Lecky: 
History of England in the Eighteenth Century, II, 321-642, which is very fair and 
impartial ; here also the opposition to culture is emphasized in which, however, 
as is always the case in such groups, the purely practical sciences are made an 
exception. Otherwise there still exists belief in devils, demons, and witches, in 
direct illuminations and miracles, healings, and Divine inspirations, a special 
Providence which continually breaks through Nature in favour of believers. 
For asceticism, see pp. 383 ff. After Wesley had visited the British Museum he 
wrote: “What account will a man give to the Judge of quick and dead for a 
life spent in collecting all these?” For the constitution, see the excellent article 
by Loofs: “ Meth .”, PRE\ XII, and Nuelsen: “Meth. in Amerika ,> , PRE 8 , XIII; 
for the ethic, see the fine section in Schneckenburger : Lehrbegriffe der kleineren prot. 
Kirchenparteien , 1863, pp. 103-131, and Max Weber: Archiv XXI, pp. 57-61. — 
With reference to Baptism, see Loofs, XII, p. 773 ; in Wesley’s abbreviation of 
the Thirty-Nine Articles, baptismal regeneration is set aside ; he does not deal 
with “de peccatis post baptismum”, but with “of sin after justification” ; 
in Article 15 the statement “Nos reliqui (alongside of Christ), etiam baptisati 
et in Christo regenerati, in multis tamen offendimus et, si dixerimus, quia 
peccatum non habemus, nos ipos seducimus” is set aside, as Loofs thinks* in 
favour of Perfectionism, but also, that which is closely connected with it to the 
disadvantage of Infant Baptism. Nuelsen quotes from the Catechism by Nast: 
The new birth “does not take place through Baptism, but it is effected by God 



PROTESTANTISM 9 6i 

at the same time with the justification which is attained by faith” (XIII, 14 ). 
Baptism, therefore, is replaced by revival work in classes of children and the 
intensive work in the school. Candidates are received first of all for a period of 
probation if they reveal an honest desire for salvation, and final admission 
into the community is preceded by this first question : “Do ye renew in the 
presence of God and of this congregation the solemn vow which is contained 
in the Covenant of Baptism?” (XIII, 18). Here, however Baptism is always 
eliminated in practice. Schneckenburger , p. 148: “Both sacraments, therefore, fall 
more under the conception of commands of Christ to which one must submit. 
Therefore, quite logically, one section of the Methodists have developed Baptist 
ideas. Amongst American Methodists Infant Baptism has almost entirely 
disappeared (?).” — Everywhere the development from the Church-type into 
the sect-type is apparent. The Methodists of South America have done away 
with the probationary period altogether. XIII, 18: “Baptized children of 
Church members are placed on a level with members on probation, and when 
they have reached a suitable age to be able to understand the binding character 
of religion, and when they can give proof of genuine piety and upon the 
recommendation of a leader in whose class they must have been under instruc- 
tion for at leas* six months, they can be received into the Church as full 
members, while they publicly accept the baptismal covenant in the sight of the 
congregation and answer in the affirmative the questions about doctrine and 
Church*order. The practice of confirmation is not known in Methodism, yet 
the pastors are obliged to divide the baptized children as soon as they are 
ten years old into special classes and to instruct them in those truths which are 
necessary to make them wise unto salvation” (XIII, p. 19). “In many con- 
gregations since the time of a pastor’s ministry (at one station) has been 
lengthened, the Class system has been introduced, and instead of individual 
classes every Sunday there is a general Class Meeting (testimony meeting) or 
the weekly prayer and experience meeting. The testimony meeting of the 
youth association has been brought in” ( ebd ., iy). Loofs gives the following 
summary ( XII, p. 810) : “At one time people were only received as members 
who had been at least two months on probation in a Class. Now the member- 
ship in the junior Society Classes counts as a probationary period, which means 
that the children of Methodists grow up into the Society just as they do in 
State Churches. Human nature being what it is, there must be several amongst 
these members who have thus grown up within the Society, who do not fit 
spiritually into the Methodist Church. A Methodist National Church is an 
impossibility. Methodism will never wholly overcome the difficulties which are 
caused by the tension between its growing expansion and its Society character 
(which cannot be quite removed from it), unless it ceases to be what it is.” — 
Further, it is Loofs in particular who, in his presentation, allows the sectarian 
features to remain in the background in a remarkable way; these features are 
much more clearly expressed by the Methodist Nuelsen . He desires a similar 
awakening for Germany, where, in his opinion, everything is ripe for another 
Wesley, and where the movement ought not to be separated from the Church. 
Only against such an awakening we must place the fact that the functions 
which were at that time exercised by Methodism have among us been taken 
over long ago by social democracy, upon whom a message of the type of 
Wesley’s would make no impression at all. Loofs also underestimates the 
difference in the inner structure when he thinks that it would be possible to 
combine a Territorial Church and Methodism. If the Gemeinschaftsbewegung 
(Fellowship Movement) among us were to grow to a similar size, then we also 
vol. n. kk 



962 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

would find it impossible to unite the two types. Such things depend on num- 
bers. — For the class limitation of Methodism, see Lecky , 600-602. 

484 (P- 7 2 ^.) For Christian Socialism, in addition to the works which have 
already been indicated, see those of Theod. Mayer , Ratzinger , Uhlhom , Naumann , 
Gohre , Wenk, von Schulze-Gavemitz , Rauschenbusch , Wemle , Traub, Ragaz , and 
Kutter, also the Biography of the Bishop 1/0/1 Ketteler Pfiilf, 1899, and the articles 
“Christlich-Sozial” , “ Evangelisch-Sozial” > “ Katholisch-Sozial” , in Schiele* s Lexikon , 
also the essay by Ragaz: “Z ur gegenwdrtigen Umgestaltung des Christentums ” 
(Neue Wege , ifaj*/, /pop), and by Liechtenhahn: Die religios-soziale Bewegung in der 
Schweiz ( Christl . WW/, /p//), and also the collected addresses of the ifcr/i/i W'or/d 
Congress for Free Christianity , Religion , Socialism , published by Schneemelcher, 

jqii . — For the fanatical early stages of Marxian Socialism, see Sombart: 
Sozialismus und soziale Bewegung 5 , /pop; he rightly emphasizes the strongly 
rationalistic and equalitarian element which the religion of the Enlightenment 
has brought into this kind of Chiliasm. — The religious social movement in 
Switzerland gives the clearest interpretation of the problem of Christian 
Socialism, and in it there are revealed most plainly the essentially Christian 
motives of this whole group of thinkers. The Evangelisch-soziale Kongress occupies 
an intermediate position. The “ Kirchlich-Sozialen** of the Catholic and Lutheran 
kind are not Socialists at all. — In a practical judgment of matters we must not 
overlook the fact that the real social development approaches rather analogous 
mediaeval attempts to solve the problem of the struggle for existence: This is 
being illustrated in many ways at the present time. 

In any case, it is clear that everywhere individualism is being restricted, and 
that soon there will no longer be too much individualism, but too little. As 
political tendencies are becoming increasingly Democratic, religion may once 
again provide a refuge for individualism. On this point see the excellent book 
by Joh . Plenge: Marx und Hegel , 1911 . The book is conceived entirely from the 
point of view upon which my own work is based. For the future possibilities of 
our social development, see above all, pp. iyQ-182. 

445 (p* 7 2 9*) An infinite amount has been written about Tolstoi, but very little 
that is good. The article by Johannes Muller: Chr. Welt , /p//, pp. 218-224 , is 
excellent : “The new life which Jesus represented and aroused was alien to his 
thought. This life which welled up out of invisible depths, filling^ restoring, 
creating, the stable and free superiority to all things upon that point outside 
the world which lies within us, the divine ‘Yea* to all that exists, the goodness 
which at bottom lies in all this, the truth which struggles for life, which sees 
the glory shining through and therefore sets God’s seal upon it ; the love, the 
outpoured life and the surrender of the soul without choice and without limits, 
the reverence and kindness, the wrestling for the immediate experience in the 
inmost soul, he knew not.” That is a good word for the Christian ethic, but, 
however, the formation of this life in the concrete conditions of existence 
remains difficult enough. Muller , for his part, thinks also of a transformation 
of the world, and he regards Tolstoi at least as a signpost pointing to the 
forgotten radicalism of Christianity: “He opened my eyes to the fact that 
Christianity had become conformed to the spirit of this world, while the state- 
ment of theologians that it must be secularized in order to become a world- 
religion only had the effect of increasing the mistrust which had been aroused. 
If only it had remained the way to life which is called a sect** c 

444 (P* 73°*) Appeals to Luther’s teaching on the Spirit : in Sebastian Franck: 
Ketzerchronih , II, igc/>; Hegler: Geist und Schrift, p . 269; Gottfried Arnold , II, 229: 
“It is well known from Luther’s writings that in his earlier works he often 



PROTESTANTISM 


963 

wrote very freely about this grace (the inspiration of the Spirit), indeed, often 
his language gave more offence than that of many people who were called 
Enthusiasts, and he also referred everything to the Spirit** ; among the Quakers, 
Arnold , II, 661, 671 , and 673. — Otto: Anschauung vom hi. Geiste bei Luther , 1898, 
also shows the beginnings, only with this exception that seeking opposition to 
the “fanatics** in the wrong place he explains Luther himself too much in the 
sense of a “Spiritualist**. — For the measure of “Spirituality** in Luther, Zwingli, 
Calvin, Capito, Oecolampadius, and Bucer, see the interesting accounts in 
Richard GriUzmacher: Wort und Geist , 1902. Luther and Zwingli also regard the 
doctrine of predestination in this sense as an expression of the immediacy of 
the expeyence. Capito even goes back to the old mystical idea that the inner 
illumination is only kindled in the elect through the Divine Spark which 
indwells man. Oecolampadius even published writings of Schwenkfeld. Bucer 
is absolutely a preacher of the immediacy of the Spirit in connection with 
predestination. To the extent in which Luther did not merely co-ordinate the 
working of the Spirit with that of the Scriptures, but made this (the Scriptures) 
the sole means, the doctrine of predestination retired into the background and 
the idea of the Church and the objectivity of salvation came into the fore- 
ground. Calvin ^tvoided all this by the idea which he established at the outset 
that predestination worked out in the Scriptures, the ministry, and the Church. 
— It is plain how much Spirituality of this kind there was among the Reformers. 
Therefore these ideas appeared afresh again and again out of the influence of 
their writings. Sippell gives a particularly interesting example in W. Dells 
Programm. The sermons which I have been able to get at in an edition of Dell’s 
works of 181 7( !) reveal everywhere a distinct and conscious affinity with the 
“spiritual” elements in Luther. The same is true of the Lutheran Antinomians, 
who were the horror of the Puritan Precisians and the men of the jus divinum 
in the Church ; see Sippell, pp . 2-4. 

470 (p* 733 *) For primitive Christian “Enthusiasm”, see Gunkel: Wirkungen des 

hi. Geistes nach der populdren Anschauung der apostol. Zeit und nach der Lehre des 
Apostels Paulus 3 , 1909 ; Weinel: Geist und Geister im nachapostol. 1899 ; 

Taufe und Abendmahl bei Paulus, 1903 ; for the mysticism of Paul there is very 
instructive material in Reitzenstein : Die hellenistischen Mystereinreligionen, 1910 . 
From this point of view we can also understand the idea of an opposition 
between I%ul and the Christ according to the flesh, which becomes to so great 
an extent a starting-point for fantastical conclusions. All mystics after Paul 
have also thought like that about dogma. Reitzenstein emphasizes rightly that 
there is in Paul also “conflict between the autonomy of religious feeling and the 
rigidity of tradition” (p.38) ; the “mystical ideas freed themselves imperceptibly 
at the outset from the tradition which had begun to form within the Church 
upon Jewish soil, and the struggle which soon followed brought him the con- 
sciousness of freedom which for him now is everywhere where the Spirit of the 
Lord is** (p. 60). — Also Deissmann: Paulus, 1911 , brings this out without, however, 
in this respect sufficiently recognizing the conflict between the primitive com- 
munity and the starting-point for all “spiritual” mysticism. The emphasis on 
the combination of historical and “spiritual” elements is very apt. P. 134: The 
first leads to the sect, the second to spiritualismus. 

471 (p* 74 ®*) For this cf. above all Preger: Gesch . d. deutschen Mystik, one of the 
grpat classics of Church-history. In different places also there is a great deal of 
material in Ritschl and Harnack . Denifie identifies this kind of mysticism with 
Scholasticism, and says that he sees no difference between them; this seems to 
me very much the point of view of an apologist and does not touch the psycho- 



964 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

logical depth of the problem. The reason that Ritschl and his disciples accepted 
this statement so eagerly was that in that way they wished to complete the 
equation of Catholicism with mysticism, like that of Catholicism, the Anabaptist 
movement, the sect, and monasticism. In that way, then, from the standpoint 
of the Lutheran Church, mysticism is dismissed. — Further, particularly in 
Ritschl' s Geschichte des Pietismus , there are a number of most acute conclusions 
based upon detailed study, in which his Churchly instinct displays the essential 
anti-ecclesiasticism of mysticism, even in its expressions, which still seem to be 
quite in harmony with the Church and with dogma. But even so there can be 
no question of any identification with Catholicism. The well-known statement 
by Harnack that anyone who is a mystic without becoming a Catholic is a 
dilettante, I cannot feel is in any sense right. On the other hand, however, the 
equation of mysticism and spiritualismus with the essential idea of Protestantism, 
which is the tendency of Weingarten , A. Dorner , Barge , and also Dilthey , is 
certainly not right, even though we ought not to depreciate the strongly 
“spiritual” element in Luther. It is that element in Luther which the modern 
man understands best of all. The Luther monument at Worms bears not in 
vain solely “spiritual” sayings. — Very valuable also is the great work by F. von 
Hiigel, one of the leaders of so-called Modernism: The Metical Element of 
Religion as Studied in St. Catherine of Genoa and Her Friends , London , 1908; this 
book gives one such an insight into the wealth of the component parts which 
constitute the Christian world of thought as is given in few other works; 
in the course of time Christianity has become an entirely complex religion. 

478 (P- 740.) For the whole, see above all Gottfried Arnold ', and also Ludwig 
Keller: Erbkam; Geschichte d. Pietismus bei Gobel , Heppe , and Ritschl. There is a 
good deal in Hegler: Geist und Schrift bei Sebastian Franck , who, on p. 277, tries a 
grouping; further, Maronier: Het inwendig word , Amsterdam , 1890 ; Rich. Griitz - 
macher : Wort und Geist , 1902 , also the fine treatment of the subject by Dilthey in 
Archivf. Gesch. d. Philos. Of ecclesiastical theologians the nearest to this tendency 
were Capito and Oecolampadius ; Bucer's relationship to it still needs to be examined. 
Cf. also Hegler: Beitrage zur Gesch. d. Mystik in der Reformations zeit, issued by 
W. Kohler, 1906; this consists of extracts from writings by members of the 
group influenced by Sebastian Franck. In Sippell: Ueber den Ur sprung des 
Qudkertums , there are some valuable remarks; a very apt observation about 
the difference between Enthusiasm and mysticism, Chr. W., 1916 , p. 460. — 
A splendid collective characterization also of this tendency in Gobel , II, 680- 
690 , who also sees very clearly the difference between the sectarian Separatist 
groups (Labadie and Spener) and the mystical Separatist groups (above all, 
Gottfried Arnold). 

474 (p* 74^*) Cf. the statement of Ernst Ludwig Gruber , which is quoted in 
Gobel , II, p. 681: “The true Separatists do not begin any new sect, neither do 
they try to build up that which was broken down, but they retire into the 
inward sanctuary, into their heart, wherein they seek to serve God in Christ 
Jesus through His mercy, in spirit and in truth, for whose gracious revelation 
and appearance in them and without them they then wait with joyful and 
believing hope, and, for the rest, they lead a quiet and exemplary life; also, so 
far as they have means and opportunity, they try to show all the love they owe 
to their own members and to their fellow-men. There is not much to say about 
their outward service of God because they have no formed and distinct rules, 
habits, and times, but they arrange such in accordance with the daily, hourly, 
and momentary impulse of God and the opportunity which is offered to them 
with prayer, singing, reading, and the handling of the Divine Word to the 



PROTESTANTISM 965 

edification of themselves and of others. ” On this point see further the descrip- 
tion of the mystical Separatists in II and III ; there the sociological characteristic 
of the “Philadelphian period” {III, 71-86), also the “Philadelphian invitation” 
G&bely however, only treats the movements of Calvinistic and Lutheran 
mystical Separatism in West Germany. The subject is wider than that. Already 
in Preger there are all kinds of material of a quite similar kind for mediaeval 
mysticism, further material in Hegler's Schrift und Geist. Gobel and Ritschl 
describe only the comparatively small Pietistic conventicles in which, owing 
to the fact that they were excluded from participation in public affairs, was 
diverted into the channels of religious brooding ; these religious Grubelei groups 
were sometimes emotional, sometimes very dull, and sometimes overexcited. 
Among such people there is no trace of the great ideas of mysticism of the 
kind represented by Sebastian Franck, Gastellio, and Goornheert. Only the 
latter, however, can be compared with the Church way of thought in greatness 
and theoretical acuteness. 

476 (p. 748.) Ritschl , who is the harshest and most acute opponent of mysti- 
cism, is very instructive upon this point. As he develops his institutional 
Church interest in close connection with popular Christianity, he is obliged 
to teach that th$ forgiveness of sins is an attribute of the congregation or of the 
Church, in which the individual as a member of the Church shares through 
Baptism. Corresponding to this he opposes in mysticism nothing so much as 
its neglect of both the correlates : objective assurance of the remission of sins 
and the Christian community as an institutional Church. No one has recognized 
these connections as clearly as he has. Therefore from this point of view he has 
based his own ecclesiastical dogma upon the correlation of Christ, the assurance 
of the forgiveness of sins and the Church. His teaching, however, is particularly 
interesting because he questions the atonement as the basis of the forgiveness 
of sins. He is, therefore, obliged to construct this doctrine as the endowment of 
the Church, with a certainty based upon the supernatural authority of Christ, 
in God’s readiness to forgive sin, and in so doing he comes very close to the 
Socinians, amongst whom, however, he misses the correlation with the Church. 
Thus it is extremely interesting to read his detailed explanation of the 
“Spiritualist” Dippel and £inzendotf {Geschichte des Pietismus , III , 423-433), of 
whom the former denies the atonement and the latter maintains it, and both 
destroy, of at least weaken, the idea of the Church. Through emphasis on the 
Church and her objective assurance of remission of sins, for which it is not the 
atonement which is needed but Christ’s guarantee, he resolves the conflict 
between the two in a “higher third”. 

477 (p. 748.) For this simplification, see Otto: Anschauung Luthers vom hi. Geiste; 
also Kant-Friesische Religionsphilosophie , pp. 18-23 > on ^y it is wrong to refer the 
corresponding endeavours after simplification of the theology of the Enlighten- 
ment to Luther ; it is Pietism and Spiritualismus which this theology here follows. 
Luther’s development of the “verbum consummatum ac breve”, out of the 
objective means of salvation, of the Word into doctrine, is the unavoidable 
result of ecclesiastical theology, which has an absolute external authority and 
must have it in the orthodox sense of the conception of the Church, and which 
then, naturally, must also develop this authority out to the circumference in 
order to leave no obscurities in which fanaticism could establish itself. 

4 78 (p. 751.) Cf. my Trennung von Staat und Kirche , pp. 21 ff. The deduction of 
a uniform Church system and of intolerance, also of the opposite attitude from 
the manner of the conception of truth, seems to me a very important point to 
recognize. Yet at that time I did not recognize sufficiently the difference 



966 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

between the Baptist movement and Spiritualismus , in ascribing the opposite 
position simply to the Anabaptist movement. As the Church is connected with 
a definite conception of truth, so also the sect and Spiritualismus are connected 
with a definite conception of truth. The sect renounces compulsion and con- 
formity, but not the absolute character of the conception of truth ; Spiritualismus 
makes it relative in various forms of expression of a truth which is only to be 
attained spiritually and inwardly, and which, therefore, can never be finally 
and adequately formulated at all. 

479 (p* 752.) The relationship between Spiritualismus and the moralist 
sectarianism and the Enlightenment, which for orthodox minds like that of 
R. Griitzmacher is a natural thing, is also a leading idea of Ritschl, who 
absolutely derives the Enlightenment from this disintegration of a sound 
Church system. Thus he forms at this point the astonishing equation of 
Catholicism, monasticism, sectarianism, mysticism, and Enlightenment, in 
which every member at the same time represents the unhealthiness of the other 
one, and over against which there only remains RitschVs moderately rationalist 
but still essentially positively supernatural Lutheran ecclesiasticism, which is 
adapted to a modern popular ethic. Thus, at that time also, following Ritschl , 
W. Bender in Dippel: Der Freigeist aus dem Pietismus , 1882, has described the self- 
transformation of mysticism into Enlightenment. These statements, however, 
in Ritschl are obviously nothing more than an apologetic for his ecclesiastical 
Lutheranism, and Bender's statement is positively false. The change of opinion 
into Rationalism which takes place just as much in orthodoxy as it does in 
Pietism and in mysticism, must have its reason in something which equally lies 
beyond them all ; this is proved by the fact that this same phenomenon occurs 
after quite different presuppositions. In orthodoxy the transition takes place 
by means of its intellectual, scholastic element, in holiness-Pietism by means of 
its moralist element, and in secular and scientific matters by means of its 
purely utilitarian, empirical element, in mysticism by means of its idea of a 
timeless religious element which is contained in Reason or the soul as such. 
In every case, however, the Enlightenment does not arise out of religious 
interests, but out of the political and social upheaval, and out of the emancipa- 
tion of interests from the leading religious ideas of the past ; this is accompanied 
by a completely new, that is, causal natural-science orientated philosophy, and 
by a development of new technical possibilities which is connected therewith. 
The Enlightenment was the stronger movement, and in all groups it sought the 
element which was akin to it at that time ; naturally this is different every time. 
The change into Enlightenment on that account never took place naturally 
anywhere. In England the change was achieved by the Whig revolution and 
prepared for by the Cromwell revolution. The Enlightenment only penetrated 
into European life on the Continent as the result of this struggle and of this 
victory, and in other countries it never made its way completely without a 
struggle. The fight was carried through, above all, by absolute royalty. The fact 
that then the new movement everywhere drew out of the old that which was 
akin to it is indeed clear. In this sense many Christian ideas — altered — also live 
on in the Enlightenment, above all the idea of Natural Law and Natural 
Right, which I have studied in its development; see my essay, Das stoisch- 
cknstliche Naturrecht und das modeme profane Naturrecht , //.£., 1911, VoL 106. 
All the individualism of the Enlightenment is connected with the Christian 
subjective tendency which existed apart from the churches, as Plenge: a.a.O ., 
brings out very aptly in many places. Its ultimate reason, however, the social 
upheaval and the definite rise of the bourgeoisie, is likewise connected with the 



PROTESTANTISM 967 

previous Protestant development, but with only the ethical social effect, which 
was quite unintended, of increasing the commercial bourgeoisie ; on this point, 
see Max Weber . — The connection between Deism and the radical parties and 
“Spiritual Reformers ,, of the English Revolution has not yet been made 
thoroughly clear. In Locke’s principle of toleration it is clear. But Locke’s 
theology and also that of Toland suggest the presence of Arminian and Socinian 
influences. Among the average Deists the opposition of the Dissenters to the 
whole Catholic element is clear, but there is no trace of a merging of mystical 
or Pietistical ideas in Rationalism. In Germany, Edelmann and Lorenz 
Schmidt, influenced by Spinoza, do not represent a phase of Christian 
mysticisnj. — Dilthey also seems to me to overestimate the “rational element” 
in the “Universal Theism” of Franck and Coornheert.— The difference between 
“spiritual religion” and the rationalistic theology of the Socinians, Arminians, 
and the Deists is also quite interesting on its sociological side. These Rationalists 
liked to remain within the churches, confining their efforts to introducing 
liberal ideas, or else at least they were content if they were tolerated ; the reason 
for this was that they realized that in their scientific arguments they possessed 
a driving force which was much weaker psychologically, and that they were 
only able to reach the intellectual classes ; their own power of forming churches 
did not suffice. When they were forced to separate from the churches they 
revealed an energy in propaganda and instruction, a scientific instinct for truth 
which i§ quite alien to mysticism and “Spiritual” religion in general. It would 
be very attractive to study the sociological aspect of the rationalist group- 
formations through the centuries down to the free religious group-formations 
of the present day. They do not in any way resemble the free mystical groups, 
neither have they any similarity with Holiness groups, nor with the Church. 
Ritschl, with his extraordinarily acute power of detecting any divergence from 
the Church-type, compares this tendency with the school (Rechtf. und Vers.*, /, 
pp. 320-323), and he deduces from this characteristic its approximation to the 
sect- type, its intellectual propaganda, its lack of emphasis upon worship, and 
the frequency of division about opinions on doctrine. The uniting element 
is only intellectual agreement combined with all the needs of expansion and 
instruction, but also with all the dangers of division and the lack of that com- 
prehensive spiritual substance which belongs to the common possession of the 
permanent witness of the churches. 

480 (P* 753 -) Ritschl* s Geschichte des Pietismus gives a good deal of information 
upon this point also. Otherwise it is not possible to generalize on this question. 
This is precisely the difference between the “spiritual” ethic and every kind of 
ecclesiastical and sectarian ethic. Above all, it is important to recognize that 
asceticism has here more of a metaphysical and directly religious meaning than 
one of discipline, and just on that account it can also easily develop into 
libertinism. In connection with these groups, therefore Weber's, description of 
asceticism does not apply at all, unless perhaps owing to its Calvinistic origin 
they understood asceticism from the beginning in the Calvinistic sense; an 
example of this is Tersteegen, who thought that Zinzcndorf was frivolous. — 
Information on ethics also in Hegler : Geist und Schrift, pp. 148-150, 166, 170-184 . 
In Franck the social doctrines are essentially the same as those of Luther, only 
the spirit of resignation is still more evident. — Reference to the absolute Law 
of # Nature, which is here naturally equated with the Divine Seed and the 
Divine Spark, with the higher Divine Nature which humanity contains, but 
which also agrees with the natural moral consciousness and is identical with 
the Decalogue— in Hegler , pp. 209, 243 , 116; the Ten Commandments con- 



968 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

tained in the “inner Word” ( pp . 92 ff.). The “Natural Law of love” in the 
mystic Sperber ( Ritschl , I, 304) ; likewise Dipped I, 337 ; conscience and Natural 
Law, the eternal Word and the supernatural Light ( 7 , 354) , which Ritschl 
naturally immediately regards as Illuminism. In Barclay, p. 225, some elders 
declare that the Holy Ghost is imparted not only through the Word, but also 
through “His handywork in the whole creation, the Law of Nature written 
in the hearts of mankind, the light of conscience”. — Saltmarsh, whose Sparkles of 
Glory , 1647 , in a Jubilee edition of 1847, has been sent to me by Herr Sippell, 
is most interesting. There breaks forth from the degree of Nature, or the Law 
of Nature, impelled by its conscious sense of its incapacity to attain an ultimate 
value, the law of the Spirit as a higher stage: “The Christian is*one who 
should live in an higher region than flesh or nature ; and when God sayth ‘Come 
up hither’ he shall live there even in the Spirit with Him ; so as though grace 
destroys not nature, yet it perfects and glorifies nature, and leads it out into 
higher and more excellent attainements, than it can find in itself. Nature lives 
by this law: preserve thyself, thy life, thy lands, thy rights, and privileges, 
avenge thyself, an eye for an eye and a tooth for a tooth and love only thy 
neighbour. Grace lives by this law : deny thyself, forsake lands, life, houses, take 
up the cross, if he take thy cloak let him have thy coat also, love thy enemies, 
bless them that curse thee.” That reminds us of the Catholic application of the 
idea of development, but it is conceived rather differently. Nature, which 
finally asserts itself in the competitive struggle and the desire for self-preservation, 
becomes an ethic of love directed by God, “disengaged from the love of power, 
dominion, riches, earthly glory”. The morality of the New Testament is only 
a literal preparatory stage and preparation for this third stage of the ethic of 
love, which is to be exercised in the freedom of the Spirit. These are conceptions 
of Natural Law and of grace which I have never met anywhere else, and which 
contain an element of profound truth. 

482 (p- 756-) Cf. the great work by Barge , who, however, takes up a very one- 
sided position in favour of Karlstadt for the sake of the political-social position, 
which also for Karlstadt lay quite on the circumference. The mysticism of 
Karlstadt would certainly have been both unable and unwilling to create 
anything permanent in this direction. But Luther’s ruthless attitude towards 
the opponents of his idea of the Church is here, however, rightly and instruc- 
tively brought out quite clearly. In the official picture of Luther these traits 
are usually very much toned down. Also Scheel: Individualismus und Gemein - 
schaftsleben Z* Th. R., 1907; R. Griitzmacher , 156-158; Gottfried Arnold, II, 231-239. 

483 (P* 758*) Cf. Griitzmacher , Art. Schw. PRE Z , Wort und Geist, pp. 158-173; 
Gottfried Arnold, II, 246-261 , who goes into great detail here and does not 
disguise his sympathy. Griitzmacher as well as Preger refer to possible in- 
fluences of the Bohemian-Moravian Baptists and their theory of the Verbum 
substantiate and Verbum grammatical. In any case, from the point of view of 
religious psychology his theory is very subtle, see Griitzmacher : Wort und Geist, 
p. 165 : “The Scriptures are only an image and a parable of that which was 
worked in the hearts of the Prophets through inspiration.” “Whereas one can 
neither write nor express with the lips spirit and life, but can only express it in 
parable, so must one know how to distinguish as is meet between the Scripture 
and the living Word of God (that is, the inward Word), and not give symbols 
of that which is rei et veritatis.” “For although God has spoken through His 
Spirit with the holy men by whom the Scriptures were written, and gave to 
them what they ought to write, this does not mean that He spoke to them 
through writing syllables and letters as we would do, but through spirit, 



PROTESTANTISM 969 

power, and life (which according to their nature cannot be written down in 
a book, but only according to a parable or a picture), to which, then, a spiritual 
judgment will belong through which the written Word is distinguished from 
the living Word of God and the image from the truth.* * “The holy men of 
God who were moved to write and to speak by the Holy Ghost were not able 
to express and to give to others in tablets of stone and in the Scriptures the 
wealth which they had received as they felt it livingly within their hearts. 
Scarcely were they able to give any picture of it at all, and with sound voice 
or Scripture to witness in the Holy Spirit. The pen was unable to express the 
heart entirely on paper, neither could the lips give utterance to that which it 
had taste^l of the living fountain, but therefore they have given us their message, 
as much as is necessary to us, in parable, and through that means they have 
pointed to the one and only Saviour, Fountain, and Light (that is, to the 
Christ who reveals Himself within our hearts)”. Several times Schwenkfeld 
tried to get into friendly contact with Luther, but always in vain. At the last 
attempt Luther gave the messenger a note with the words : “The silly fool who 
is possessed by the Devil doesn’t understand anything or know anything of 
what he is talking about. . . . And this is my last word : the Lord curse thee, 
thou Satan, and thy spirit, and all thy ways and all that belongs to thee” 
( Arnold , II, 251). Other orthodox theologians were more just in their opinions : 
“He wanted to be neutral, a sceptic, an unusual man.” “He agreed neither 
with the Papists nor with the Lutherans, nor with the Sakramentierer [i.e. 
Zwinglians and others. — Tr.] nor Anabaptists, but in everysecthe onlyapproves 
of something, and he goes off on a new and peculiar form of religion of his 
own” {Arnold, II, 242). He himself expresses his views in a similar manner: 
“That I now belong to no party or sect as men call them, neither to the 
Papists nor to the Lutherans, neither to the Zwinglians, nor to the Baptists on 
account of my conscience, has many reasons and this brings to me not a little 
persecution. ... I do not try to hide the fact of this separation, and I hold it 
as certain that the Christian should go with his heart out of this wicked world 
in order that he may again and again direct his heart into the heavenly sphere 
where his treasure is, even Jesus Christ” {ibid.). On p. 242 he emphasizes very 
clearly the opposition to the popular and National Church, which was becoming 
increasingly rigid in its objectivity. In Pennsylvania there are to-day still four 
congregations of Schwenkfelders, with 306 members ( Newman , p. 156). — The 
newest and the fullest account of the subject is the book by Karl Ecke : Schwenk- 
feld, Luther und der Gedanke einer apostolischen Reformation, igu , a very valuable 
book. It is written from the standpoint of the Pietistic Fellowship Movement, 
and in Schwenkfeld it celebrates the founder of his movement, who, in agree- 
ment with Luther’s original ideal of the ecclesiolae, was, however, on the other 
hand unable to go with Luther in his tendency towards popular Christianity 
and the sacramentalism which was bound up with it (especially p. 103) ; in the 
writer’s opinion Schwenkfeld developed Luther’s original idea from the Bible 
into a pneumatic charismatic form of fellowship Christianity, and in so doing 
he reached the true idea of Christian fellowship. In spite of the most cautious 
treatment of Luther, Luther here comes out in a similar light to that in which 
he is treated in Barge's Karlstadt. Ecke defends his hero against the charge of 
“heretical mysticism” like that of Franck, for example, who “has never scaled 
the heights of the Reformation experience of salvation” {p. g6), as against 
mysticism and Anabaptism in general in order to explain him purely from 
the point of view of primitive Christianity. This, however, is only true in so far 
as the Bible itself actually contains elements of sectarianism and of mysticism. 



970 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Otherwise, Sippell: K. S. Chr . W., lgn , rightly inserts him once again in the 
mystical and sectarian succession as a combination of both. Schwenkfeld’s 
judgment about Luther’s treatise Himmlische Propheten, Ecke , p. 80 is worthy 
of note: “Would to God that people would look carefully into this little book 
with their eyes wide open, looking at Christ our Lord therein and at His 
divine truth, and would that they might compare this with the previous writings 
of Dr. Martin, and that they might know whither and how far he has now 
come, and that they might understand how much misery, instability, and error 
are therein and in the future will still be born out of this.” — Very interesting 
opinions of Schwenkfeld about the Baptists in Ecke, 204-212 , 8g. So far as ethics 
are concerned it is characteristic that Schwenkfeld complains that the J^utheran 
merchants did not observe Luther’s ethic at all, but only the forgiveness of sins 
and predestination (p. 163). — The influential ideas of the disappearance of the 
primitive Church, of the ecclesiastical formalism which has prevailed since 
then, of the immanence of an apostolic reformer with Divine credentials, of the 
future outpouring of the Spirit and of the End which will then follow; see 
Ecke , pp. 227 , 323-334. The Chiliasm of the Anabaptists was of a different kind, 
although its basis was the same ; from this point of view also a light falls upon 
the question of the emergence of eschatological ideas in Independency and 
Pietism. Every attempt to take the question of a Holy Community seriously 
for the masses leads to Chiliasm. 

4®3a (p 759.) For Weigel, see Griitzmacher : Wort und Geist, pp. 185-igfi; here 
Weigel appeals to the younger Luther: “In the books of Luther ye had better 
seek; there ye will find even such words as ye have heard from me at this 
present in especial in his earlier writings.” His radical subjective theory of 
knowledge (“All knowledge comes from the knower”), and the identification 
of the psychological religious movement of thought with the thought of the 
Logos or of the Divine Nature of Christ in us, has also procured him a place in 
histories of philosophy; see J . E. Erdmann: Grundriss , IP, 1878 , pp. 483-488, 
and Windelband : Geschichte der neueren Philosophic 3 , I, 483-488. It is genuine 
Neo-Platonic mysticism in which its Christian character is only preserved by 
the assumption of a positive agreement with the Logos and Christianity. 

484 (p. 762.) Cf. the excellent book by Hegler ; Gottfried Arnold, who adopted 
Franck’s idea of the Ketzer geschichte, and continued it, and in general is very 
close to his position {II, 281-283) ; Dilthey: Archiv V, 38g~400. Dilthey does not 
emphasize, in my opinion, the connection with mediaeval mysticism strongly 
enough, and he modernizes too much. The relation between his ideas and the 
modern philosophy of religion after Lessing, Kant, Schleiermacher, and Hegel, 
is indeed evident. In Franck, however, there is no question of the historic 
movement of truth; his conception of truth is completely non-historical, 
absolute, entirely spiritualized ; he champions a dualism which is hostile to the 
world, which excludes a progressive and victorious religious movement, and 
is absolutely opposed to modern ethics ; finally, he treats the Scriptures more 
along the lines of allegory and occultism than as the history of religion, or 
psychologically. His individualism, which dispensed with external forms of 
worship, and his mystical idea of immanence, meet with the approval of 
modern people, as is shown by the new edition of his Paradoxa, rgio, published 
by the Diederich Verlag. Luther took no notice of Franck, who, owing to his 
individualism, condemned himself to be ineffective ; only after Franck’s desgh 
did Luther thus express himself: “He had not wished to write anything against 
such an evil man because he despised him too much ; he was a blasphemer, the 
Devil’s own and favourite mouthpiece. ... So far as I can understand and 



PROTESTANTISM 


97i 

judge he is either an Enthusiast or a ‘Geisterer*, who is content with nothing 
except ‘Spirit*, ‘Spirit*, ‘Spirit* (‘Geist’, ‘Geist’, ‘Geist*), who has no use for the 
Word, the Sacrament or the ministry. . . . He has wandered through all kinds 
of filth, and has at last got stifled in it** ( Arnold , 77, 282 ). This was Luther’s 
verdict on one of the noblest and freest souls of that period. In Germany he was 
soon forgotten, but his influence was felt for some time in the Netherlands. 
Arnold could only get hold of his writings with difficulty ! Gf. in addition, also, 
Hegler's Programing Sebastian Franck's Lateinische Paraphrase der deutschen Theologie , 
und seine hollandisch erhaltenen Traktate ”, 1901 ; also 77 '. Ziegler: £./. wiss. Theol ., 
1907 ; also Hegler's Beitrdge zur Geschichte der Mystik. Herr Sippell will report 
about Franck’s writings in England, which he has found in some of the archives 
there. It seems to me that a man like Saltmarsh is unintelligible without Franck ; 
their ideas are everywhere akin to each other, and at the same time they are 
most winning, human, and gracious. 

485 (p. 764.) Cf. the excellent book by Buisson: Sebastien Castellion , sa Vie et son 
(Euvre, Paris , 1892. For Castellio’s mysticism and spirituality, see 7, 310-314; 
77, pp. 38 , 99 , 194-197 , 201-213 , 239. The essence of this toleration with its 
“spiritual** basis, which still counts so strongly with the general Christian 
atmosphere that from the point of view of toleration it only envisages differences 
between Christians, but otherwise takes it as a matter of course that the 
“Spiritual Christian truth’’ will propagate itself, see 7, pp. 366 , 373; 77, 38 , 
290 , 29 5. Castellio compares particular dogmas to the small coin which varies 
in every country, while he compares the truth of the Spirit with the gold which 
is accepted everywhere. Thus we can understand how it came to be later on 
that in England and America toleration was only exercised within Christianity 
and did not include atheism. This is not illogical, but it is the result of the 
“spiritual” argument for toleration. The only difference between this idea of 
toleration, with its confidence in the victory of the Spirit, and Luther’s earlier 
position is this, that for Castellio the “Spirit”, with its looser and often alle- 
gorical relation to the letter of Scripture, is a simpler and less defined principle 
than Luther’s idea of the Spirit, which is always combined with the “Word”. 
A greater freedom of movement thus arises. But it would be erroneous to 
consider this freedom as one which is without restrictions. This enlarged 
of toleration, however, is based upon a different conception of 
that of the Reformers. The truth lies in the power of the Spirit 
which is sealed subjectively in the conscience, whereas all that is external, 
literal, ceremonial, and institutional is merely relatively valuable, a veil for the 
truth which can only be lifted by the Spirit. Absolute truth is limited to the 
spirit ; it is, however, here also clear and inescapable. All that is literal, both 
Bible and dogma, on the contrary, belong to the sphere of relative truth. At the 
same time this truth is entirely subjective, only to be tested by the individual 
in his own experience. It is thus neither the conception of truth of modern 
science nor that of the ecclesiastical organ ofsalvation, but it is that of “spiritual” 
religion and of mysticism. — We can well understand why his opponents were 
so horrified ; in these ideas they beheld the essence of Satanic dangers, “academic 
scepticism”, “arrogant fantasy”, the removal of all possibility of a true Church 
and a stable authority (77, 23-39, 122, 249, 233, 238). Very characteristic is 
Beza*s objection to the idea of trust in the spiritual self-propagation of the 
trfith : “What then is the Church to do? She must cry to the Lord, you will say, 
and He will hear her. . . . Yea indeed, she will cry to the Lord. . . . But he 
who is hungry also cries to the Lord, but at the same time he does not wait 
for an angel to bring him something to eat, but the food which another gives 


conception 
truth from 



97a THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

him or that he himself will have acquired by honest and right means, he will 
take as from the hand of God” (//, p. 27). Here in reality is the real point at 
issue. In this idea of mystical trust in the victory of the Spirit and the relativism 
which tolerated various kinds of literalisms, the ideal of the united Church 
and self-affirmation in the feverish mass struggles of the time could not possibly 
be carried through. Castellio’s weak point, therefore, lies in the lack of clearness 
of his conception of the Church. He never thinks at all about the formation of 
sects or conventicles, but always about the triumph of the Spirit in a spiritual 
way for the whole (II , 57, 230) : “Be content with agreement with the principal 
points of religion which are clear and evident in the Holy Scriptures, then 
they are at every point in agreement with you.” True Christians, however, are 
rare (II, 232) : “Those who thus care about numbers (like Calvin), and for 
that reason treat people with compulsion, resemble a fool who, broaching a big 
barrel and only finding a little wine therein, fills it up with water in order to 
have more, and in so doing he does not increase his wine, and he even spoils 
that which was good. For which reason we must not be surprised if to-day the 
wine of the Christians is so little and weak since it is mixed with such a lot of 
water!” In order to keep the Church pure he considers that it would be 
sufficient to exclude people from fellowship without any civil punishment (II, 
235) : “These are the right methods of resisting heretics : by words if they use 
words, by force if they use force.” All this is still much further removed from 
modern ideas of toleration than Buisson thinks. 

487 (p. 766.) For the relationship between Castellio and Coornheert, see 
Buisson , II, 324 ff. ; for C.’s mystical doctrine, see Heppe: Geschichte des Pietismus 
und der Mystik in der reform. Kirche namentl. d. Niederlande , 1879, pp. 80-86. “These 
saints are and live in Christ, who is the Light of the world and therefore they 
alone can know God. Taught by God Himself, by means of His living Word, 
namely, the Logos, and by the Spirit of truth, and led into all truth, and 
illuminated by the unction of the Spirit, they need not henceforth that any 
man should teach them” (p. 84). “Christ has become Man . . . and has risen 
gloriously in order that we through His active obedience in us should in Him 
become Divine” (p. 88). An acquaintance also with Franck and Schwenkfeld 
is highly probable. Dilthey : Archiv V, 486-493 , brings him too near to Erasmus, 
even though he says also that “he went far beyond that which Erasmus con- 
sidered it politic to say in his writings” (p. 492). Rachfahl , who in geAeral takes 
his cue from Erasmus, with his Dutch liberal ideas, as the supporter of the 
Netherlands national spirit, makes him a true disciple of Erasmus (Oranien, 
I, 431). This, however, is not true. He is only a Humanist in his acceptance of 
the “Natural Law” and in his Stoic character, in which, indeed, he is also at 
one with the Reformers, Castellio and Franck. He certainly emphasizes this 
underlying element and its identity with the Logos much more strongly. In the 
main, however, he is an idealist and a mystic who makes the ladder of sanctifi- 
cation from detachment to freedom from sin the centre of his teaching, ascribing 
everything to the inward working of God ; see also Busken-Huet, II, 47-36. His 
ideas upon the Church I take from extracts which Herr Sippell has collected 
and allowed me to see, but the publication of which he has retained for himself. 

487a (P* 767.) For the Collegiants in detail see Hylkema: Reformateurs, and 
Sippell: Ueber den Ursprung des Quakertums, Chr. W., 1910, pp. 483-487. I likewise 
thank Herr Sippell for making known to me the “79 Articles ” and their 
“explanation”, which is often mentioned by Hylkema, the publication of which 
he has likewise retained for himself. For the connection of the Rynsburger with 
the Anabaptists, see Newman: Antipedobaptism, pp. 321 ff. ; for their “inward” 



PROTESTANTISM 973 

character quite in the manner of Coornheert, see Barclay: The Inner Life , p. go. 
For Coornheert and his followers, as representatives of the Inward Word and 
companions of Sebastian Franck and Schwenkfeld , see also Maronier , pp. 307— 303; 
for the beginnings of the Collegiants, see Barclay , pp. 83-32 , and for their later 
development from 1650 onwards, see Hylkema. A biography of Coornheert, or, 
at least, an account of his theology, would be very valuable, and would 
illuminate his connection with the past and with the future. The prevailing 
one-sidedly denominational conception of the history of the Reformation could 
thus once again at an important point be restricted. 

488 (p. 769.) For this cf. in general Hegler: Geist und Sc hr if t, and Keller : Staupitz . 
Keller caljs these idealistic Baptists the “better Baptists”; Maronier does the 
same {p. 327) ; others call them “free Baptists”, which is a contradictio in adjecto. 
For Bunder lin, see Hegler, p.51; Entf elder Hegler, 273; and Keller, 360. For Thamer , 
see Neander: Th. als Reprdsentant moderner Geistesrichtung , 1842 , and Hochhut: 
Zf hist. Theol. , 1861 . Like Sebastian Franck, Coornheert, and the Collegiants, 
Denk finally denies all spiritual ministry, even that with which he was entrusted 
by the Baptists ; without a supernatural call like that of the Apostles there is no 
ministry. This again is Schwenkfeld’s idea, or can it be that in this respect 
Schwenkfeld hjmself is going back to an earlier mystical theory? This is 
equivalent to the removal of all churches and sects in general, see Keller: 
Denk , 1882 , p. 226; in this book his writings are analysed. His so-called 
“ Widermf ” is only the reaction from the Baptists to mysticism. 

489 (p- 77 °-) P° r the whole subject, cf. Hegler and Gottfried Arnold. For the 
“spiritual religion” of Servetus , see Tollin: Servet und d. Bibel , £./«r wiss. Theol., 
1873. For Paracelsus see the fine essay by Eucken in the Beitrdgen zur Einfuhrung 
d. Geschichte der Philosophic. For Bohme see in this connection merely Ritschl: 
Geschichte des Pietismus , II, 301-303 , and R. Griitzmacher , 133-204. The religious 
philosophy and metaphysics of these thinkers do not concern us at this point ; 
on this question see the Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophic 3 , by J. E. Erdmann , 
which still to-day is an incomparable book (/, 462-302 ), also Gottfried Arnold. 
Here they appear solely in their “spiritual” and mystical effect, which makes 
their connection with the historic facts of salvation, upon which churches are 
based, superfluous, or makes them mere aids for producing the real, decisive, 
quite individual personal process. Ritschl has rightly seen that with the clear 
vision of lfete ; for Kepler see likewise Eucken , pp. 38-33 ; here the characteristic 
confession of Kepler to an orthodox opponent: “Tibi Deus in naturam venit; 
mihi natura ad divinitatem aspirat” {p. 43). His attitude towards the Scriptures 
in Deissmann: Kepler und die Bibel , 1834 ; there also the analogy with Sebastian 
Franck is emphasized (pp. 28 ff .). — For Amos Comenius , see the article by Schiele 
in his Lexikon and the publications of the Comenius gesellschaft , which quite 
logically has also taken the other “spiritual” Reformers under its wing, often, 
unfortunately, in the uncritical manner of their leader, Ludwig Keller , even 
though in so doing he was following a right instinct. For the connection 
between asceticism, Spiritualismus , and Pietism, with an empirical pedagogy 
and philosophy, see the very illuminating remarks by Max Weber: Archiv XXI , 
pp. 33 and 37. 

490 (P- 77 i •) On this point see Gottfried Arnold , to whom he is a favourite 
saint, but who was regarded by the orthodox with great hatred as an arch- 
hejretic and blasphemer — a sign of the inclination of several branches of 
Pietism towards him ; in addition, the exemplary research which works up the 
whole subject by Nippold: Zf Hist., 1863 and 1864. Here the discussion between 
Joris and Menno Simons (B. 33, pp. 1 41-149, and B. 34, pp. 533 - 557 ) > which 



974 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

illuminates in an excellent manner the difference between the sect and 
mysticism: the spirit versus the letter, liberty versus law. The three types 
(B. 34, p. 554) i where Blesdyk explains : “Some (the sects) have a false con- 
fidence in external virtues and they sacrifice everything for a literal faith . . 
others (the churches) have a false confidence in a self-chosen form of worship . . . 
or in the illusion which they call faith that Christ has died for them and has 
become their righteousness and their sanctification. . . . And this false con- 
fidence they support and maintain, some with many external works, the others 
with talking about and reading the Holy Scriptures, which they declare to the 
people according to learned commentaries (but they call it God’s Word), and 
with the use of the Lord’s Supper, which they regard as the seal of redemption 
and justification.” Over against that Joris, as a newly raised-up prophet, 
proclaims the Religion of the Spirit ( p . 354 ). The discussion with Coomheert , 
34, pp. 627-641 , especially p. 633: “Hereby the defender (of David) reproaches 
Coornheert, saying that he does not understand what David means (in so far 
as C. adheres to his belief in the incorporation of the Spirit in the Bible instead 
of in the new prophet), because he confuses it with the views of Franck and 
Schwenkfeld with which he himself (C.) agrees. For David does not teach 
like these that in the last days no one will teach the other either by word of 
mouth or in writing, but he calls the ‘letter’ or the external doctrine that which 
is taught by the wise of this world without the spirit. Over against this he 
describes that which is spoken by the true ambassador of Christ (that is, by 
David himself) through the Holy Ghost in the times of the Holy Ghost or of 
perfection, as Spirit and life.” This is borne out by the content. No class 
distinctions in this sect ( 34 , p. 373). New editions at the end of the sixteenth 
century (B. 34, pp. 566, 627, 667). Reproaches of the Jorist movement against 
Knutzen, 1674 (34, p. 672). Arnold’s vindication also testifies to the impression 
upon radical Pietism. — For the sect of the Nazarenes, see Kalbe , 273-283. 
One of my relations, who belonged to this group, had in his possession all the 
mystical literature which was usual, including Gottfried Arnold and the 
“Berleburger Bibel”. 

491 (p* 773 *) Cf. Gottfried Arnold and Nippold: Z. f. hist. Theol. , 1862. Here, 
however, the English development of the group is only treated in a very 
meagre way. For the latter see Belfort Bax , 338-380; he connects the Ranters 
and the Quakers with them ; see also Barclay: The Inner Life of tLe Religious 
Societies of the Commonwealth , 1876, pp. 23-33. No class movement ( Nippold , 370), 
recognition of the existing order of Society and external adjustment to existing 
conditions, including ecclesiastical (377 ) ; hostility of Coornheert (388 and 336) ; 
the ideal ethic in the sense of a libertine mysticism ( 516 ), the origin of 
principle of the Holy Community and the system of penitential discipline in 
the Baptist movement ( 539-342 ) ; the hierarchical secret organization for 
worship, but without apostolic succession or institutional form, merely the 
inner calling of the Spirit and the recognition of this calling by an act of 
consecration (549-563). It is a peculiar mixture of spiritual mysticism, visionary 
Enthusiasm, Catholic hierarchy, and the Baptist Congregational ideal, with, 
at the same time, a very strong emphasis upon the perfection and union with 
God of the Primitive State which is to be restored in the Third Dispensation. 
For this reason Berens connects Winstanley closely with the Familists (pp. 15-18). 
— For the Irvingites, see Kalbe , pp. 439-455 . — Further prophetic communities 
are the Ubbonites (Heppe, p. 68), others in the two treatises of Nippold. 

491 (P* 773 -) Cf. Heppe, pp. 240-374; Ritschl, I, 194-246. The dualism of the 
idea : “Mysticism and the idea that the converted can have no fellowship with 



PROTESTANTISM 975 

the unconverted” ( p . 316). The opposition of the pure mystic, Gichtel, is 
characteristic “who could not feel at home within an exclusive sect, because 
he himself had no desire to form a sect at all” (ibid., 317) .—Continuance of the 
influence of the Labadists upon the Church in the Netherlands (Heppe, 394- 
464) : “The Conventicles were the sphere in which usually Pietists, Labadists 
and Hattemists met in fellowship” (p. 399) ; in the German Reformed Church 
(Heppe, 482 and 489). Thereby the communistic and monastic experiments came 
to nothing, but the tendency remained to Separatism, to non-historical 
mysticism, to Enthusiasm, to Chiliasm, to Perfectionism, and now and again 
also to the uncontrolled sexual tendencies of a Perfectionism of that kind. 
For offshoots of this movement in the Philadelphian societies, which include 
the so-called “Buttlarsche Rotte” (Separatist movement, led by Eva v. 
Buttlar (1670-1717) ), s eeHochhut: Geschichte und Entwickelung der philadelphischen 
Sozietdten , £./. hist . Theol., 1863. — For resemblances to and connections with 
the Waldensians and the Baptists see Maronier , p. 136; on the journey from 
Geneva to Middelburg, Labadie actually took refuge among some Waldensians 
in the Palatinate. 

494 (P* 774 -) For the intercourse of Spinoza with Collegiants and Mennonites, 
see Kuno Fischer, 4 Geschichte d. n. Ph ., I, 163 , 137 ff.; for his relationship with 
mysticism, ibid., pp. 133-133, in his correspondence: “For salvation I do not 
hold it necessary to know Christ according to the flesh ; quite otherwise, on the 
other hand, do I think of that eternal Son of God, namely, of the eternal 
Wisdom of God which has revealed itself in all things at its highest in the 
human spirit and amongst all men at its highest in Jesus Christ; for without 
this Wisdom, which alone teaches how we can differentiate between truih and 
error, good and evil, no one can be saved.” That is the doctrine of the “Spiritual 
Reformers”. Windelband also points out connections of this kind in his Geschichte 
d. n. Ph., I, 213. Hegler , p. 288 , rightly puts the question whether perhaps, 
especially in Holland, Spinoza had come into touch with Sebastian Franck. 
Also Hylkema: Reformateurs, Haarlem , 1900 and 1902 , places Spinoza in this 
connection (II, 367, 473-477) • It is not until we realize this, so it seems to me, 
that we understand the religious and ethical side of Spinoza’s thought. Geulinex 
belongs undoubtedly also on the religious and ethical side to the same general 
group of ideas, as Heppe rightly emphasizes. 

«» (p. f ] 6 .) For this new wave of mystical life, see the deeply interesting 
book by Hylkema. It is a perfect mine of the characteristic peculiarities of this 
kind of “spiritual religion”, and it exhibits in an amazing manner parallels 
with the English movement. The name, however, is rather unfortunate, also 
the connection between the history of dogma and the earlier mysticism, and the 
relationship with the Baptists, is not brought out sufficiently clearly; the 
political and social doctrines, as well as the theological ideas of this Spiritual 
Reformer, are interpreted too much in the sense of modern rationalistic and 
politico-social phenomena. — No class restrictions (/, p. 80; II, 203-208); 
a common opposition to the Church and the Baptists (/, 138, 169, 185; II, 7) ; 
radical non-ecclesiasticism (I, 100 ff.), opposition also to the ascetic Pietism 
within the churches (II, 86 ff., 472) ; equation of the true ethical content of the 
“spirit” with conscience and reason (/, 161, 167, 176) ; ethics in relation to the 
State ( 7 , 147-178), the inward aspect, see also II, 1-111. The theoretical 
independence and remoteness of this religious idea, in relation to all morality 
in general, is brought out very well in II, 83-111 ; among the Collegiants the 
Calvinist and Puritan characteristics take the lead, in the other movements the 
chief features are communistic, sectarian, and democratic. Among the former 



976 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

it is very interesting to note how it agrees with the economic features of Ascetic 
Protestantism, as they have been described by Max Weber ; van Hoek cries aloud 
to his Collegiant brethren : “Vergenoegt u met een seedig gelat en gemoed, 
met deftighijd in handel en wandel !” (II, 14). Here also the systematic-rational 
element in Calvinistic asceticism, so strongly emphasized by Max Weber, finds 
its classic expression (II, 49). “Liever dan er 00k maar de minste ruimte aan 
te geven (i.e. to the flesh) wil hij het stelselmatig tyraniseeren. Juist omdat het 
vleesch op gemak gestelld is, zal hij sich zetten tot strengen arbeid, etc.” — 
Among the real Spiritual Reformers and pure mystics, on the other hand, 
this system gives way in order to make place for the liberty of the Spirit. 
There is a great difference between the mysticism which recognizes the 
Calvinistic ethic of the “calling” and uses it as a means of discipline, and 
Quietistic contemplative mysticism. Also fanatical world-reformers have little 
to do with the Protestant ethic of the “calling” ; here the prevailing spirit 
is that of the radical sect, with its visions of world-renewal. 

4#fl (p. 780.) For the whole subject see Hylkema , who throws a good deal of 
light upon the connection between Dutch and English spirituality ; in particular 
he shows the significance of the influence of the Collegiants on the Seekers and 
the Quakers ; further, and above all, Barclay , who presents qn extraordinary 
mass of material in a confused and most obscure manner ; his treatment of the 
subject, however, carries one completely into the atmosphere of the time, and 
reveals on all hands the differences between Independents, Baptists, and pure 
mystics, as well as the various developments of these groups, and the way in 
which they agreed and disagreed with each other. He rightly sees that the 
decisive factor in this situation is the problem of war and non-resistance, in 
addition to the need to discern the genuine mystics. — The most instructive 
work of Sippell is based upon the material in both these books, and develops 
the suggestions which they give ; see Ueber den Ur sprung des Quakertums, Chr. W., 
1910, and Dells Programm. Above all, he has thrown a good deal of light upon 
the mystical treatises and their connection with the Collegiants, and thus 
indirectly with Coornheert, and he has also followed up the question of the 
references to Luther’s earlier “spiritual” congregational ideal. I owe a good 
deal to verbal information from Herr Sippell , who has also most kindly placed 
at my disposal several rare treatises of that period which were in his possession. 
Thus I have learnt to know DelVs Sermons and Dell's Select Works , London, 1773, 
and the wonderful little mystical treatise by Saltmarsh , entitled Sparkles of Glory, 
London, 1847 , as well as Eaton's Honey-Combe. It is only through these treatises 
that one can understand the period. For Dell, see the interesting work by 
Sippell ; Sippell appears, however, to me at any rate, to undervalue the relation 
with Congregationalism, which itself contained mystical elements and to 
estimate too highly the connection with Luther. Dell’s doctrine, however, is 
in reality Congregationalism transformed into “spiritual” mysticism, which 
further accepts the purely technical support of the ecclesiastical system by the 
State, as was obvious under Cromwell ; in this connection we can also think 
of Schwenkfeld, as Sippell himself has remarked recently (Chr. W., 1911 , p. 966). 
We may also state as a fact that there took place among the essentially 
Calvinistic Puritan Independents a development from originally pure dogmatic 
Calvinism to the Enthusiastic Independents under the influence of Baptists 
and Spiritual Reformers ; above all, under the influence of the excitement and 
agitation of the period (Barclay, pp. 1 50-159). This, however, is not pure 
mysticism; cf. the passage which Barclay quotes from C. H. Spurgeon : “It 
happened that the Puritans were getting into the sere and yellow leafe; and 



PROTESTANTISM 977 

the Independents and Baptists and others sects who were at times thoroughly 
and even remarkably spiritual, were growing worldly, political and vain- 
glorious. They had the opportunity of grasping the carnal sword, and they 
embraced this opportunity; and from that very moment very many of them 
lost the spirituality for which they had been eminent. The danger was lest the 
Evangelical sects should quietly settle down into one State Church . . . and 
preach each one after his fashion. ... At that very moment God sent into the 
world George Fox. ... He stood up in the face of the Christian world, and 
said to it, ‘No, thou shalt not do this. Thou shalt not conform thyself to the 
world. Thou shalt not go into an unholy alliance with the State ; there shall 
be in the midst of thee a spiritual people who shall bear their protest that 
Christ’s kingdom is not of this world, and that religion standeth not in forms 
and ceremonies, but is a matter connected with the inner man, and is the 
work of God’s Spirit in the heart.” This shows the whole difference between 
“spiritual religion” and the spirit which has just been described above of the 
Baptists, Hussites, Huguenots, and Calvinists, who approved of war for the 
establishment of the establishment of the Kingdom of Christ. The same 
difference is seen in the observation of Barclay on p. 623: “The Christianity of 
Cromwell’s soldiers at the commencement of our civil wars cannot be doubted, 
but it is more than doubtful whether it improved in quality by the conflict. 
They had, however, seen enough of war to be apt disciples of Fox, and many 
of thenj became preachers of the Gospel of peace and goodwill to men.” — For 
the English followers of Boehme, see Barclay , p. 214 ; for the Seekers and their 
connection with the Collegiants, pp. 73 and 410-41 3 ; for the Ranters, pp. 414- 
428 ; Barclay thinks that they owe their origin to the “Libertins” of Calvin’s 
time, and to the mediaeval “Brethren of the Free Spirit”, whereas to me this 
seems a mere resemblance which can be explained by the fact that they have 
a common basis. — The spiritual course of many souls is reflected in this report 
about Salmon’s treatise ( p . 428, I): “First he became a Presbyterian; they 
appeared to him to hover gently and soar sweetly in a more sublime region 
than the Episcopal people. Then came Independency on the stage, a people 
far exceeding others in the strictness of their form. Then the doctrine of 
Believers’ Baptisme. He became a Baptist preacher, braved persecution, and 
built a tabernacle. Then came that voice from the throne of the Almighty: 
‘Arise an^ depart, for this is not your rest.* ” — See also the account in Firth: 
Cromwell's Army . Here “spiritual” religion penetrated through lay-preaching, 
and through the substitution of “spiritual” chaplains like Dell, Saltmarsh, 
Sedgwick, and Hugh Peters for the Presbyterian chaplains, who withdrew 
(p. 320). The gradual elimination from the Army (p. 340): “a sober Con- 
gregationalisme became the dominant form of religion.” Cromwell interprets 
the coming Kingdom of God in a spiritual sense, in contrast to the Fifth 
Monarchy men, and therefore he desires to allow existing outward institutions 
to continue ( p . 341). Monk complains that these “spiritual” men arc very little 
use in the Army ( pp . 344 ff .) ; “spiritually minded” officers cashiered (34^ ff-)- 
Here is a description of a Captain Jackson : “In the language of the time he 
was one of those who had passed through all forms, and was above all forms 
and above all ordinances, whose religion was not made up of laws and duties, 
but all exaltation and inward bliss. For such, he said, all external forms of 
duties and performances are turned into praises and thanksgivings. Now there 
is nothing but mirth in them, there is a continual singing of birds in them, 
chirping sweetly, in a sweet harmony of soul-ravishing delightful music.” He 
was under the thumb of a Presbyterian colonel, but he was very useful as a 
VOL. II. LL 



978 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

military man, for which cause Fairfax did not wish to sacrifice him. That even 
in this Cromwell would not let things go too far, and punished those who held 
Socinian or Antinomian theories, as “derogation to the honour of God” is 
shown in the case of a Captain Coveil (347 ff .). — In this whole connection 
Sippell ascribes a very restricted influence to the Familists ( p . 2) ; he thinks that 
the “enthusiasm” and mysticism come from the eschatological tendency of 
Puritanism ( pp . 5-/0). However, in Everard, Dell, and Saltmarsh the whole 
mystical, “spiritual”, literary tradition is undeniably in the background 
(Sippell, pp . 80-88). 

497 (p* 784*) On this subject see especially Barclay , who gives information on 
the most important particulars; obviously, however, he wishes to give the 
impression that Quakerism is a voluntary Church of a Pietist and Scriptural 
kind. See also Weingarteriy who traces its descent from the Anabaptists, and 
Sippell , who ascribes its origin to the mystics, and also the Journal of George Fox 
(German translation, 1910), with the beautiful introduction by Wernle, who 
emphasizes chiefly the fact that the Quakers take the Sermon on the Mount as 
an ideal which is meant to be actually realized in life. In my opinion the whole 
question of the character of Quakerism is only intelligible when we take the 
following points into account : (a) that primitive Quakerism, with its emphasis 
upon inwardness and its “enthusiasm” was entirely unorganized and lacking 
in support ; ( b ) that it only achieved organization when it began to follow the 
example of the community organization of the Baptists ; (c) that this oiganiza- 
tion, once it had been completed, led the Society inevitably into a closer com- 
promise with the world, until (d) the Society attained the Puritan morality of 
the “calling” and an almost ecclesiastical form of Church-order and tradition. 
Quakerism is a synthesis of mysticism and the Baptist movement (which was 
finally urged into close contact with the Puritan outlook), which from the 
beginning it had rejected so resolutely. — This is the main result of Barclay’s 
study in accordance with which he tones down its mystical and enthusiastic 
origin. The connection with the constitution of the Mennonites ( p . 247) : “Does 
not this clearly show the way in which the doctrine of the Light, associated 
with the doctrines and practices of the Mennonites, passed into England and 
found a powerful and active exponent in George Fox?” The abiding difference 
( p . 243) : “In Friesland he, a Quaker missionary, says, that they (the Baptists) 
hung exceedingly on their outward visible things, so that I am confident it was 
as easy for the Apostle taking the sect of the Pharisees off from circumcision, 
offerings, temple, and the traditions of the elders, as it is for us to bring these 
people away from their external celebration of the ordinances called Baptism 
and the Lord’s Supper.” The connection with the Mennonites and Collegiants 
especially (pp. 352-338). — Tension between both elements was, therefore, not 
lacking (pp. 431 ff.). The difficult problem of the establishment of the member- 
ship on the basis of the assumptions of mysticism (pp. 353-366) , likewise the 
appointment of the minister and the teaching elders as the recognition of a 
spiritual endowment by the community (p. 445). The solution of the problem 
of “infallibility”, that is, of the decisive authority which determines questions 
of membership and position, is the Spirit in whom one must trust (p. 446) : 
“None ought nor can be accounted to the Church of Christ but such as are 
in a measure sanctified or sanctifying by the grace of God and led by His 
Spirit ; nor get any made officers in the Church but by the grace of God apd 
inward revelation of this Spirit.” It was in the impossibility of solving this 
problem that Luther’s idea of small groups of pure Christians proved imprac- 
ticable. Among the Quakers, however, this interpretation of the leading of the 



PROTESTANTISM m 

Spirit was interpreted along two lines: (a) it led to the idea of birthright- 
membership, that is, to the supposition that the children of Quakers will 
become filled with the Spirit, and that, therefore, they must be educated as far 
as possible on very intensive religious lines; ( b ) so far as officials were con- 
cerned, the guidance of the Spirit came through the vote of the majority, who 
chose and controlled their own officers. This constitutes the process of seculariza- 
tion, which Barclay laments from time to time {pp. 527 and 362) .—The accept- 
ance of the Puritan ethic of the “calling”, supervision of the community by the 
laity, who interfere in every detail of business and family life (pp. 490-501) ; 
here we find the supervision of labour and wages conditions, strict avoidance 
of all kipds of luxury, exclusion of mendicancy, and the impossibility of finding 
a poor man in the community. The only standard for activity is usefulness ; 
in one group the members are forbidden to plant flowers ; that is a luxury, 
instead of flowers they are to plant potatoes and turnips. Here also the economic 
results are described in which he agrees with Weber: Archiv XXI> pp. 61-72 , and 
especially Bernstein , pp. 680-685.— For the Quaker State in Pennsylvania, see 
the extremely interesting book by Sharpless: A Quaker Experiment in Government , 
Philadelphia , 1902. — Barclay complains of the numerical decline within the 
Society, and attributes it to lack of propaganda and laxity in excluding unworthy 
members, and to marriage with non-Quakers. The reason for that decline, 
however, is inherent in the sociological principle of the Society, which can 
only expand widely in times of religious awakening. A gain in numbers from 
a natural increase in population is only experienced within the churches, who, 
through Infant Baptism, increase along with the population, and who are able 
to combine their standards with a religion for the masses. I met with similar 
complaints among Unitarians and Gongregationalists when I was in America. 
With such principles this is inevitable, and it can only be avoided by an 
approximation to Church principles, which, indeed, the birthright membership 
of the Quakers really is (see Barclay y p. 362). — For the policy of the Quakers in 
questions of poor relief, provision of employment, etc., and for the effect of the 
removal of poverty within a small circle, but aloofness from the working classes 
and the tendency of the Society to become bourgeois, see Barclay , pp. 157-521 , 
and Bernstein , 683. — On Bellers, see the highly interesting information given by 
Bernstein, pp. 694-718. It is the radical Christian Baptist element in Quakerism, 
which isjhere expressed, combined with a Puritan emphasis upon work. The 
book bears the characteristic motto: “Industry brings plenty. The sluggard 
shall be cloathed with rags. He that will not work shall not eat.” 

499 (p. 788.) For the Unio mystica, see the pertinent remarks in Hupfeld: Ethik 
Gerhards, pp. 204-232 ; for Arnd, see Lasch: Arnds Wahres Christentum , Monatsschrift 
J. Pastoraltheologie, 1909 ; a good deal in Gob el, who loves to trace mysticism so 
long as it remained within the Church ; for further books, consult the literature 
mentioned in connection with Pietism. Ritschl understood very well the 
difference between “indifferentism” and the “sect” and the peculiarity of their 
way of forming fellowship. With his usual charity he calls this kind of thing 
a “clique” (//, pp. 359-362; /, 475 , 483) ; he sees in the spiritual leaders of the 
Friends of God an imitation of the Catholic director, in mysticism the ultimate 
cause of the martial Jesuit order, or a luxury which is due to the fact that there 
are “enough people who think like that (like Tersteegen) some of them 
weavers whose imaginative powers and devoutness were no help to their 
mechanical work, partly rich people who did not need to work, partly women, 
especially unmarried women, who always have the time and the capacity for 
mystical contemplation” (/, 478) ! According to his idea, such people ought to 



980 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

be in a convent, and the whole doctrine simply comes from the cloister. In 
contrast with this, however, he can endure the ascetic sects : “For Separatism 
betrays a secret attachment to a confessional Church the more ardently it 
fights against the impurity of the same, at least to the extent that it assumes 
the necessity for a particular Church formation at all” (/, 483). This is a 
complete misunderstanding! — For the attitude to the State and to Society, 
see Gottfried Arnold and Dip pel, II, 313 and 327, also Gob el, II, 638-735, and 
III , 166-133. DippeVs treatment of the subject has some Quietistic features, but 
in reality its whole spirit is not monastic as Ritschl seems to think, nor is it 
due to Thomas Aquinas, but it is genuinely Lutheran. He recommends agri- 
culture and farming, considers work a kind of asceticism and a ipeans of 
self-support, as well as the love of one’s neighbour, treats private property as 
the result of the Fall, etc. He has, however, an aversion to official work under 
the State, a tendency which we see in Luther so far as individuals were con- 
cerned, but not with reference to official position, and he objects to a profes- 
sional ministry, which, of course, for Luther would have been quite impossible. 
Gottfried Arnold accepts the existing situation in the genuine Lutheran sense, 
just as Sebastian Franck accepted it in his day. In II, p. 365, he says, very truly : 
“The practice of-the early Anabaptists and of the English Baptists differed 
from that of the Separatists in Germany to the extent in which their piety 
was not bound up with any political claims or any tendency to social reform. 
Their complete detachment from the world, and their quite individual tendency 
towards self-denial, which often led to Quietism, made them feel that the thing 
to be most desired was the isolation of each individual.” This description, 
however, only fits the mystics ; among ascetic Pietists and Church reformers 
the reasons for such a passivity were different, and Ritschl has not gone into 
them further. Those reasons were the impossibility of any social reform from 
the point of view of German Lutheran Absolutism, and the acceptance of the 
ethic of the “calling” from the Calvinists, which from the very outset was 
bourgeois and conservative. — For Christian Thomasius , see Ritschl, II, 552, and 
R. Kayser : Christian Thomasius und der Pietismus, 1300. — If we speak of radical 
Pietism we must then distinguish between the ascetic sectarian wing and the 
mystical indifferentist wing; in Lutheranism the latter has been decidedly 
more important and influential than the former, whereas, on the other hand, 
within Calvinism the former has been most important down to the prs^ent day, 
and from this source receives ever fresh reserves of energy and fresh impulses 
for progressive movement. For mysticism in the Calvinistic Church, see above, 
pp. 774-763 ; also Heppe, p. 70; Ritschl, I, 122-130 ; Max Weber: Archiv XXI, 
p. 44 . In the study of Dutch and English mysticism outside the churches we 
have already shown its connection with the mystical elements in the Baptist 
movement and the early spirituality of the period of the Reformation. — For the 
reappearance of mediaeval mystical literature there are numerous instances in 
Ritschl, also Keller: Reformation, pp. 470 ff. Very interesting also is Hegler: 
Sebastian Francks lateinische Paraphrase der deutschen Theologie, 1301 , p. 16: “In 
the orthodox period the estimate of the Theologia Germanica was keener among 
the Calvinists than among the Lutherans.” — The different attitude of mystics 
and “spiritual” men towards practical ethics, that is, the lack of contact with 
Calvinistic rational asceticism and the ethic of the “calling” in favour of a more 
passive suffering and non-theoretical attitude towards the world, has oft«n 
been suggested by Ritschl and Max Weber (Archiv XXI, 41), but it has not been 
traced to its real reason, which lies in the fact that the fundamental doctrines 
and sociological quality of mysticism are different. Here, then, there is no 



PROTESTANTISM 


981 

systematic utilitarianism, and the main impression is one of spontaneity in 
response to moods, feelings, and passing impressions. But just because of that 
fact they again come nearer to Lutheranism, from which they only differ in 
ethics by a stronger theoretical rejection of the flesh. But here, indeed, Luther’s 
followers for their part were also very uncertain. 

600 (p. 790.) Cf. Plitt: Zinzendorfs Theologie , 1869 /.; Becker: Zinzendorf und 
sein Christentum im Verhdltnis zum kirchl. und religidsen Leben seiner Z e ^> 1900, 
Ritschl is also very acute in his analysis; he considers that the Count was 
originally attracted to the spirit of Philadelphianism and “indifferentism” in 
the sense in which Arnold uses it, and that he only approached sectarian ideas 
througlf the influence of the Moravians. This expression of opinion has been 
questioned by Becker ( Studd '. u. Kritt ., 1891 ), since he points out that Zinzendorf 
always remained a Lutheran. Ritschl , however, is right in the main because the 
Lutheranism in question was supra-ecclesiastical and interconfessional in 
character, that is, it is Lutheran Christ-mysticism and an ethic of feeling, and 
the difference between that and Lutheranism in the ecclesiastical sense was 
only not realized by the Count. In this matter he was amazingly naive and 
non-reflective. Mystical features in Ritschl , Illy 407, 384, above all in Becker, 
76-82, 249-262. His misgivings about the Moravians refer to their sectarian 
character, “their tendency to separatism, to form themselves into harmful 
sects if they had only something external to show for it” ; “that was an Italian 
Waldensian false spirit” (words of Zinzendorf in Muller, 100 ff.). He himself 
explains clearly why from his personal mysticism he came to see the need for 
membership in a community: “The Moravian constitution had to take place; 
otherwise we would have had to invent some other form. For at bottom it is 
a fanatical idea to say, What have we to do with sects? With human organiza- 
tions? We want to be a Church of Jesus Christ. But what kind of a Church then? 
The invisible Church? Then you would have to become hermits once again. 
The visible Church? Then know that there is no visible Church without a 
definite religious form” ( Muller , 99). These words are highly illuminating as 
showing the difference between the sect-type and mysticism and idealism. 
This fact also explains his opposition to the Church discipline which the 
Moravians wished to introduce, and to the development of their religious body 
into a state within the State; see Becker, 225-232. — For the aesthetic indi- 
vidualism, which was due to this outlook and very little to the voluntary 
character of the movement, see the interesting sketch by Sam. Eck: Ueber die 
Herkunft des Individualitatsgedankens bei Schleiermacher, Giessen, 1908. For the 
transformation of Spener’s conventicles into free religious “sociability”, as 
something which is due to the social nature of man and therefore also justified 
in religion, as well as on the other hand the development of conventicles into 
free associations, which are intended to fertilize the territorial churches by 
concentrating an inward and spiritual Christianity round their chosen leaders, 
see Becker, 163-178; 153: “The Zinzendorf Brotherhood has nothing to do with 
that which is usually described as Church development, but it is solely a 
religious movement within the popular churches which organizes itself into 
free groups and associations.” Zinzendorf himself seems to have held this point 
of view: “In the opinion of Zinzendorf the future belongs to the free religious 
association which is founded solely upon Christ crucified, and whose only aim 
is to exalt Him, and therefore desires to serve the popular churches from this 
point of view which is its sole standard.” 

602 (p* 79 2 *) I* k impossible to illustrate this question in detail. A certain 
amount can be found in Keller: Reformation, 483-488; the monthly review of the 



982 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Comenius Society studies this question unceasingly from Keller’s point of view ; 
see also Troeltsch: Das Historische in Kants Religionsphilosophie , 1904. Similarly 
Kronenberg: Geschichte des deutschen Ideal ismus, /, 1909 , makes the statement that 
German Idealism signifies the breaking through of Christian mysticism “into 
the universal human”. His treatment of Hamann and Jacobi is very fine. 
The fact that he practically identifies Christianity, mysticism, Protestantism, 
Romanticism, Platonism, and that he argues that the spiritual conflict is due 
to the original opposition of this tendency to Enlightenment, Rationalism, 
Scholasticism, Ecclesiasticism, is very little help in making clear what is right 
in his assertion of mystical and spiritual influences upon German Idealism. — 
The criticism of J. Plenge is very instructive because he entirely negiects the 
sociological point of view ; see his Realistische Glossen zu einer Gesch . d. deutschen 
Idealismus , Archiv fur Sozialwissenschaft , XXXII , 1-35: “Critical subjectivism 
experiences a brief period of critical brilliance, supported by the social optimism 
of a bourgeoisie which has attained its freedom. ... It seems to have been an 
anticipation (that is, in face of the task of a renewal of Society in connection 
with the religious idea) which was only possible through the specific develop- 
ment of the problem of Reason which had grown up within the sphere of 
Christian subjectivism” (p. 34). — For the very interesting and influential 
Lavater , see the excellent studies by von Schulthess-Rechberg and Heinrich Maier in 
J. C. Lavater , 1902 , as well as my Anzeige HZ, 93 . — On the whole subject see 
Sell: Die Religion unserer Klassiker f 1904. Even to-day the best treatment of the 
subject is that of Gelzer: Die deutsche poetische Literatur seit Klopstock und Lessing , 
1846. Sell , p. 775, expresses it excellently when he says that the common 
element in the classic writers consists in this : “It is the conviction of the com- 
plete relativity of all that is offered as revelation, with a complete recognition 
of that whence all revelations come and of that which it receives : of God and 
the soul.” Goethe is, upon the whole, not unchristian, but absolutely outside 
the churches. “This Pietism (of Lavater and others) could and must interest 
Goethe because it was a form of personal religion invented by oneself, not a 
religion based upon authority or mere custom or because of submission to any 
kind of authority” (p. 176 ). “According to that, Goethe (apart from the central 
period of his life, when his whole attention was directed to antiquity) was a 
man who was self-taught and followed the Bible in his own way, a believer who 
only obeyed the witness of his own conscience” (p. 189). Goethe’s exjfiession is 
instructive : “There is the standpoint of a kind of religion, that of pure Nature 
and Reason, which is of Divine origin. This will eternally remain the same, 
it will endure and be of value so long as Divinely endowed beings exist. It is, 
however, only for chosen souls, for it is much too exalted ever to become 
general” (p. 206) ; that is not meant in the rationalistic sense ; Goethe’s intention 
was something spiritual, with the inclusion of Nature in the revelation of the 
spirit of the All. The well-known word about Christ : “If I am asked whether 
it is in my nature to yield to Him in reverent worship I answer, Certainly. 

I prostrate myself before Him as the divine revelation of the highest principle 
of morality” is likewise quite in the meaning of mystical idealism, excepting 
that God at the same time similarly reveals Himself powerfully in other realities, 
as, for example, in the Son as the most favoured revelation of the generative 
principle ; “the worship of Christ is only a conditional recognition of something 
which he has experienced of Him” (p. 190). Very significant is the religions 
education in the pedagogical period of the years of travel, because it outlines a 
peculiar form of worship which corresponds to these ideas ; further, it is quite 
different from that of the churches and reveals the sense of need to give to the 



PROTESTANTISM 


983 

new conception of Christianity also a form of worship and a community for 
instruction and education ; it is the idea of an educational system and a form 
of worship which is to be freely entrusted to various groups.— To this connection 
belong Bjornson and Ibsen, who both started from the Pietism of their family. 
Ibsen's idea of the Third Era is the same as the Evangelium aetemum of Lessing, 
the three stages of the mystics, or the threefold Gospel, and it can be traced right 
back to Joachim of Fiori ; see also Weinel: Ibsen , Bjornson, Nietzsche , igo8 . — 
The whole subject deserves to be made a subject of independent research. 

504 (P» 795 -) On this point see the works of Dilthey and Haym. The anti- 
ecclesiastical element in Schleiermacher' s Reden can only be held to be an esoteric 
expression if we misunderstand the sermons preached at the same time; 
Ritschl has rightly felt this ; see Schl? s Reden und ihre Nachwirkungen auf die evangel . 
Kirche in Deutschland, 1874; see also Troeltsch: Schl. und die Kirche (Schl., der 
Philosoph des Glaubens, igio). — No one has seen better than Kierkegaard the 
aesthetic and immanential character of Romantic religion as well as its radical 
individualism ; Kierkegaard rejects the aestheticism and the theories of im- 
manence, whereas he lays great stress upon radical individualism. — The 
completion of this individualism by a Romantic tendency, which copies the 
Catholic Church, as for instance in Novalis, is shown by Paul de Lagarde in 
his German writings, which, in spite of many fads, belong to the most important 
studies that have ever been written about the modern religious situation; he 
thinks that the whole situation means the break-up of the previous churches 
and the preparation for a new religion through a Gospel renewed from before 
the time of Paul and an ethically deepened spirituality. — A. Bonus: Die Kirche 
(Aus die Gesellschaft, hsg. v. Buber, XXVI) is very characteristic in its complete 
loss of the idea of the Church, and it is distinctive for countless people who are 
thinking along those lines. — Influential groups like that of Johannes Muller at 
Schloss Mainburg reveal the character of an ethical mysticism : awakening of 
the Divine Seed in man through Christ to a free personal development from 
the Spirit which is one with Christ, but which goes far beyond the letter; 
the incarnation of man by obedience to natural laws of the personal life, 
revealed and made known by Christ, is nothing other than the spiritual 
doctrine of the awakening of the Divine Spark in contact with Christ — all, 
however, removed into the sphere of activity. This group is also typical in its 
oppositidh to the Church and the sociological character of its spirituality; 
see Muller's Bergpredigt (turned into contemporary German, 1906). — The con- 
ception of Christianity, which Eucken describes as the necessary development of 
the same, is “spiritual" ; see Konnen wir noch Christen sein, 1911, p. 190 : “We are 
then in line with the movement of world history if we demand a further 
changing of the visible into the invisible, and if we desire to see a still clearer 
distinction drawn between genuine reality and that which can be touched by 
the senses. Therefore, we are not departing from our contact with Christianity, 
the religion of the Spirit, if we regard the happenings of the spiritual life as 
the only thing that matters and which ought to be treated accordingly." 
P. 200: “Religious fellowship must take its stand upon the truths . . . which 
belong immediately to the life process, which do not come first of all out of 
metaphysical speculation or out of historical tradition, truths, that is, which 
represent and are related to the facts of the appearance of a new world in 
nflan and the further formation of this world through struggle and conflict, 
the facts of a fundamental fighting and victorious spirituality."-— A very 
original form of mysticism which is indifferent to Christianity has been 
developed by Maeterlinck, whose influence upon the present day can likewise 



984 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

be interpreted from this homogeneity ; see The Treasure of the Humble . Mysticism 
develops in a deliberately anti-Christian sense under pessimistic influences in 
Schopenhauer and Ed, v. Hartmann , and is still more hostile in character in their 
disciples Arthur Drews and von Schnehen. Here, by the extinction of the whole 
theistic and personalistic element, all desire to form a community and every 
form of worship falls away completely, and the central point of the Christian 
cultus, Jesus Christ, is set aside altogether ; all the same these religious philoso- 
phers believe that they are able to revive a declining religion by this kind of 
religion of the immanence of the individual spirit within the All, apart from 
all fellowship, practice of worship, and basis in history. — Highly characteristic 
also is Simmel: Das Problem der religidsen Lage (in the collection Weltanschauung , 
Philosophic und Religion , 1911)9 who conceives religion as something entirely 
neutral without any definite content or stimulus, and therefore he excludes all 
connection with worship or with history. — Modern mystical lyrics, like those 
of R. M. Rilke , also belong to this tendency, and similarly the religious tendency 
of the Diederich Verlag and the whole modern claim to be not irreligious but 
apart from the churches, as well as many other things of the same kind. 

50to (P- 797*) It 1S not uninteresting to classify contemporary Protestant 
theology from this point of view. Present-day orthodoxy has a st^pngly Pietistic 
element mingled with a strong emphasis upon the inward life ; but since in the 
inward experience of the spirit it always considers, above all, that the Bible, 
the Sacrament, and the Church constitute the supernatural agent ’of the 
immediate experience, it retains a sufficient amount of objectivity, authority, 
an external standard and miracle in order to be able to think and work as a 
Church ; from this point of view the Virgin Birth and the Resurrection are 
interpreted from the standpoint of inward experience; it is ecclesiastically 
“potent”. — Schleiermacher and his disciples are essentially “spiritual” in their 
outlook; but he reacted from this “spirituality” to a modernized form of 
Christ-mysticism, and in so doing he retains a Christian form of worship and 
a canon of doctrine which are to some extent conceivable, the recognition of 
redemption through the supernatural impression of the personality of Christ 
as united to God ; in accordance with this he would maintain the Church and 
a community for worship, while he would give up the very individual arrange- 
ments of the Christian life-substance which is clothed in the form of the popular 
Church ; from this point of view a stable ecclesiasticism in the old &nse will 
never be attained. — The followers of Hegel went in the same direction, in so far 
as they wished to remove religion from pure intellectualism and a mere party 
and scholastic connection; or they made the “principle” of the Spirit entirely 
independent, in contrast with the “Person” of Christ, and in so doing they 
only retained for the Church the spiritual fellowship which was entirely 
anonymous. — Ritschl and his genuine followers reduced the body of doctrine 
in a peculiar way, but they demanded for it a strictly authoritative ecclesiastical 
value, and for that very reason they laid great emphasis upon the Church, 
and drove mystical spirituality out of every hole and corner; Ritschl was 
triumphant when he could prove to his orthodox opponents their Pietistic 
modifications of the conception of the Church, showing them that he was more 
ecclesiastical than they. His doctrine, therefore, is completely planned to fit 
the possibility of a popular and Territorial Church. — Herrmann maintains a 
Christ-mysticism similar to that of Zinzendorf and Schleiermacher, whidi 
asserts a kernel of certainty given from without, which guarantees confidence, 
and is thus a redeeming revelation, but otherwise everything is left to personal 
conscientious conviction; therefore, from the side of the Church he believes 



PROTESTANTISM 


985 

in Luther’s confidence in the supernatural proclamation of Christ which itself 
effects conversion, which needs no other artificial aids, and is able to carry 
itself out by its own power ; the consequences of this position for Church-order 
have been deduced by Rudolph Sohm and Erich Forster ; this would lead in 
practice to Congregationalism, within which all that matters is faith and 
trust in God; in this case there would be nothing to fear from any anti- 
ecclesiastical influence. The so-called Religious Historical School goes back 
entirely to “spiritual” religion, and is, therefore, ecclesiastically “impotent”. 
My own theology is certainly “spiritual”, but for that very reason it seeks to 
make room for the historical element, and for the ritual and sociological factor 
which is £>ound up with it. Naturally I am aware of the difficulties of such an 
undertaking. — Harnack (see especially his remarks about the World Congress for 
Free Christianity , Aus Wissenschaft und Lehen , 1911, /, 146-152) considers that a 
theoretical solution of the problem is altogether impracticable, and he only 
wishes to see an intelligent tolerant form of Church government, which would 
leave the pastors freedom of movement ; this really means the destruction of 
the Church as a system, and it would be preserved solely by the exclusion of 
very “advanced” pastors; the limits within which their “advanced” views 
might be toler^cd could only be determined by the verdict of some committee, 
acting according to the best of its knowledge, taking the general personality 
into account ; this, then, might form a bridge to happier forms of organization 
later on: a conception which thoroughly corresponds with the mingling of 
spirituality and historicity in his theology (sec ibid., Christus als Erloser, pp. 81 - 
94). From that point of view also we must interpret a work like that of General- 
superintendent Kaftan: Wo stehen wir? Einekirchliche ^eitbetrachtwig, 191 r .H^ exalts 
the ecclesiastical “potency” of the orthodox, and casts up at the Liberals their 
ecclesiastical “impotence” which he says is due to the features which lay most 
stress upon “spirituality”. In order to save the Church he would banish the 
“subjective” members from it. The characterization is not false. Still we must 
draw attention to the fact that qualities are essentially bound up with “ecclesi- 
astical potency”, which ethically are very hard to bear, and that the qualities 
which go with “spiritual impotence” are qualities which correspond to 
gentleness, goodness, and inwardness of Christianity. This presents, in fact, the 
sociological antimony between the claims of organization and those of the 
development of a free personality. Mutatis mutandis the political parties are in 
a similar position, with the exception that they do not theoretically serve the 
formation of the personality. If, however, the matter really were so, another 
way than that of Kaftan would be desirable, for if his way were followed the 
Church would be saved at a very great cost, and it would alienate spiritually 
minded men everywhere. — There are some fine remarks upon the whole 
subject in SeWs article Die zweifache Theologie , Ch. W. , 1911 ; see also my memorial 
speech, Richard Rothe , 1899. Rothe only preserved himself from the ultimate 
consequences of pure “spirituality” through his Christology, but even in this 
he comes very close to theosophy ; here he reminds us of Schwenkfeld, Para- 
celsus, Bohme, Octinger, and Arnd. — For the whole see also the book which 
has already been mentioned by Bruhn. 

505 (p* 798*) Pertinent remarks upon this tendency in Novalis and in the 
French Romanticism in Windelband: Die Philosophie im deutschen Geislesleben des 
199 Jahrhunderts , 1909 , pp. 32-36; for St. Simon see Lorenz Stein: Sozialismus und 
Kommunismus. Herder, in his time at Buckeburg, had tendencies of that kind. 
To what a limited extent, however, such tendencies arise out of the real spirit 
of Romanticism is proved by present-day Neo-Romanticism, which renews 



986 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

the old aesthetic, differentiating spirit, and which has again entirely cast off 
the positive historical tendency, possibly only in order to experience a similar 
transformation. 

508 (p. 802.) For further details, see Ritschl and Gabel. The Geschichte der 
Ethik , by Luthardt , II, 248-340, and Gass, II, 1 , pp. 283-325, and 359-368, shed 
practically no light upon this subject. Dippel has written a work on social 
ethics entitled: Christenstadt auf Erden ohne gewohnlichen Lehr -, Wehr-, und 
Nahr stand oder kwrze dock eigentliche Abbildung der aits dem Reiche der Natur entstan - 
denen und im Z°m Gottes bestdtigten Ordnungen unter den Menschenkindern . Extracts in 
Walch: Religionsstreitigkeiten, pp. 723/. and 753 /. The existing social order of 
Natural Law belongs only to the economy of the Law or of the Father. — 
Saltmarsh, in his Sparkles of Glory, expresses similar ideas. A completely new 
order of humanity is to arise which will be entirely free from legalism moving 
only in the spirit of love and idealism, but in itself becoming a real organism 
through love. Until that time comes Christians are to live apart from the 
world in quietness and humility. — Sebastian Franck tolerates the existing 
situation in the sense of the Lutheran Natural Law with a great deal of emphasis 
on resignation and a pessimistic view of humanity ( Hegler , pp. 260-263 , 243, 
116, 179-184) ; Schmoller and Wiskemann are also in sympatljy with Fraqck 
to a certain extent. — Gottfried Arnold also is conservative in his attitude 
towards the present day, but idealistic and revolutionary with regard to the 
future, so far as this problem is concerned ( Ritschl , II, 311 , 315 ). Winstanley 
and Lilburn, on the other hand, expect the renewal of Society in the demo- 
cratic and communistic sense through the Spirit, and they work consciously 
though without violence towards this goal. — The sex ethic and the permission 
of woman to preach should be noted, for this in itself constitutes the removal 
of ecclesiastical and especially of Lutheran patriarchalism. Otherwise, the 
finer conception of sex ethics does not appear until we come to the modern 
spiritual idealists, who combine the religious idea of personality with an 
aesthetic-immanent conception of Nature. On this point Schleiermacher's Letters 
on Schlegel's Lucinde are characteristic ; see Rade: Stellung des Christentums zum 
Geschlechtsleben, pp. 61-89, in which, however, the whole question is connected 
too closely with Luther instead of with the tendency in mysticism and spiritual 
idealism to emphasize the subjective side of personality. Schleiermacher’s ideas 
are entirely non-Lutheran. — The fine works on sex ethics by Lhotzky&Das Buch 
der Ehe, 1911 , and Johannes Muller: Beruf und Stellung der Frau , 191 J, also belong 
to this school of thought. It represents entirely non-ecclesiastical sex ethics. 
Johannes Muller is particularly characteristic of the modern spiritual, idealist 
ethic ; his attitude is not quietistic but energetic and resolute, aiming at the new 
creation of humanity through the awakening of the “original being” or Divine 
Spark, latent in every soul, which is wakened by the impression of Jesus and 
which creates a spirit leading to free personal development. It is a spiritualized 
Chiliasm. This teaching naturally exerts its highest influence on purely personal 
relationships and therefore affects sex relationships. Muller's Bergpredigt, 
translated into ordinary German in 1906, contains, however, some very 
vague and impossible idealistic ideas of reform in the State, economics, and 
Society, which do not even remotely do justice to the complicated condition 
of the actual life of Society. 

810 (p. 809.) At this point my presentation of the subject converges wkh 
the well-known researches of Max Weber on Der Geist des Kapitalismus , etc. 

( The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism , translated by Talcott Parsons, 
George Allen & Unwin, 1930, 10s. 6d. net). Weber's researches start from 



PROTESTANTISM 


987 

the endeavour to discover the constitution of modern capitalism, with its 
emphasis upon trade and its bourgeois character as distinguished from the 
capitalism of the ancient world and of the later period of the Middle Ages. 
On the basis of practical observation in Westphalia and the Lower Rhine, in 
Scotland, England, and America, he represents one of the constituent factors 
as Ascetic Protestantism, whose nature Weber analyses with a view to under- 
standing its significance in economic history, or better still in the history of 
civilization. My study has a different aim. It only intends to give a clear 
presentation of the Protestant social ethic for its own sake. I therefore set aside 
Weber’s further references. On this point I was able to follow his presentation 
of Ascetic Protestantism precisely because every time I studied this subject 
afresh I felt that his argument had proved itself to be a brilliantly acute piece 
of observation and analysis. — For the rest, however — as I would like to take 
this opportunity to remark — my researches do not start from those of Weber. 
Externally they were caused by the task with which I was entrusted, of 
reviewing (for the Archiv) the book by Nathusius: Die Mitarbeit der Kirche an der 
Losung der sozialen Frage ( The Co-operation of the Church in the Solution of the Social 
Question). When I was engaged in this task I found that there were no books in 
existence whicfy could serve as a basis for the study of such a question, and I 
then began to try to lay the foundation for such a study myself. This book was 
the result of my endeavour. When I began this work, however, I found that all 
the interests of my research contributed to it: the sociological phenomena 
connected with the conception and nature of the Church, which were based on 
the familiar doctrine of Rothe (see Religion und Kirche , Preuss. Jahrbb ., i8gf) y 
interests which concern the history of the Christian ethic (see Grundprobleme der 
christlichen Ethik , Z- f Th. u . K., 1902), and, above all, my researches into the 
meaning of the Lex Naturae (they run through a whole number of treatises 
from my Melancthon und Gerhard onwards). Finally the book embodied the 
programme which in 1901 I outlined in my review of Seeberg's Lehrbuch der 
Dogmengeschichte , Gott. Gel. Anzz 1902, pp. 21-30. Weber’s work, however, did 
not appear until 1903. Without Weber certainly, I should have been unable to 
gain a clearer conception of Ascetic Protestantism than that which had already 
been prepared by Schneckenburger and Ritschl. Indeed, we only need to study 
the works of both these eminent, acute, and extremely learned men in order to 
arrive at Chis conception. Weber’s own important discovery is the setting of this 
conception within the whole framework of universal, economic history and 
history of civilization ; at the same time also we must not overlook the psycho- 
logical penetration of his dogmatic-ethical analyses. They are based upon 
penetrating studies of Baxter, Spener, Bailey, Sedgwick, Hoornbeck, and the 
works of the Puritan divines, London, 1845-1848. 

411 (p. 810.) Cf. Weber: Archiv XXI , p. 79 f “A sober procreation of children” 
is the aim, according to Baxter ; Spener has similar ideas, with concessions to 
the coarse Lutheran view. . . . According to an idea prevalent in many 
Pietistic circles, the highest form of Christian marriage is that which preserves 
virginity ; the next best is that in which sexual intercourse serves the purpose 
exclusively of the procreation of children, and so on, down to those which are 
entered upon for purely erotic reasons, or for external convenience, which 
from the ethical point of view may be regarded as concubinage. In all this, 
thft marriages which are contracted at a lower level, and those which are 
contracted for external reasons, are preferred to those which are based on 
eroticism (because the former are based on rational considerations). The theory 
and practice of the Moravians may here be left out of account.” Thus Whitfield 



988 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

expresses himself in an offer of marriage : “I bless God, if I know anything of 
my own heart, I am free from that foolish passion which the world calls love. . . . 
I trust I love you only for God, and desire to be joined to you only by His 
commands and for His sake’* ( Lecky , II, p. 5 8g ). Further, Weber, p. ?gf . : “As in 
that rational interpretation of sex relationships among nations which have been 
influenced by Puritanism, there grew up, finally, that refinement of spirit and 
ethical penetration of marriage relationships and the delicate blossoms of 
married chivalry — in contrast to that boorish patriarchal spirit which among 
us is often present, even in the circles of the Geistesaristokratie — this does not need 
to be developed further here ; the protection of the freedom of conscience of 
woman and the extension of the idea of the priesthood of all believers 4 to include 
her were also, by including this question, the first breaches in the patriarchal 
ideas. In the Th. JB., ign , W. Kohler calls attention to a paper by Ellen A . 
MacArthur in the Ecclesiastical History Review, 24, pp. 6g8-yog, on the subject 
“Women’s Petition to the Long Parliament” ; on this he remarks : “Why did 
women come to the fore just then when the Puritan rule and Quakerism were 
about to emerge? From what circles do they come? What are their motives? 
The Calvinistic influence is quite clear.” Parliament certainly answers : “Good 
women, we entreat you to repaire to your houses and turncj your petitions 
into prayers at home for us.” For the reasons of the position of woman in 
America see Bryce, II, 742: “The cause is the usage of the Gongregationalist, 
Presbyterian, and Baptist Churches, by which a woman who is a member of 
the congregation has the same rights in choosing a deacon, elder, or pastor as 
a man has.” — For the often emphasized tendency of Ascetic Protestantism 
towards an extended system of popular education without philosophy and 
academic theology, but combined with Scriptural instruction and realistic 
technical education, see also Dell's Education Programme in Sippell, 63-71, whose 
similarity with that of the Quakers and Pietists Sippell also emphasizes. He 
desires a strict discipline of youth, general elementary education, as many 
high schools as possible, but no scholastic, theological, philosophical, and 
privileged universities : “Especially the mathematical sciences must be highly 
honoured at the universities such as arithmetic, geometry, geography, and the 
like which do not have evil results, and are also very useful for human society 
and the various needs of this present life.” 

511a (p. 812.) The illustrations of this point are scattered througWfche whole 
of this book ; of special importance also is the study by Tocqueville and Kuyper . 
There is also a certain amount of material in Bryce, II, 617-834 ; characteristically 
he is fond of comparing American piety with that of Scotland and the English 
Nonconformists. On the State in //,/). 701 he says : “The State is not to them as 
to Germans or Frenchmen and even to some English thinkers an ideal moral 
power, charged with the duty of forming the characters and guiding the lives 
of its subjects. It is more like a commercial company, or perhaps a huge 
municipality, created for the management of certain business in which all who 
reside within its bounds are interested. That an organization of this kind 
should trouble itself, otherwise than as a matter of police, with the opinions or 
conduct of its members, would be as unnatural as for a railway company to 
enquire how many of the shareholders were total abstainers.” — Cf. also Veit: 
Englische und deutsche Frommigkeit, Ch. W., igo6. 

612 (p. 815.) I am here giving again an outline of Weber's ideas on *the 
capitalist relations of Calvin and the sects, although I have already indicated 
it above. Here alone have we reached the point at which it can be fully intro- 
duced, because in this respect the matter of importance is not so much Calvinism 



PROTESTANTISM 


989 

as Puritan, Pictistic, ascetic Calvinism, and its agreement with the sects. 
Rachfahl has not noticed this, although Weber has emphasized it clearly enough, 
and his study includes a large number of sects. — One example of the question, 
purely from the latter point of view, is the description of Quakerism in Wein- 
garten , 397-405, The characteristic expression of Rentmeister Gottes (The Lord’s 
Stewards) is used in Heppe , 188 , and also in LodensteyrCs Meditation on “ Die 
Darbringung der zeitlichen Giiter eines Christen an ihren Eigentiimer y \ In the form of 
a conversation with God, in this Meditation he makes the Christian hand over 
quite formally all his possessions to God, whose steward he desires to be. — 
For further study of this subject, see Weber and also the anticipatory statements 
above (pp> 709-723 ). I believe, however, that through my presentation of the 
sects, and especially in the clear distinction between mysticism and the sect- 
type, I have in some particulars made Weber f s idea clearer, and also that 
through the manifestation of the sectarian elements in primitive Calvinism 
I have made the fusion of Calvinism with the sect-type more intelligible. — 
In my opinion Sombart's brilliant book, Die Juden und das Wirtschaftsleben , does 
not weaken the force of Weber’s argument at all. Above all, it justifies the whole 
formulation of the problem as the search for the origin of the “capitalist 
spirjt”, which supports the “capitalist system”, which is the absolutely necessary 
presupposition for its modern mass-form, and is anything but easy to under- 
stand. Further, it shows one of the component parts of the modern capitalistic 
spirit, which is always recognized and emphasized by Weber, but which in that 
connection was not to be further analysed. Above all, however, through 
Sombart's researches that tendency of the capitalistic spirit, with which Weber 
was most concerned, is not touched upon — a tendency which is still more 
important for the understanding of modern civilization, the tendency, that is, 
which is directed towards bourgeois mass capitalism, with its modern idea of 
professions and specialists. The bourgeois spirit of modern civilization had to 
be explained in relation to the treatment of Capitalism, which had always been 
working from the time of antiquity, and was not specifically bourgeois and in 
relation to the technical, political, and colonial stimuli. Further, see above, 
p. 720. For the rest, I repeat, that in all this I have no intention of making a 
contribution to the history of Capitalism ; this I must leave to the experts in 
this very difficult sphere. All that I have to do here is to interpret the social 
teaching of Protestantism, alongside of which everything which belongs other- 
wise to the history of Capitalism can here remain untouched. 

615 (p. 818.) On this point cf. the various statements in Max Weber , whose 
interests are concerned precisely with this problem. He has formulated thus 
the programme of research (p. 109) : “The task is . . ., to show the significance 
of ascetic rationalism (that is, of Ascetic Protestantism with its utilitarian 
character which systematizes labour), for the content of the social-economic 
ethic, that is, for the kind of organization showing the development and function 
of social groups through their varying forms from the conventicle up to the 
State. Also, its connection with Humanistic Rationalism and its life-ideals and 
cultural influences, with the further development of philosophical scientific 
empiricism, with the technical development and the spiritual values of civiliza- 
tion, must be analysed. Then, finally, its historical growth must be followed 
through the different stages — from the early mediaeval beginnings of an 
asceticism within the world to its disintegration in pure utilitarianism, and 
through the particular spheres in which ascetic religiosity has been widespread. 
Only when this has been done will the significance for civilization of Ascetic 
Protestantism, in relation to other plastic elements of modern civilization, 



990 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

emerge.” The programme is very difficult to carry out as long as the history of 
Humanism, of humanistic culture, and of the classes which it affected, as well 
as the history of modern philosophy in its social aspects, has not been made 
perfectly clear. Both in the works of specialists, as well as in those of Church 
historians until the present time, this subject has never been fully cleared up. 
The history of technical developments, which in no way coincides with that 
of the natural sciences, would also need to be clearly presented. Weber’s 
programme is thus, in my opinion, not yet possible to realize, but the idea is 
very stimulating, like other suggestions of Plenge : a.a.O . Such a programme of 
the history of civilization is particularly instructive as contrasted with Lam- 
precht, who, with quite other methods, is aiming at a similar scientific goal of 
knowledge. Lamprecht’s methods are based upon “psychological” laws, which 
enable him from the outset to prescribe the order of facts in definite series, 
whereas my own method is essentially directed towards the analysis of the 
concrete particular situation with reference to its content and its special 
causal relations, which are only'conncctcd with this concrete situation. To this 
extent also in this work I would like to show the contrast between my method 
and that of Lamprecht, who tries to reach an extremely valuable goal of 
knowledge by impossible methods. — I am in entire agreement with J:he 
methodical reflections about the connection between the history of Christianity, 
and the history of civilization which Harnack has developed in his lecture 
Ueber das Verhdltnis der Kirchengeschichte zur Universalgeschichte , A us Wissenschaft 
und Lebeti , //, 41-62. Only I believe that in this work I have shown that the 
religious development reveals a firmer and more independent attitude, 
especially in relation to political constitutional developments, than Harnack 
thinks. 



CONCLUSION 


Developments in Christian Social Doctrine 
since the Eighteenth Century 

Our inquiry is over. It was only possible to treat it exhaustively 
as far as the eighteenth century. The developments which have 
taken place from that period down to the present day could 
merely be suggested. With the nineteenth century Church History 
entered upon a new phase of existence. As a result of the dis- 
solution of the unity of civilization controlled by a State Church, 
combined with the development of the independence of modern 
thought, it has since then no longer possessed a fixed and ob- 
jective ideal of unity. The result has been that the social philo- 
sophy of the Christian community has also suffered an undeniable 
disintegration, through its dependence upon continually changing 
conditions. 'Jhese groups are living in a new world, the world 
of modern bourgeois capitalist society and of bureaucratic 
militaristic states. The relation between Church and State has 
been weakened, and in some cases entirely severed. Social theory 
has developed out of a naive preoccupation with antiquity, the 
Bible, and theology into an independent science, which examines 
entirely afresh the relation between the land and the population, 
the connection between the economic substructure and the 
spiritual superstructure, and the sociological laws and conditions 
which govern the growth of fellowship ; this social theory has far 
outdistanced the social philosophy of the Church. 

Above all, the modern bourgeoisie, the Law of Nature, the 
emancipation of the fourth estate, and, finally, scientific rational- 
ism have created a new sociological fundamental theory of 
rationalistic individualism, which is connected, it is true, with 
the older ideas of Christian individualism, but which in its 
optimistic and equalitarian spirit is sharply opposed to it. The 
repercussions caused by this atomistic and essentially indivi- 
dualistic democratic spirit (which is plain even within Com- 
munism and Socialism) were only partly determined by the 
social philosophy of the Church ; they are due also to the biolo- 
gical spirit of natural science or to the organic spirit of Platonism ; 
both are in sharp opposition to the leading ideas of Christian 
social philosophy. Further, the actual practical restrictions of 
modem individualism, the neutralization of the competitive 
stouggle, which had been unleashed for two hundred years by 
bourgeois individualism, and allowed to spread throughout the 
world, is likely to become an effect of purely economic and 



992 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

political conditions of power, in which the division of the product 
spheres and the influence of the producers bring assured 
quotas ; and, when these spheres are fixed, both the mobility of 
the population and the production of offspring will be com- 
pressed within fixed limits. Radical individualism will probably 
soon be an interlude between an old and a new civilization of 
constraint. This individualism may be compared with the process 
of taking the materials of a house which has been pulled down, 
sorting them out into the actual individual stones, out of which 
a new house will be built. What the new house will look like, 
and what possibilities it will provide for the development of 
Christian ethics and of Christian social philosophy, no one can 
at present tell. Christian social philosophy will bring to the task 
both its common sense and its metaphysical individualism; but 
it will have to share the labour with other builders, and like 
them it will be restricted by the peculiarities of the ground apd 
of the material. 

Under these circumstances it is impossible to give a description 
of the present situation, and to deduce from it principles for the 
future. Even if the undertaking were restricted to a mere descrip- 
tion of the different Christian endeavours, schemes, and associa- 
tions of the present day, the whole situation is so complicated 
that the subject would have to be treated in a separate work. 
In order to conclude this survey, therefore, it is not necessary to 
deal further with the present situation ; all that is required is to 
collect and formulate the results of this inquiry in some brief 
general statements. 

Our inquiry began with the social and ethical tasks and 
possibilities of Christianity at the present day. It then reverted 
to the point at which the form in which the social development 
of the religious idea was expressed, severed its connection with 
the secular social formations. It discovered that these connections 
take very different forms, according to the special conception of 
the Christian idea, and of the organization which corresponds 
to this conception. Our inquiry then traced the course of de- 
velopment of the different church and group formations, and of 
the social ethic which corresponded in each case to this develop- 
ment. It was finally confronted with the fact that all these social 
developments were determined by the general conditions of 
civilization, and in every instance the question had to be asked : 
At any given time, what was the relationship between the two 
forms of influence, and how did they mutually react upon one 
another? Thus we find that the results of this inquiry are 



CONCLUSION 


993 

connected with the whole conception of the nature and history 
of Christianity in general. In the following paragraphs these 
results are briefly summarized. 


RESULTS OF THIS SURVEY 

Three Types of Christian Thought 

(i) It has become clear how little the Gospel and the Primitive 
Church" shaped the religious community itself from a uniform 
point of view. The Gospel of Jesus was a free personal piety, 
with a strong impulse towards profound intimacy and spiritual 
fellowship and communion, but without any tendency towards 
the organization of a cult, or towards the creation of a religious 
community. Only when faith in Jesus, the Risen and Exalted 
Lord, became the central point of worship in a new religious 
community did the necessity for organization arise. From the 
very beginning there appeared the three main types of the socio- 
logical development of Christian thought : the Church, the sect, 
and mysticism. 

The Church is an institution which has been endowed with 
grace and salvation as the result of the work of Redemption; 
it is able to receive the masses, and to adjust itself to the world, 
because, to a certain extent, it can afford to ignore the need for 
subjective holiness for the sake of the objective treasures of grace 
and of redemption. 

The sect is a voluntary society, composed of strict and definite 
Christian believers bound to each other by the fact that all have 
experienced “the new birth”. These “believers” live apart from 
the world, are limited to small groups, emphasize the law instead 
of grace, and in varying degrees within their own circle set up 
the Christian order, based on love ; all this is done in preparation 
for and expectation of the coming Kingdom of God. 

Mysticism means that the world of ideas which had hardened 
into formal worship and doctrine is transformed into a purely 
personal and inward experience; this leads to the formation of 
groups on a purely personal basis, with no permanent form, 
which alsp tend to weaken the significance of forms of worship, 
doctrine, and the historical element. 

From the beginning these three forms were foreshadowed, and 
ali down the centuries to the present day, wherever religion is 
dominant, they still appear alongside of one another, while 
among themselves they are strangely and variously interwoven 

VOL. II. MM 



904 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

and interconnected. The churches alone have the power to stir 
the masses in any real and lasting way. When mass movements 
take place the sects draw closer to the churches. Mysticism has 
an affinity with the autonomy of science, and it forms a refuge 
for the religious life of the cultured classes; in sections of the 
population which are untouched by science it leads to extrava- 
gant and emotional forms of piety, but in spite of that it forms 
a welcome complement to the Church and the Sects. 

Christian Thought dependent 
on Sociological Factors 

(2) The results of this survey throw light upon the dependence 
of the whole Christian world of thought and dogma on the 
fundamental sociological conditions, on the idea of fellowship 
which was dominant at any given time. The only peculiarly 
primitive Christian dogma, the dogma of the Divinity of Christ, 
first arose out of the worship of Christ, and this again developed 
out of the fact that the new spiritual community felt the necessity 
for meeting together. The worship of Christ constitutes the" centre 
of the Christian organization, and it creates Christian dogma. 
Since the God whom the Christians worship is not to be regarded 
as another god of the Mysteries in the polytheistic sense, but 
represents the redeeming revelation of the monotheistic God of 
the Prophets, the dogma of Christ develops into the doctrine of 
the Trinity. All the ideas which have been borrowed from 
philosophy and mythology are only used as a means of expressing 
ideas which have grown up out of the inner necessity of this 
Christian community for worship. Within the spheres of the 
Church, the Sects and Mysticism, however, this doctrine of 
Christ is interpreted very differently. 

The Christ of the Church is the Redeemer, who in His work 
of salvation has achieved Redemption, once for all; working 
marvellously through the ministry, the Word, and the sacraments 
in the Church, He imparts to individuals the benefits of His 
Saving Work. 

The Christ of the sect is the Lord, the example and lawgiver 
of Divine authority and dignity, who allows His elect to pass 
through contempt and misery on their earthly pilgrimage, but 
who will complete the real work of Redemption at His Return, 
when He will establish the Kingdom of God. 

The Christ of mysticism is an inward spiritual principle, felt 
in every stirring of religious feeling, present in every influence 
of the Divine “Seed” and the Divine “Spark”; this mystical 



CONCLUSION 


995 

Christ was Divinely incarnate in the Christ of History, but He 
can only be recognized and affirmed in inward spiritual ex- 
perience; this principle therefore agrees in general with the 
“hidden ground” of the Divine life in man. 

The same course of development can be traced in other doc- 
trines. As the Christ-dogma absorbed into itself Jesus’s original 
message of the Kingdom of God, so also the various transforma- 
tions of the Christ-dogma determined the fate of this second 
fundamental Christian doctrine. The Church is the Kingdom of 
Christ, and is therefore identical with the Kingdom of God in 
the world, or at any rate it is the method by which it is con- 
tinually produced afresh. In the sect Jesus is still the Herald of 
the Kingdom of God which He ushers in Himself; the sect is 
inclined to Chiliasm. In mysticism the dominion of Christ means 
the dominion of the Divine Spirit, from this point of view there- 
fore the Kingdom of God is only within us. 

The doctrine of Redemption undergoes an analogous process 
of development. From the viewpoint of the Church the work of 
Redemption was finished by the Atoning Death of Christ; this 
“finished work” endows the Church with the power to transmit 
remission of sins and sanctification. The sect believes that real 
redemption lies in the Advent of Christ and the establishment 
of the Kingdom ; the whole previous process of history was a 
mere preparation for this consummation. In mysticism redemp- 
tion is conceived as a process which is continually being repeated ; 
it culminates in the union of the soul with God ; in this experience 
Christ only serves as a quickening impulse or a symbol. In actual 
life, of course, these different types mingle and combine with 
each otjjer, just as the different types of the Christian fellowship 
also mingle and combine. But this abstract analysis makes the 
history of dogma much clearer and simpler. This system of doc- 
trine is neither a development of the Christian idea of God along 
the lines of Immanence, nor an amalgamation of the mythology of 
the ancient “mysteries” with speculative philosophy, nor an accu- 
mulation of ecclesiastical doctrinal definitions, nor an immediate 
expression of the Christian attitude towards life at any particular 
time. The religious doctrine was the expression of the religious 
vitality and development of thought which was focused first of 
all in the cultus, and then radiated forth from it again, so far 
as for this purpose ideas were necessary at all. Philosophical and 
purely dogmatic considerations were quite secondary. No one 
had ever felt the need for a dialectical interpretation of the 
instinctive conception of the idea of God itself which lay behind 



996 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

the cultus, and behind the idea of fellowship, which prevailed 
at any particular time. Individual ideas were simply linked 
together and classified. The real religious fundamental idea itself 
lay in the unconscious, and it was also embedded in the in- 
stinctive idea of fellowship and cultus which belonged to that 
conception. It was, of course, only natural that individual thinkers 
should ponder deeply upon these questions, and that, from the 
viewpoint both of theology and of the philosophy of religion, that 
they should attempt to search into the depths of her Qhristian 
knowledge of God; but so long as they remained attached 
to any kind of fellowship, even they found that the sociological 
character of the ideal of fellowship, which was vaguely defined 
in their minds, affected and limited their ideas on dogma. 

On the other hand, an essentially dogmatic criticism also 
involves a shifting of emphasis in the fundamental sociological 
sense. This, however, throws a great deal of light up<m the nature 
and the destiny of theology, on the scientific elaboration of 
Christian thought. 

The theology of Catholicism — which represents the essentially 
ritual and sacramental development of Christian thought — is the 
formulated fixation and insertion of the depositum fidei of the 
institution of Redemption into the framework of the idealistic 
development of the metaphysic of late antiquity. 

The theology of Protestantism — with its principle of the Church 
which spiritualizes public worship and the Sacrament — made the 
purified doctrine into an intellectual system, which, however, 
retains its connection with the sermon in public worship, and 
with the authoritative basis of grace and doctrine ; in consequence 
it oscillates between a system of ideas which are valid \n them- 
selves, and a group of dogmas based on history and supported 
by miracles, an uncertainty which has only been increased by 
the influence of modern science. 

The sect, which belongs essentially to the lower classes, and 
which therefore does not need to come to terms with thought 
in general, goes back to the pre-Church and pre-scientific stand- 
point, and has no theology at all ; it possesses only a strict ethic, 
a living Mythos, and a passionate hope for the future. 

“Spiritual Religion” alone conceives Christian piety as a living 
creative movement of the present day, and as a factor in the 
universal movement of religious consciousness in general. Hence 
it alone has produced a truly scientific theology, a real religi&is 
philosophy, based upon universals, and with a hope of real 
development before it. Hence of all Christian systems of thought 



CONCLUSION 


997 

it alone has been taken over and developed by the great thinkers 
of modern Idealism. Since, however, it arose out of the failure 
of the real ecclesiastical spirit, it finds it difficult to establish 
satisfactory relations with the churches, and with the conditions 
of a stable and permanent organization. This accounts for the 
difficult problem of the relation between Christianity and the 
modern cultured classes of the present day. 

Conception of Truth, 
and tiIe Idea of Toleration 

• (3) The diversity of ideas which the Christian conception of 
truth contains is evident in these three different types of religion, 
and this explains the complicated and inconsistent relation of 
Christianity to the authority of the State and to the idea of 
toleration. 

# The aim pf the Church is to be the Church of the people and 
of the masses ; it therefore transfers all divine and sacred character 
from individuals to the objective organ of redemption, with its 
divine* endowment of grace and truth. The Church possesses a 
redeeming energy which is directly miraculous, and in contrast 
to all other kinds of human power. Thus it possesses an absolute 
directly divine truth and doctrinal authority over against all 
human subjectivity. In its very nature such truths must be uni- 
form and universally authoritative. Thus in the Church itself this 
unchangeable truth is justified, and indeed bound to maintain 
its supremacy over pastors and teachers, and also over the laity. 
Every idealistic attempt to ascribe this development of the truth 
to the inward miraculous power of the Church itself, without 
compulsion, breaks down in the practical impossibility of carrying 
it through, and simply results in a return to compulsion. This 
attitude of compulsion must, however, finally express itself ex- 
ternally, because errors and customs which dishonour God ought 
not to be tolerated, and because it is not right that people who 
have been born into the membership of the Church* should be 
allowed to fall a prey to temptation. Finally, the Church must 
see to it that the whole nation shall hear the message of salvation, 
and that everyone shall have at least contact with divine 
salvation. Mercy requires it, and the absolute divine origin of the 
truth of salvation justifies this procedure. Here it is permissible 
to force people for their own good. This, however, demands the 
co-operation of the material power of the State, without which 
neither the inner uniformity of the Church, nor the building up 
of popular and territorial churches, would ever have come into 



998 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

existence. In all ithis the Church is only fulfilling its duty towards 
Divine Truth. This line of argument explains the rise of the 
complicated question of the relation between Church and State. 

The point of view of the sects, however, is quite different. They 
do not wish to be popular churches, but Christian denominations 
composed of “saints”. The sects are small groups which exist 
alongside of the State and Society. They also maintain that they 
possess the absolute truth of the Gospel, but they claim that this 
truth is far beyond the spiritual grasp of the masses and of the 
State, and therefore they desire to be free from the State, further, 
since it is precisely this absolute Gospel which forbids them to 
use force, authority, or law, they also must renounce forcing their 
opinions upon anyone, either within or without their community. 
Hence they demand external toleration, the religious neutrality 
of the State. Within their own borders, however, they practise 
a spiritual discipline of doctrine and of morals. They possess ^he 
tolerance of an idealism which believes in its own cause, and they 
forbid their followers to deduce from the absolute character of 
Truth the right to use violence in order to enforce it upon others. 
They do not expect to see the Truth permeating the masses before 
the Last Day. Where various sectarian groups exist alongside of 
each other, they permit the exercise of purely spiritual controversy 
and merely ethical rivalry without losing faith in the absolute char- 
acter of the truth they possess. This truth is not meant for the 
masses, or for humanity in general; and it will only attain its 
final consummation at the Last Day. Their conception of tolera- 
tion and freedom of conscience is of a toleration extended to 
groups like their own by the churches and the ruling powers; 
within their own borders, however, they had very little idea of 
toleration, since here Scriptural law prevails. Since, however, 
in order to uphold this unity they renounce State aid, and at 
the most can exercise the method of social boycott, endless 
divisions arise among them. It is a fact that real conformity can 
only be secured with the aid of the State and the exercise of 
compulsion. 

Finally, the point of view of spiritual idealism and mysticism 
differs entirely from that of the churches or the sects. From its 
standpoint the truth of salvation is inward and relative, a personal 
possession which is unutterable, and lies unspoken beneath all 
literal forms. The merely relative significance of the Biblical, 
dogmatic, or ritual form in which Truth is expressed makes 
mysticism independent of all liistoric forms, and the inner Unity 
of the Spirit quite naturally unites all souls in the common truth 



CONCLUSION 


999 

which is purely spiritual, and impossible to forihulate. From this 
point of view, and from it alone, are toleration and freedom of 
conscience also possible within the religious community, since the 
organization becomes merely a method of ecclesiastical adminis- 
tration, while the religious life itself can move freely under various 
forms of expression which are relatively justified. This, however, 
led to difficulties, for from this point of view it was very difficult 
to decide by what authority it was possible to determine the 
standard of what constituted Christianity in general. The usual 
answer, “the Spirit recognizes the Spirit”, was found to be useless 
•in practice. Hence this standpoint easily led to the giving up 
of all and every kind of organized fellowship, or to a withdrawal 
into private groups of a purely personal character composed of 
kindred souls. As well as conformity mysticism threatens to 
sacrifice fellowship altogether, and it easily falls into a compara- 
tive individualism. The problem of Christian toleration and 
liberty of conscience in relation to the conditions of the formation 
of religious fellowship belongs to this group of ideas. There is 
no escape from it. There are only varying practical suggestions 
of approximate utility which emerge out of this tragic interplay 
of forces. 

History of the Christian Ethos 

(4) Another result of this inquiry is the light which it throws 
upon the history of the Christian Ethos, a subject which, as is 
well known, presents extraordinary difficulties. The Ethos of the 
Gospel is a combination of infinite sublimity and childlike in- 
timacy. On the one hand, it demands the sanctification of the 
self for # God by the practice of detachment from everything which 
disturbs inward communion with God, and by the exercise of 
everything which inwardly binds the soul with God’s Will. On 
the other hand, it demands that brotherly love, which overcomes 
in God all the tension and harshness of the struggle for existence, 
of law, and of the merely external order, while it unites souls 
in a deep spirit of mutual understanding, as well as in the most 
self-sacrificing love, which, even in its simplest expressions, gives 
a true hint of the nature of God Himself. This is an ideal which 
requires a new world if it is to be fully realized ; it was this new 
world-order that Jesus proclaimed in His Message of the Kingdom 
of God. But it is an ideal which cannot be realized within this 
\forld apart from compromise. Therefore the history of the 
Christian Ethos becomes the story of a constantly renewed search 
for this compromise, and of fresh opposition to this spirit of com- 



1000 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

promise. The ChArch in particular, however, as a popular institu- 
tion, is forced to compromise ; this she effects by transferring to 
the institution the sanctity and the grace of forgiveness proper 
to it as an institution; the Church completed this compromise 
by making a covenant with the Stoic idea of the relative Law of 
Nature, which has prevailed since the Fall, which permits for the 
term of the earthly life the existence of law, might, tyranny, 
war, private property, and the desire to acquire possessions; it 
regards these things as the results of sin as well as means £or the 
healing of sin. 

When this compromise had been effected, however, within the c 
Church, the average morality of the world and the strict morality 
of holiness then separated and went their different ways. The 
ethic of holiness became fused with the dualistic asceticism of 
late antiquity, and organized the monastic system, whence it once 
more influenced the world by permeating secular Vfe with its 
higher ideals. Thus there arose a dualistic ethic which the classical 
Catholic theory worked into an ingenious system of evolution: 
the ascent from Nature to Grace. 

Ecclesiastical Protestantism destroyed this dualism, and wove 
both its elements into the ethic of the “calling” : Lutheranism 
carried this out with a careless acceptance of existing conditions, 
which are due to the presence of sin in the world, Calvinism 
and Ascetic Protestantism in an attempt to restore in a rational 
manner the holy community within the life of the world. 

Alongside of these ecclesiastical compromises, however, there 
stood from the beginning the sect, which desired to realize the 
ideal of the Sermon on the Mount in all its purity; this view 
forced it into sharp opposition to the world. In the form t of the 
passive and persecuted sect it realized the ideal with the fewest 
concessions in small and quiet groups, and comforted itself with 
the thought of the coming Kingdom of God, until, through its 
connection with Ascetic Protestantism, it also found a way of 
becoming incorporated with the life of this present world. In the 
form of the aggressive sect, when the End of the World seemed 
imminent, it felt justified in using force, and tried to establish 
the Christian order of life by violent methods; naturally, the 
experiment was never permanently successful ; also such outbreaks 
always damaged the real Christianity of the sect, for then the 
Apocalypse and the Old Testament took the place of the Gospel. 

Finally, untroubled by any of these questions of compromise, 
mysticism and “spiritual religion” went its own way, proclaiming 
the freedom of the Spirit and liberty of conscience, antinomian 



CONCLUSION 


ioo i 


in the good, and also incidentally in the bad, sknse ; even where 
it was severely ascetic it maintained its spirit of freedom. This 
is the piety which acts or refrains from action as it is “moved 
by the Spirit”, to use the language of the Quakers; that is, its 
action is controlled by its sense of inward communion with the 
living and holy God, and it expresses itself in a purely inward 
personal communion of individuals. This point of view certainly 
prevents its influencing the masses, or effecting any kind of 
organisation of life on a large scale. But from the very outset 
this type of Christianity does not expect to influence the life of 
•the world on a large scale; or if it does cherish such hopes it 
bases them purely on confidence in the interior “power of the 
Spirit”. In the general way, it leaves to chance the question of 
the extension of its spirit into the general life of the world, and 
of a consequent inner transformation. In all these ethical move- 
ments, howgver, the impelling power is that of Christian hostility 
to the world. To-day this fundamental Christian tendency has 
been sensibly weakened by the tendencies of modern life : with 
it®. Utilitarianism and its optimism, with its ideas of Immanence, 
its Naturalism, and its aesthetic glorification of Nature, often to 
the extent of being unable to interpret its own meaning. But it 
breaks forth anew from the fundamental ideas of religion and 
out of the self-destruction of every kind of purely secular op- 
timism. In the midst of all the pleasures of civilization and of 
all mere sceptical pessimism, once again it summons the Christian 
ethic to face its task. 

To-day, therefore, the main problem of the Christian Ethos is 
still the problem of supernaturalism, and of its unavoidable result, 
asceticism, in the metaphysical-dualistic or in the disciplinary 
rigorist sense, an asceticism which is never merely a simple denial 
of the world and of self. On the other hand, its second main 
problem is how to supplement this religious onesidedness with 
an ethic of civilization which can be combined with it. The 
Church effected this supplement by drawing on the philosophy 
of late antiquity, and incorporating into its own ethic the idea 
of the moral Law of Nature. When the sect gave up this idea of 
a supplement of this kind altogether, it became uncultured 
and insignificant, while mysticism became complete and solitary 
resignation. Whenever both these movements rose to importance, 
they likewise introduced, each in its own way, a supplement. 
Tb-day, however, in an entirely new state of civilization these 
earlier supplementary movements have become impossible. 
A new supplementary process, therefore, is necessary. In a 



iooa THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

permanent worldj the Christian Ethos cannot live and be entirely 
self-sufficing. The* question is simply this : How can this supplement 
be shaped to-day? The answer to this question constitutes an 
imperative demand for a new Christian ethic. 

Significance of the Marxist Method for the 
Study of Christian History 

(5) The last important point which is illuminated by our 
historical survey is that of the right to apply a method of social 
history to Christianity, and the limits within which this may be 
exercised. The “Marxist” method, especially those elements* 
within it which seem clearly justified, is gradually transforming 
all our historical conceptions, and naturally it also transforms 
all our ideas about the present and the future. Scholars of the 
“class-war” school have undertaken to represent the whole of 
Christianity as an ideological reflection of economic development, 
and in so doing they have not only impressed the comrades 
within their own Party. In a finer and more instructive way 
quite recently Maurenbrecher applied this conception to the 
origin of Christianity. In opposition to the exclusive and doc- 
trinaire application of this method, however, the whole of this 
survey has shown that all that is specifically religious, and, above 
all, the great central points of religious development, are an 
independent expression of the religious life. Jesus, Paul, Origen, 
Augustine, Thomas Aquinas, Francis of Assisi, Bonaventura, 
Luther, Calvin: as we study their thought and their feeling we 
realize that it is impossible to regard them as the product of 
class struggles and of economic factors. 

On the other hand, however, it is clear that in the causal 
connection out of which their peculiar form of religious thought 
gains concrete stimulus, force, movement, and aim, social and 
even, finally, economic influences are at work, though this is not 
always apparent, and their significance varies considerably. As 
in all other spheres of life, so also in that of the history of religion, 
the conception of the causal connection is considerably widened 
and altered by giving fresh attention to this co-operating element. 
As previously we have been in the habit of placing scientific- 
historical, philosophical, race-theory biological causalities in the 
context out of which and in which the concrete movements of 
religious history arise, so also this newly discovered causality 
must be accepted in its full significance. In theory this means 
nothing new, once we have become accustomed to the idea of 
seeing religious revelations developing out of a causal connection ; 



CONCLUSION 1003 

we will not deal further with their supposed “Necessity”, or with 
“supposed laws of history”. Causality knows no hierarchy; no 
degree of greater or lesser importance, and so it is no depreciation 
of previous theories (as many people suppose) if this newly 
discovered causality is granted just as much right to exist as 
those which were previously in a position of honour. In practice, 
however, this does mean a considerable shifting of emphasis. It 
then becomes clear that Christianity and the idealistic ethical and 
religiqjus aspirations and endeavours of late antiquity (which were 
so closely akin to Christianity) were certainly connected with the 
• final result of the social history of the Ancient World, and there- 
fore they also met and united to form the new world; we have 
seen how the Middle Ages maintained its existence with the 
support of the Church and of the Christian Ethos within a rela- 
tively simple and undeveloped social setting, and that only thus 
did a Christian civilization become possible; we have seen that 
the individualism of the Reformation presupposed the collapse 
of rqediaeval society, and that the triumphant realization of 
Ae Reformation can only be explained from the standpoint of 
political and social conditions ; we have seen that the difference 
between the two great divisions of Protestantism is very largely 
caused and conditioned by its political and social setting; we 
have seen how modern Protestantism is bound up with modern 
bourgeois society and with their ideals of civilization, and, finally, 
we have seen that Capitalism, the modern Nationalist and 
Imperialist State, and the vast increase in the population of the 
world, constitute a crisis for the previous Christian ethic. The 
social position and relations of the sects reveal the hidden reasons 
for sudden changes of religious thought, which could not have 
been explained from their merely intellectual dialectic. 

All this means that the history of religion is being drawn far 
more deeply into the stream of events, and into the varying 
conditions within the fundamental elements in life. Thus it 
becomes still less possible to find an unchangeable and absolute 
point in the Christian ethic, since this also only means the mastery 
of an existing situation, which is determined pre-eminently by 
social conditions and the establishment of an ideal which corre- 
sponds to this situation. The history of religion, however, has 
long been moving towards such a conception, ever since it learned 
to place the religious life within the general current of historical 
Evolution. Thus it becomes clearer than ever that each factor is 
relatively conditioned as a synthesis which cannot be repeated, 
and as a spiritual-ethical mastery of this particular situation, 



1004 THE SOCIAj, TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

which often sees Jhith much more clearly in the instinctive side 
of life than in the theory which overlooks and condones so much. 
Thus, finally, it becomes impossible to regard whole periods and 
groups solely as preparatory phases for an Absolute which can 
never be found in history. We then perceive the force of that 
pregnant phrase of Ranke (to which reference has often been 
made) that each epoch — not in its crude actuality, but with the 
aims and ideals which it has instinctively formed — exists directly 
for God. This truth also applies to the mastery of the tasks which 
arise out of the natural basis of life, from the economic social 
situation, out of the political conditions of power, by thought, « 
in which thought can never be independent of the material 
which it has mastered, and by which it is frequently set in motion. 
On the other hand, however, all attempts to make Christianity 
into a changeful reflection of economic and social history are 
either a foolish fashion, or under cover of the most repent science 
they conceal a hidden attack on the religious value of Christianity. 

Nature of the Christian Ethos ^ 

(6) All these results are of an historical nature. The question, 
however, naturally arises : Does an extended inquiry of this kind 
about the Christian world of life and thought really yield nothing 
more than historical light on the past and on its influence upon 
the present? Does it not also teach something lasting and eternal 
about the content of the Christian social Ethos, which might 
serve as a guiding star for the present and for the future, some- 
thing which would aid us not merely to understand but also to 
transform the situation? It certainly is in the position of being 
able to teach us something of this kind. But perceptions of eternal 
ethical values are not scientific perceptions, and cannot be proved 
along scientific lines. These perceptions have been selected from 
life in history, which the living conviction and the active will 
fully apprehend in the certainty that here we perceive absolute 
Reason in the revelation which is addressed to us and formed in 
the present connection. Only in this sense is the attempt now made 
to emphasize the permanent ethical values which are contained 
within the varied history of the Christian social doctrines. 

Firstly: The Christian Ethos alone possesses, in virtue of its 
personalistic Theism, a conviction of personality and individual- 
ity, based on metaphysics, which no Naturalism and no Pessimism 
can disturb. That personality which, rising above the natural order 
of life, is only achieved through a union of will and the depths of 
being with God, alone transcends the finite, and alone can defy 



CONCLUSION 


1005 

it. Without this support, however, every kind of individualism 
evaporates into thin air. ' 

Secondly: The Christian Ethos alone, through its conception of 
a Divine Love which embraces all souls and unites them all, 
possesses a Socialism which cannot be shaken. It is only within 
the medium of the Divine that the separation and reserve, the 
strife and exclusiveness which belong to man as a natural product, 
and which shape his natural existence, disappear. Only here do 
the associations formed by compulsion, sympathy and need of 
help, sex instinct and attraction, work and organization attain a 
' connection which transcends them all, a connection which is 
indestructible because it is metaphysical. 

Thirdly: Only the Christian Ethos solves the problem of equality 
and inequality, since it neither glorifies force and accident in the 
sense of a Nietzschian cult of breed, nor outrages the patent facts 
of life by a^doctrinaire equalitarianism. It recognizes differences in 
social position, power, and capacity, as a condition which has been 
established by the inscrutable Will of God ; and then transforms 
this condition by the inner upbuilding of the personality, and the 
development of the mutual sense of obligation, into an ethical 
cosmos. The ethical values of voluntary incorporation and 
subordination on the one hand, and of care and responsibility 
for others on the other hand, place each human being in circum- 
stances where natural differences can and should be transmuted 
into the ethical values of mutual recognition, confidence, and 
care for others. 

Fourthly: Through its emphasis upon the Christian value of 
personality, and on love, the Christian Ethos creates something 
which # no social order — however just and rational — can dispense 
with entirely, because everywhere there will always remain 
suffering, distress, and sickness for which we cannot account — in 
a word, it produces charity. Charity, or active helpfulness, is the 
fruit of the Christian Spirit, which alone keeps it alive. Whatever 
pettiness and desire to convert may be bound up with it must 
simply be regarded as human limitations within something 
which is great and noble. 

In conclusion: The Christian Ethos gives to all social life and 
aspiration a goal which lies far beyond all the relativities of this 
earthly life, compared with which, indeed, everything else repre- 
sents merely approximate values. The idea of the future Kingdom 
<5f God, which is nothing less than faith in the final realization 
of the Absolute (in whatever way we may conceive this realiza- 
tion), does not, as short-sighted opponents imagine, render this 



ioo6 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

world and life in this world meaningless and empty; on the 
contrary, it stirmilates human energies, making the soul strong 
through its various stages of experience in the certainty of an 
ultimate, absolute meaning and aim for human labour. Thus it 
raises the soul above the world without denying the world. This 
idea, which is the deepest meaning of all Christian asceticism, is 
the only means by which strength and heroism may be main- 
tained in a general spiritual situation, in which the emotional life 
is infinitely deepened and refined, and in which the natural 
motives for heroism are either altogether lost, or else the attempt 
is made to try to reawaken them on the side of brutal instinct. * 
This idea creates a perennial source of strength for strenuous 
activity, and a certainty of aim, both of which make for simple 
health and soundness of mind. All social Utopias, then, become 
superfluous; over and over again experience teaches that the 
ideal cannot be fully realized; but this does not mefin that the 
seeker for Truth and justice need lose heart and fall back into 
scepticism, a temptation to which serious and truth-loving souls 
are prone, and the effects of which are very manifest among the 
finer spirits of the present day. The life beyond this world is, in 
very deed, the inspiration of the life that now is. 

What is the best Form of Organization 
for Christian Religious Life? 

(7) These social and ethical ideas and energies spring out of the 
Christian religion. To enable them to do this it is necessary to 
maintain the vitality and to extend the scope of these religious 
energies ; again, in order to achieve both these ends, an organiza- 
tion is needed which will lead them forward and continually 
produce them afresh. 

This leads us to the question : What does our present inquiry 
teach us about this problem, which is a question of vital impor- 
tance, about the formation of the religious community itself and 
its incorporation into the other great movements? Can we not 
learn something from a large work of this kind to help us to 
overcome our miserable ecclesiastical situation, which is daily 
becoming worse? 

Here also the yield is a rich one, although it is more <a matter 
of free insight into what is expedient than a scientific proof. 
The first thing we learn is, that the religious life — on the plane of 
spiritual religion — needs an independent organization, in order tb 
distinguish it from other organizations of a natural kind. It strives 
after this from the moment it conceives of an independent exist- 



CONCLUSION 1007 

ence, and this always remains one of its most important problems. 
Public worship forms the centre of such an organization; the 
derivation of comprehensive energies from it, or the organic 
attachment of them to it, is the great problem. Unless it is organ- 
ized into a community with a settled form of worship, Christ- 
ianity cannot be either expansive or creative. Every kind of 
reaction to a mere “freedom of the Spirit” in the hope that it will 
grow and thrive without organization, is a Utopian ideal which is 
out of touch with the actual conditions of life, and its only effect 
is to weaken the whole. 

• Secondly, so far as the form of this organization is concerned, 
it has become evident that the Church-type is obviously superior to 
the sect-type and to mysticism. The Church-type preserves in- 
violate the religious elements of grace and redemption ; it makes 
it possible to differentiate between Divine grace and human 
effort ; it is ^ble to include the most varied degrees of Christian 
attainment and maturity, and therefore it alone is capable of 
fostering a popular religion which inevitably involves a great 
variety in its membership. In this respect the Church-type is 
superior to the sect-type and also to mysticism. This is why the 
main current of historical Christianity becomes the “History of 
the Church”, and this is why the first result of the missionary 
work of the Early Church was “the universal Christian Church”. 
At the same time, however, it cannot be denied that this does 
mean a modification of Christian thought in order to bring it 
down to the average level, to the level of practical possibility; 
and it is a principle of far-reaching adjustment and compromise. 

In the third place : the Church-type itself, just because of this 
element of tension between pure Christianity and adjustment to 
the world which exists within it, has had a very changeful history, 
and is to-day becoming entirely transformed. Roman Catholicism 
is the pure and logical form of the Church-type; to an ever- 
increasing degree it has sacrificed the inwardness, individuality, 
and plasticity of religion to the fixed determination to make 
religion objective in doctrine, Sacrament, hierarchy, the Papacy 
and Papal Infallibility; the only outlet it gives to the sect-type 
and to mysticism is through the Religious Orders and the devo- 
tions of 4;he Church. Since the crisis in the fifteenth century, 
when men’s confidence in its right to dominate was shaken, it 
has therefore set itself to become more and more objective and 
centralized. Protestantism, on the other hand, has developed in 
the opposite direction, seeking to make the idea of the Church 
more subjective and inward, by placing the objective organizing 



ioo8 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

element in the I^oly Scriptures and in the spiritual power which 
dwells within thfe'm, and also in the ministry which expounds the 
Word. Luther based his hopes on the all-converting power of the 
Spirit and of the Word, a hope which was speedily disappointed, 
while Calvin sought the support of a stable ecclesiastical constitu- 
tion with authority to control the faithful. 

All the ecclesiastical institutions soon found that they were 
unable to maintain and carry on their existence by moral force 
alone, and they were obliged to appeal to the civil power for aid. 
Without its help no ecclesiastical system can be permanent, 
uniform, and undivided. This situation cannot be conceived# 
without compulsion, and compulsory religion cannot be con- 
ceived without the help of the State. In periods when a naive 
type of faith is widespread, this kind of compulsion is not harmful, 
nor does it militate against religion. If one is quite sure of the 
truth, and if the general instincts of the nations are united on this 
point, then the preservation from folly, error, and the danger of 
being led astray is only sensible and healthy ; it is the assumption 
upon which the spiritual unity of Society in general is maintain^ 
which it is not right to sacrifice to the doctrinaire and super- 
idealistic ideal of free self-legislation on the part of the individual. 

In the fourth place : precisely because the Church-type is thus 
connected with the unbroken unity of an instinctive world-outlook 
of great masses of people the uniform Church-type is inwardly 
suitable for such periods alone. We have seen, in the course of 
this inquiry, that since these assumptions have disappeared the 
Church-type has been going through a process of decay and even 
of destruction. The days of the pure Church-type within our 
present civilization are numbered. Ideas which the modern 
world accepts as natural and obvious do not agree with the 
views of the Church. Compulsion is no longer a defence of the 
whole against individual disturbance ; it only means the forcible 
restraint of currents of real vitality. Either completely or partially 
the civil power has retired into the background, and soon it will 
cease to have any influence at all. 

In countries where the religious situation contains many 
different elements, the various ecclesiastical systems constitute a 
large body of opinion, in which each particular communion 
claims to possess the sole Truth, thus neutralizing the religious 
influence of all. The churches are losing their hold on the spiritual 
life of the nations, and many of their functions are now being 
exercised by educationists, writers, administrators, and by volun- 
tary religious associations. Under these circumstances the Catholic 



CONCLUSION 1009 

Church-type has been forced to exercise an increasingly powerful 
and external dominion over the consciences ormen. The Pro- 
testant churches, on the other hand, have not exercised the same 
influence. This is due to two causes: (1) because they are not 
sufficiently vigorous to be able to do this ; and (2) because their 
subjective interpretation of the idea of the Church contains strong 
tendencies which are directly opposed to a development of this 
kind. Thus they have not been able to withstand the influence of 
the sect-type and mysticism, both of which are tendencies which 
have a close affinity with the modern world. The Protestant 
•Church-type, therefore, has persisted with the aid of sectarian 
ideas and the relativism of idealism and mysticism. Protestantism 
no longer represents the pure Church-type, although the ecclesi- 
astical spirit of conformity has raised indignant enough protests 
against this irresistible development, and either secretly or openly 
c^ts longing glances at Catholic ideals. Protestantism is develop- 
ing at present along the following lines : separation between 
Church and State; suspension of the endeavour to form new 
churcfies ; the independence of the individual congregation ; the 
transformation of State churches into popular churches in which 
there is / a united system of administration, while the individual 
congregations are left a free hand to manage their own affairs; 
by this very fact, however, these churches contain a certain 
amount of high explosive which is a continual menace to their 
existence. Even beneath the veil of an apparently stable united 
confessional Church, the lack of denominational principle on the 
part of most of the members has produced this situation. More 
and more the central life of the Church-type is being permeated 
with the vital energies of the sect and of mysticism; the whole 
history of Protestantism reveals this very clearly. While Catholi- 
cism does all it can to hinder the development of these tendencies, 
they are both becoming stronger and stronger within the Protes- 
tant churches. In the mutual interpenetration of the three chief 
sociological categories, which must be united with a structure 
which will reconcile them all, lie its future tasks, tasks of a socio- 
logical and organizing kind, which are more pressing than all 
doctrinal questions. Along this path all efforts to achieve a recon- 
ciling unity have failed. An “Ecclesiastical Protestant system of 
dogma” no longer exists. Thus it is evident that union and 
cohesion must be sought in some other sphere than in that of 
ddjgma. This will only be possible on the assumption that the 
churches which have been created by compulsion, on a basis of 
authority and rigid conformity, may become homes within which 

VOL. II. NN 



1010 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

Christians of very varying outlook can live and work together in 
peace. 

The ecclesiastical organizations maintain themselves by their 
own historic weight, and, once they have been created, they can 
serve other ends than those for which they were originally con- 
structed. The pain and travail which the State Church system has 
cost in its day may be regarded as a sacrifice which the effort of 
building it has cost ; but it does not need to be continually repeated. 
The home which was constructed by compulsion and relentless 
insistence upon rigid conformity to a uniform type of doctrine and 
organization can thus be inhabited by finer spirits and especially* 
by souls of very varied types ; they will then, it is true, have to 
guard the spirit of mutual toleration within certain wide limits. 
While a mere system of Free Church organization, or a system 
based on the separation between Church and State, only ensures 
liberty of conscience alongside of and outside of tjhe churches 
while within them it fosters a very real spirit of intolerance, a 
system of that kind would be able to maintain a national (or 
popular) Church, and yet preserve at the same time liberty«of 
conscience (so ardently desired) within the Church itself, so far 
as that is at all possible. The spirit of the Church-type would thus 
be maintained in its great conviction of an historical substance 
of life which is common to all, a substance which, in the various 
smaller religious groups and declarations, would be expressed, 
partly in one group and partly in another, which would preserve 
the whole from stagnation. We thus retain the sense of a common 
faith and the consciousness of a great inheritance as a “Minimum 
of the Church” as Richard Rothe used to say. 

Christianity and the Modern Social Problem 

(8) What has become of the question, however, from which 
we originally started? — the question of the significance of Christ- 
ianity for the solution of the social problem of the present day? 
This social problem is vast and complicated. It includes the 
problem of the capitalist economic period and of the industrial 
proletariat created by it ; and of the growth of militaristic and 
bureaucratic giant states; of the enormous increase in popula- 
tion, which affects colonial and world policy, of the mechanical 
technique, which produces enormous masses of material and 
links up and mobilizes the whole world for purposes of trade, 
but which also treats men and labour like machines. • 

Bearing in mind the whole trend of this book, we only need 
to formulate this question thus in order to recognize as its most 



CONCLUSION 


IOI i 


important reply that this problem is entirely new, a problem with 
which Christian-Social work has never been confronted until now. 

In face of the vast and serious nature of this problem the radical 
ideals of social reformers of the Chiliastic sects seem like child’s 
play and childish fantasies ; admirable and noble, no doubt, but 
Utopian even in their modern form of a Christian Socialism 
which dreams of a radical social transformation of the world. 
From the very outset mysticism declined to make any attempt 
to find a solution of the problem; in all this confusion it only 
discerrfls how impossible it is for the world to give the peace which 
.passes all understanding. 

All the Christian churches — the Lutheran Church least of all, 
however — are evolving schemes for the alleviation of all this 
distress which weighs on our hearts and minds like a perpetual 
menace, and each church does its part eagerly and unselfishly. 
But in all this the churches are only returning in essentials to the 
ofd and great main types of their social philosophy, which they 
are trying to mobilize afresh for the titanic struggles of the present 
day. Now, as we have seen, there are only two great main types 
otsocial philosophy which have attained comprehensive historical 
significance and influence. The first is the social philosophy of 
mediaeval Catholicism which is based on the family, guild, and 
class, which was able to combine a relative dependence on the 
struggle for existence, the establishment of all fellowship upon 
personal relations of authority and reverence, the relatively 
simple economic forms and needs of the pre-capitalistic period, 
the remains of old solidarities in conditions which involved being 
bound to the soil or involved in the fortunes of some ancient 
family, with the Christian Ethos of the personal value of the 
individual and of the universal fellowship of love within the 
ecclesiastical organization of life. The second is the social philo- 
sophy of Ascetic Protestantism, which developed out of that kind 
*of Calvinism which was tinged with a Free Church, Pietistic 
Outlook, and also out of those ascetic sects which had almost 
broken with the churches altogether, which is inwardly related 
to modem Utilitarianism and Rationalism, with diligence in one’s 
calling and the glorification of work for its own sake, with political 
democracy and Liberalism, with the freedom of the individual 
and the all-dominating idea of the social group, which, however, 
knows how to neutralize the ethically dangerous consequences of 
modem life by the religious ideas of the responsibility of the 
individual, and of the duty of love, both of the individual and of 
the community, through the taboo on luxury, mammon, and 



ioia THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 

love of pleasure, and finally through heroism in serving the cause 
of Christ all ovdf the world. 

Other Christian-Social ideals which developed alongside of 
these two main types were unable to make any impression on the 
hard mass of social realities ; against this rock they fling themselves 
in vain to-day. 

Both these powerful types of social philosophy, however, in 
spite of their great and enduring achievements, have now spent 
their force. So far as Catholicism of the patriarchal guild type is 
concerned, its failure is due to the fact that it is almost a sheer 
impossibility to realize its aims at the present day ; a further cause* 
of failure is the fact that these ideals cannot be carried out in 
practice, owing to the weakened religious forces of Catholicism ; 
this also produces other results which are almost intolerable. Ascetic 
Protestantism, however, which had attempted to establish the 
rule of Christ over Society by a rational method, controlled by 
the ruling idea of religion, finds to its dismay that tfie results of 
its theory have long ago slipped away from its control, and that 
they have cast aside as useless all the original restrictions ajad 
landmarks, whether religious, intellectual, or metaphysical. On 
the other hand, by its cool austerity, its restraint and its concrete 
outlook, its proselytizing zeal, and its inartistic and Puritan 
characteristics, it is opposed to all the instincts of modern civiliza- 
tion; from the purely religious standpoint also its tendency to 
legalism and Pharisaism, to feverish activity and a mechanical 
outlook, is very far from being in complete agreement with the 
deepest Christian ideas. 

Under these circumstances our inquiry leads to the conclusion 
that all Christian-Social work is in a problematic condition. It is 
problematic in general because the power of thought to overcome 
brutal reality is always an obscure and difficult question; it is 
problematic in particular because the main historic forms of the 
Christian doctrine of society and of social development are 
to-day, for various reasons, impotent in face of the tasks by which 
they are confronted. 

If the present social situation is to be controlled by Christian 
principles, thoughts will be necessary which have not yet been 
thought, and which will correspond to this new situatiqn as the 
older forms met the need of the social situation in earlier ages. 
These ideas will have to be evolved out of the inner impulse of 
Christian thought, and out of its vital expression at the present 
time, and not exclusively out of the New Testament, in precisely 
the same way as both those great main types of Christian-Social 



CONCLUSION 


i 


1013 


philosophy were evolved out of the Christian ^hought of their 
own day, and not solely from the New Testament. And when 
they have been created and expressed, they will meetjthe fate 
which always awaits every fresh creation of religious and ethical 
thought: they will render indispensable services and they will 
develop profound energies, but they will never fully realize their 
actual ideal intention within the sphere of our earthly struggle 
and conflict. 

As little as any other power in this world will they create the 
Kingdom of God upon earth as a completed social ethical organ- 
ism. One of the most serious and important truths which emerge 
as a result of this inquiry is this: every idea is still faced by 
brutal facts, and all upward movement is checked and hindered 
by interior and exterior difficulties. Nowhere does there exist an 
absolute Christian ethic, which only awaits discovery; all that 
w$e can do in to learn to control the world-situation in its successive 
phases just as the earlier Christian ethic did in its own way. 
Ther$ is also no absolute ethical transformation of material 
nurture or of human nature; all that does exist is a constant 
wrestling with the problems which they raise. Thus the Christian 
ethic of the present day and of the future will also only be an 
adjustment to the world-situation, and it will only desire to 
achieve that which is practically possible. This is the cause of that 
ceaseless tension which drives man onward yet gives him the sense 
that he can never realize his ethical ideal. Only doctrinaire ideal- 
ists or religious fanatics can fail to recognize these facts. Faith is 
the source of energy in the struggle of life, but life still remains a 
battle which is continually renewed upon ever new fronts. For 
every threatening abyss which is closed, another yawning gulf 
appears. The truth is — and this is the conclusion of the whole 
matter — the Kingdom of God is within us. But we must let our 
light shine before men in confident and untiring labour that they 
may see our good works and praise our Father in Heaven. The 
final ends of all humanity are hidden within His Hands. 




INDEX OF NAMES 1 


Abelard, 235 
Adventists, 725 
Agrippa v. Nettesheim, 769 
Althusius, 634 ff. 

Amesius, 684 
Anabaptists, v. Baptists 
Andrea* J. V., 570 
Anglicans, 639, 668, 672, 678 
•Arcadius, 139 
Arians, 209 

Aristotle, 119, 239, 259, 264, 268 ff., 
270 ff, 292, 298 ff, 317, 329, 369, 
505 , 5o 8> 524, 527, 535 ff. 
Arminians, 635, 683 ff. 

Afndt, Johanfies, 786 
Arnold of Brescia, 237, 351 
Arnokl, Gottfried, 334, 788 
As'ietic Protestantism, 688 ff., 805, 
807 ff., 815, 818 

Augustine, St., 74, no, 119, 154, 156, 
158, 212, 230, 239, 244, 259, 266, 
282, 329, 333, 369, 737 

Bacon, Francis, 777 
Baptist Movement, 694 ff. 

Baptists, at Zurich, 703 ff. 

Baptists, General, 706 ff. 

Barebones Parliament, 667, 709, 713 

Barrowe, Henry, 662 ff., 665 

Baxter, Richard, 678 

Bayle, Pierre, 674 

Beghards, 371 

Beguines, 371 

Bellers, John, 712, 726, 783 
Benedictines, 244 
Bentham, Jeremy, 646 
Bernard (St.) of Clairvaux, 237, 245, 
684, 730, 737, 777, 786, 787 
Bernstein, 782 

Beza, ThecJdore, 629 f., 643, 650 ff. 
Bismarck, 24, 675 
Bodin, 537 

Bttehme, Jakob, 769, 774, 792 
Bona ventura, St., 352 


Boniface, 217 

Brethren of the Common Life, 371 
Brethren of the Free Spirit, 355 
Browne, Robert, 661 ff , 665, 707 
Brownists, 661 ff. 

Bucer, Martin, 626, 669, 677, 678 
Biinderlin, 769 

Bunyan, John, 678, 679, 709, 772 
Byzantinism, 214, 215 

Calixtines, 363 
Calvin, 579 ff. 

Calvinism, 576 ff. 

Calvinism, primitive, 625 ff. 

Carlyle, 795 

Carolingian Dynasty, 215, 219, 224, 
246 

Carpocratians, 40 
Cartwright, 678 
Castellio, Sebastian, 762 ff. 

Cathari, 245, 350, 354 
Catherine of Genoa (St.), 787 
Celsus, 124, 15 1 
Charlemagne, 217 f., 244, 246 
Chiliasm, 369, 380, 680, 704 ff., 
709 ff., 713, 758 
Chrysostom, 127, 212 
Cicero, 15 1, 505, 508 
Cluniacs, 220, 224 ff. 

Collegiants, 766, 771, 774 
Comenius, 770 
Congregationalism, 663 ff. 
Constantine, 125, 130, 138, 151, 463, 
788 

Coornheert, 749, 764 ff., 785 
Cosmas Indicopleustes, 143 
Cromwell, Oliver, 668 ff, 675, 678, 

778 

Crusades, 222, 240, 254, 352 
Cynics, no, 119 


Damiani, Peter, 229, 237 
Dana us, Lambert, 631 
Dante, 229, 231, 245, 352 

Volume II. begins at p. 455. 



ioi6 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 


Darbyites (Plymouth Brethren), 725 

Darwin, 676 

Dell, John, 753, 778 f. 

Denk, Hans, 768 ff., 777 
Descartes, 74 
Diggers, 71 1 

Diocletian, Reign of, 128 
Dionysius the Areopagite, 259, 737, 
777 

Dippel, 788 
Dolcino, 356, 370 
Dominicans, 736 
Domitian, 42 

Donatists, 209, 329, 333, 350 
Dordrecht, Synod of, 683 
Drews, Arthur, 788 
Duplessis-Mornay, 631 

Eckhart, 796 
Edelmann, 749, 788 
Emden, Synod of, 683 
Emerson, 795 

Enlightenment, The, 279, 672, 681, 
819 

Entfelder, 769 
Epictetus, 66, 67 
Erasmus, 635, 750, 760, 764 
Erastianism, 659, 683 
Estienne, Henri, 631 
Eudo de Stella, 351 
Everard, John, 777 

Familists, 71 1, 770, 772, 777 

Fichte, 792, 794 

Fifth Monarchy Men, 667 

Filmer, Robert, 637 

Flagellants, 356 

Fludd, 769 

Fox, George, 778 

Francis (St.) of Assisi, 355 ff., 362, 

777 

Franciscans, 229, 231, 237, 245, 352, 

355. 359. 374. 736 

Franck, Sebastian, 334, 484, 71 1, 741, 
750, 760 fr., 765, 767 ff., 769, 775, 
79*. 792. 796 

Francke, August Hermann, 787 
Franklin, Benjamin, 783 
Fries, 790 


Galenua, Abrahams, 766 
Gentillet, 631 
George, Henry, 712 
Geulinex, 774 
Gichtel, 769 
Gierke, 97, 98 
Gladstone, 675 

Gnosticism, 40, 105 ff., 147, 736, 769 
Goethe, 792 

Gregory the Great, 133, 154, 244, 259 
Gregory VII., 212, 225 ff, 2*7, 229, 
232 

Grotius, Hugo, 538, 635 

Hall, 777 

Hamann, 792 

Harnack, Adolf, 244 

Harrison, 667, 709, 713 

Hattem, Pontiaan van, ^74 

Hatzer, 769 

Hegel, 792,^94, 796 f. 

Helmont, van, 769 

Helwys, 707 

Henry of Toulouse, 351 

Herder, 792 

Hermas, 150 

Hobbes, Thomas, 639 ff. 

Honorius, 139 
Hooker, 637 

Huguenots, 612, 650, 655, 677 
Huss, John, 362 ff, 367 
Hussites, 355, 358, 362 ff , 368 ff , 703, 
754 

Hut, 704 

Independency, 365, 369, 514, 661, 
663, 666 ff., 671, 694, 708 ff, 741, 
778 fr. 

Innocent III., 226 
Institutio Calvini , 628 
Irenaeus, 154 
Irvingitcs, 725 
Isidore (of Seville), 154 

Jacobi, F. H., 792 
Janeaway, James, 777 
Jansenism, 715, 789 
Jellinek, 672 
Joachim, Abbot, 370 



INDEX OF NAMES 


Joachimites, 355, 366, 370 
Joris, Davids 770 ff. 

Jung Stilling, 785 
Jurieu, 631, 653 
Justinian, 130, 156 

Kant, 279, 544, 618, 792 
Karls tadt, 738, 741, 755 ff., 768 
Kautsky, 28 
Kepler, 769 ff. 

Knox, 5 ohn, 632, 655 
Kuyper, 655, 660, 676 

La Badie, Jean de, 724 ff. 

Labadists, 724 
Lactantius, 151 
Lagarde, 801 
Lampe, 653 
Casko, John% 678 
Lavater, 785 

Leibniz, 636, 792 » 

•Lessing, 792, 799 
Levellers, 710 
Lilburn, John, 710, 712 
Locke, 636 ff, 646, 669, 672, 712 
Lodensteyn, 684, 724, 774 
Lollards, 358 

Luther, 465 ff, 515 ff , 603, 610, 613, 
618, 692, 694, 716, 730, 740, 745, 

75 ° 753 > 756 > 77 ° 

Lutheranism, 515 ff, 605 ff, 610, 613, 
617, 641, 647, 649, 652, 678, 680, 
690, 697, 714, 716 ff., 740, 803, 
810 ff., 814, 819 

Macchiavelli, 532, 559 
Major, John, 632 
Manchester School (econ.), 647 
Marsiglio of Padua, 372 
Marx, 726 

Maurenbrecher, 1002 
Melanchthon, 493, 523, 527, 535 ff., 
613 

Mennonifes, 705 ff., 662, 699, 781, 805 
Merovingians, 221 

Methodists, 689, 715, 721 ff, 74 L 759 > 
9 784 ff. 

Methodius, St., 131 
Meyer, Edward, 206 


Mill, John Stuart, 677 
Millennarians, 712 
Milton, John, 671, 674 
Monarchomachi, 630 ff, 651 
Monk, General, 709 
Monophysite Churches, 209 
Montanism, 148, 329 
Moravians, 719 ff, 788 ff. 

More, Sir Thomas, 278, 378 
Miinzer, Thomas, 754 ff. 

Murton, 707 

Nathusius, 26, 28, 33 
Naumann, 568 
Nazarenes, 771 

Neo-Calvinism, 673 ff, 688 ff., 805 ff. 
Neo-Platonism, 239, 271, 273, 276, 
329, 736 ff., 748, 770, 777, 788, 
792 

Nestorians, 209 
Nicholas da Cusa, 278 
Niclaes, Hendrik, 772 ff. 

Nietzsche, 571 
Nominalism, 278, 464 
Novalis, 790, 794, 797 

Occhino, 762 

Ockham, William of, 374, 464, 480 

Oldenbarneveld, 636 

Origen, 1 51, 777 

Ortlieb, 355 

Osiander, 738 

Otto I and II, Emperors, 215, 220 
Owen, Richard, 712, 726, 784 

Paracelsus, 769, 790 
Patarini, 350 

Pelagian Controversy, no 
Penn, William, 782 ff. 

Peter of Bruys, 351 
Peter of Chelzic, 367 
Peutinger, 559 
Philip of Hesse, 669 
Pietism, 514, 567, 657, 677 ff., 686 ff., 
714 ff., 740, 770, 771, 774, 777, 
784 ff., 799 

Pilgrim Fathers, 665 ff., 681 
Pirckheimer, 559 
Plato, 67 



ioi8 THE SOCIAL TEACHING OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES 


Platonism, 44, 47, 143, 163, 202 ff., 
231, 242, 249, 259, 792 
Pliny, 42, 124 
Plockboy, P. C., 712 
Plotinus, 777 
Poimandres, 777 
Poiret, 769 
Pordagc, John, 713 
Precisianism, 682 ff. 

Presbyterians, 634, 661, 666, 667, 
678 

Proclus, 777 
Pufendorf, 538, 639 
Puritanism, 365, 545, 609, 657, 659, 
661, 663, 671, 677 ff., 683, 687, 697, 
7 i 4 > 7 i 5 > 795 

Quakers, 672, 712, 713, 723, 741, 748, 
77o> 777> 780 ff, 81 1 

Ranke, 207, 1004 
Ranters, 772, 777 
Remonstrants, 763 
Richard of St. Victor, 730 
Rijnsburger, v. Collegiants 
Ritschl, 789 
Robinson, 665, 707 
Romanticism, 793 ff 
Rosicrucians, 716 
Rothe, Richard, 796, 802 
Rous, Francis, 753, 777 
Rousseau, 46, 636 
Ruskin, John, 677, 795 

Saint-Simon, 726, 797 
Salian Franks, 215 
Saltmarsh, John, 778 ff. 

Salvation Army, 689, 725 
Schelling, 792, 794 
Schleiermacher , 746, 790, 793, 794, 
795 > 798 ff , 802 
Schmalkalden, League of, 532 
Scholasticism, 275, 527 
Schortinghuys, 774 
Schwenkfeld, 738, 741, 751, 756 ff, 
762, 767, 771 

Seckendorff, L. von, 553, 562 
Seekers, 777 
Segalleli, Gerhard, 356 


Seneca, 66, 67, 154 
Servetus, 763, 769 ,* 

Simons, Menno, 705 
Smith, Adam, 646 
Smyth, John, 706 ff. 

Soccati, 356 

Socialism, 621, 712, 729, 817 
Socialism, Christian, 365, 602, 623, 
649, 711, 726 ff., 802, 804 ff, 817, 
818 

Socinians, 749 * 

Sombart, 645 
Spencer, Herbert, 676 
Spener, 716, 787 
Spinoza, 636, 749, 774, 792 
Spruyt, 766 

Stahl, Julius, 538, 568, 675 
Stein, Lorenz von, 28 ff. 

Stoicism, 41, 47, 64 ff., 1V0, 143, 14 4, 
152 ff, 162, 231, 239, 257, 258, 259, 
3 2 9> 389* 508, 674, 728, 736 t 
Swedenborg, 790 «* ♦ 

Taborites, 363 ff, 703, 754 
Taffin, 683 
Tamchelm, 351 
Tauler, 768, 777, 787 
Teellinck, 683, 774 
Tersteegen, 753, 785 
Tertullian, 120 
Thamer, 769 

Theologia Germanica , 377, 762, 768 f 
777 

Thomasius, Christian, 538 * 

Thomas Aquinas (St.), 203, 230, 232, 
272, 295, 298, 299, 312, 317 ff, 366, 
375 

Thomism, 257 ff, 280 ff, 293, 313 ff, 
316 ff, 320, 461, 464, 465, 512, 515, 
5 2 4 > 54 i 

Tolstoi, 214, 728 f. 

Udemann, 683 
Utraquists, v. Caiixtines 

Verschoor, Jakob, 774 
Victorines, 235, 245, 737 4 

Vives, Ludovico, 559, 566, 769 
Voet, 684 ff, 810 



INDEX OF NAMES 


Waiters, 772 

Waldensians* 237, 352, 354 ff, 359 , 
365* 6 99 , 725 
Weber, Max, 319, 645 ff 
Weigel, Valentine, 741, 759 ff. 
Wesley, John, 722 
Whitgift, 665 
Wichem, 568 


Williams, Roger, 672, 674 
Winstanley, Gerard, 71 1, 712 
Wirtz, 771 

Wiirttemberg Temple, 725 
Wyclif, 358 ff, 362, 363, 365, 367 

Zinzendorf, 719 ff, 759, 788 ff. 
Zwingli, 626, 669, 703 





GEORGE ALLEN & UNWIN LTD 
London: 40 Museum Street, W.C.i 
Cape Town: 73 St. George’s Street 
Sydney, N.S.W.: Wynyard Square 
Auckland, N.Z.: 41 Albert Street 
Toronto: 77 Wellington Street. West 




Ethics 

by NICOLAI HARTMANN 

Professor of Philosophy, University of Berlin 
translated by Stanton Coit, Ph.D. (Berlin) 

Demy 8 vo. In Preparation 

Professor Hartmann's Ethik was first published in Germany in 1926, 
and was immediately recognized by leading thinkers as an original 
contribution to the philosophy of moral experience. Its originality is 
especially marked in two particular aspects. It is a rigorous interpreta- 
tion of the data of ethics from the point of view of metaphysical 
realism. It is also a systematic application of the methodology of 
Professor Husserl and his school to the phenomena of conscience, 
responsibility and guilt. Both the metaphysics and the method exhibit 
the subject-matter of ethics in a new light, showing the inner structure 
and objective self-existence of values as well as their dependence upon 
the ontological categories. 


The Social Substance of Religion 

Demy 8 vo. by GERALD HEARD 10s. 6 d. 

In this book Mr. Heard shows that mental conflict is the real cause of 
social instability and upheaval, and that this has always been the case. 
But the Freudian explanation of the conflict is unsatisfactory, that 
of “Group Psychology'* being more accurate. The latter allows of an 
interpretation of human history which not only explains the strength 
and pertinacity of Religion, but points to a religious solution of the 
present social conflict. Mr. Heard’s writing contains many suggestive 
and original ideas which make this a work of unusual value. 


A Study of the Philosophy of Malebranche 

Demy 8 vo. by R. W. CHURCH, D.Phil. 125. 6 d. 

An examination of the philosophical system of the great Oratorian. 
His theories of the relation between reason and faith, of perception, 
of judgment, and of knowledge are exhibited in their dependence on 
the three main doctrines of his system : the vision of God, Occasionalism, 
and the vision in God. These doctrines are studied in detail and in their 
historical relations to La Forge, Cordemoy and Arnauld. 


Myth, Nature, and Individual 

Aspects of the Philosophy of Art and Magic 

Cr. 8 uo. by FRANK ALISON BAKER 55. 

These essays define the thesis to a comprehensive study of the status 
and significance of Mythology. Myth is regarded as a valid and autono- 
mous activity of the mind; its rdle is discussed in relation to Science, 
to Art, and to Philosophy. In particular the essays are a vindication of 
Mythology and a re-assertion of its rights in defiance of the strictures 
of dogmatic rationalism. 



The^Revelation of Deity 

by J.’E. TURNER, M.A., Ph.D. 

Author of “Personality and Reality,” “The Nature of Deity,” etc. 

(Reader in Philosophy in the University of Liverpool) 

Demy Bvo. $ s , td. 

The author discusses the various ways whereby the Divine Nature can 
manifest itself so as to be comprehended by the human mind. 

"Dr. Turner has won the reputation of being one of the ablest apologists 
for theism at present writing in England ." — Saturday Review 


The Mystic Will 

by HOWARD H. BRINTON, Ph.D, 
Introduction by Rufus M. Jones, D.Litt. 

La. Cr. Bvo. 8s. 6 d. 

"An illuminating study of the philosophy of Jacob Boehme. ... It 
would be difficult to over-praise the care and skill with which Dr. 
Brinton has striven to unlock the secrets of his thought and to place 
him in his true rank in the history of philosophy ." — Expository Times 

Democracy and Religion 

A Study in Quakerism 
by G. VON SCHULZE GAEVERNITZ 
Swarthmore Lecture, 1930 

Cr. Bvo. 2nd Impression Cloth 2 s. 6 d., Paper is.6d. 

The well-known German authority on social and economic questions 
traces the descent of Democracy, not from the official Reformation, but 
from the traditions of Plato, Christ, St. John, St. Francis, the Baptists, 
Mennonites and Quakers, with Kant, Goethe and Hegel in the same 
line of succession. He summarizes the main ideas in the world of sects 
from which Democracy crystallized towards the end of the seventeenth 
century. He then studies the historic mission of the Quakers, examines 
Social Democracy as a Western ideal, and concludes with an exposition 
of the mission of Quakers in the present day. 


The Meaning of the Glorious Koran 

An Explanatory Translation 

Demy Bvo. by MARMADUKE PICKTHALL 18s. 

It is fairly certain that no holy Scripture can be adequately rendered 
by one who disbelieves its message. As this is the first translation 
# of the Koran to be made by an Englishman who is also a Muslim, it 
may claim to be the most authoritative interpretation, from the Muslim 
poinf of view, which has yet been presented to English readers. Mr. 
Pickthall has been a lifelong student of Al-Qur'dn, and he began the 
present work over ten years ago. He later took the manuscript to 
Egypt, where he revised it, word by word, with expert help. He 
contributes an illuminating introduction summing up the salient 
features of Muhammad's life, and adds some valuable notes to the text 
of the Scriptures themselves. 



Sin and the New Psychology 

by CLIFFORD E. BARBOU&, Ph.D. 

Cr. 8 vo. Introduction by H. R. Mackintosh, D.D. ^ 6 s. 

"Compact and masterly pages. . . . Here is a writer who reads and 
thinks ." — United Methodist 

"Dr. Barbour is not only a sound psychologist, but a sane Christian 
teacher also ." — Methodist Times 


Creative Worship 

by HOWARD H. BRINTON, Ph.D. '» 

Swarthmore Lecture , 1931 

Cr. Svo. Cloth 2 s. 6 d., Paper is. 6 d. 

The author's purpose is to compare the mechanistic and organic trends 
in religious worship and in particular to analyse and evaluate the contri- 
bution of Quaker practice to what he calls organic worship. The Puritan 
and Quaker types of worship are selected for comparison and to illustrate 
the main theme. The subject of worship is approached from the biological 
standpoint, and the experience of the Quakers is used to show the possi- 
bility of something new and creative and unpredictable emerging in and 
through the worship of a Group. "Quakerism," he states, "is the belief 
that the highest type of worship is a group mysticism which affords 
opportunity for the silent growth of organic relations uniting the wor- 
shippers with God and with each other." 


The Holy and the Living God 

Demy 8vo. by M. D. R. WILLINK ios. 6 d. 

Some years ago, Professor Otto’s book, The Idea of the Holy , brought 
into prominence the awful and daunting side of our apprehension of 
deity. The present writer has traced the idea in the Bible and Christian 
history, and shows that it plays an essential part in the working of 
spiritual forces, that it throws light on obscure passages of the Old 
Testament, and that the present weakness of our religious life may be 
partly due to our forgetfulness of this aspect of religious consciousness. 


A Study of Conversion 

by the Rev. L. W. LANG 

Foreword by William Brown, M.D., B.Sc. 

Demy 8vo. Ios . 6d. 

This is a study of the process of Conversion and also of abnormal 
variations, including mystical phenomena. The process conforms to a 
spiritual law of assimilation, and the opinion that the Conversion-crisis 
is a sudden disruptive event is shown to be erroneous. Many Christian 
conversions of various degrees of intensity and duration are discussed, 
of people belonging to different periods and sections of the Church, 
such as Dr. Paton, George Fox, S. Teresa, Luigi Settembrjni, Andrew 
Carnegie and others. This study treats Conversion from a new point of 
view and is indispensable for those interested in Christian evangelism or 
in the psychology of religion. 

A 11 prices are net 


LONDON: GEORGE ALLEN & UNWIN LJD 




rrr?T 5TJ7TT?T?T g^qrmq 

Ld Bahaaur Shastr/ National Acadmey of Administration Library 

MUSSOORIE }0)SL*iK 

qf qq? qrfqq q;T?fr 1 1 

This book is to be returned on the date last stamped. 


Date 

^arTT^xT 1 } 
qvf qJsJTT 
Borrower's 
No. 

fearer 

Date 

qft qwr 

Borrower's 

No. 

i 

i 

1 



J 

s ' i 

1 

i 

i 


j 


! 

i 

! 


i! 

| 

1 



i 

| 


. 

1 






i 











GL 280 
TRO 



ini 9*0 



280 

Tro 


Class No 
%-J-TT 


r 

sriF'ct qw 

Acc No. 4-^06 

*rmT 

Book No. 


Author Troeltsch** E_^ 


T* 0 


Titlo 


LIBRARY 




LAL BAHADUR SHASTRI 

National Academy of Administration 

MUSSOORIE 


Accession Na. _ [ Oj ^ 

1. Books are Issued for 15 days only but 
may have to be recalled earlier If urgen- 
tly required. 

2. An over-due charge of 25 Paise per day 
per volume will be charged. 

3. Books may be renewed on request, at 
the discretion of the Librarian. 

4. Periodicals, Rare and Refrence books 
may not be issued and may be con- 
sulted only in the Library. 

5. Books lost, defaced or Injured In any 
way shall have to be replaced or its 
double price shall be paid by the 
borrower.